Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-07T02:40:20.842Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reductionism and proxy failure: From neuroscience to target-based drug discovery

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 May 2024

Arash Sadri*
Affiliation:
Lyceum Scientific Charity, Tehran, Iran https://lyceum.charity Interdisciplinary Neuroscience Research Program (INRP), Students' Scientific Research Center, Tehran University of Medical Sciences, Tehran, Iran
Sepideh Paknezhad
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Sari Branch, Islamic Azad University, Sari, Iran sepidehpaknezhad@outlook.com
*
Corresponding author: Arash Sadri; Email: arashsadri@lyceum.charity

Abstract

Reductionist methodologies reduce phenomena to some of their lower-level components. Researchers gradually shift their focus away from observing the actual object of study toward investigating and optimizing such lower-level proxies. Following reductionism, these proxies progressively diverge further from the original object of study. We vividly illustrate this in the evolution of target-based drug discovery from rational and phenotypic drug discovery.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ahn, A. C., Tewari, M., Poon, C. S., & Phillips, R. S. (2006). The limits of reductionism in medicine: Could systems biology offer an alternative? PLoS Medicine, 3(6), e208. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.0030208CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Al-Ali, H. (2016). The evolution of drug discovery: From phenotypes to targets, and back. MedChemComm, 7(5), 788798. https://doi.org/10.1039/C6MD00129GCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frangou, S. (2020). The enduring allure of explanatory reductionism in schizophrenia. Biological Psychiatry, 87(8), 690691. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biopsych.2020.01.008CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gazzaniga, M. S. (2010). Neuroscience and the correct level of explanation for understanding mind. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(7), 291292. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2010.04.005CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horrobin, D. F. (2003). Modern biomedical research: An internally self-consistent universe with little contact with medical reality? Nature Reviews Drug Discovery, 2(2), 151154. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrd1012CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krakauer, J. W., Ghazanfar, A. A., Gomez-Marin, A., MacIver, M. A., & Poeppel, D. (2017). Neuroscience needs behavior: Correcting a reductionist bias. Neuron, 93(3), 480490. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2016.12.041CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lazebnik, Y. (2002). Can a biologist fix a radio? – Or, what I learned while studying apoptosis. Cancer Cell, 2(3), 179182. https://doi.org/10.1016/s1535-6108(02)00133-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parker, D. (2022). Neurobiological reduction: From cellular explanations of behavior to interventions. Frontiers in Psychology, 13, 987101. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2022.987101CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sadri, A. (2023). Is target-based drug discovery efficient? Discovery and “off-target” mechanisms of all drugs. Journal of Medicinal Chemistry, 66(18), 1265112677. https://doi.org/10.1021/acs.jmedchem.2c01737CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Uttal, W. R. (2003). The new phrenology: The limits of localizing cognitive processes in the brain. MIT Press.Google Scholar