Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-10T10:41:31.293Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Feminist Radical Empiricism, Values, and Evidence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Abstract

Feminist epistemologies consider ways in which gender (among other social factors) influences knowledge. In this article, I want to consider a particular kind of feminist empiricism that has been called feminist radical empiricism (where the empiricism, not the feminism, is radical). I am particularly interested in this view's treatment of values as empirical, and consequently up for revision on the basis of empirical evidence. Proponents of this view cite the fact that it allows us to talk about certain things such as racial and gender equality as objective facts: not just whether we have achieved said equality in our society, but whether we are, in fact, all equal. I will raise the concern that the way in which they model the role of values in epistemology may be a problematic idealization of the open‐mindedness of human agents. In some cases, resistance to value‐change cannot be diagnosed as a failure to respond adequately to evidence. If so, the strategy of empirically testing our values that some feminist radical empiricists suggest may not be as useful a tool for social change as they think.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2016 by Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alcoff, Linda. 2006. Commentary on Elizabeth Anderson's “Uses of value judgments in science.” Symposium on Gender, Race, and Philosophy 2 (1).Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2004. Uses of value judgments in science: A general argument, with lessons from a case study of feminist research on divorce. Hypatia 19 (1): 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 1992. In my father's house: Africa in the philosophy of culture. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Begby, Endre. 2013. The epistemology of prejudice. Thought 2 (2): 9099.Google Scholar
Campbell, Richmond. 1994. The virtues of feminist empiricism. Hypatia 9 (1): 90115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clough, Sharyn. 2004. Having it all: Naturalized normativity in feminist science studies. Hypatia 19 (1): 102–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clough, Sharyn, and Loges, William E. 2008. Racist value judgments as objectively false beliefs: A philosophical and social‐psychological analysis. Journal of Social Philosophy 39 (1): 7795.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connor, Steve. 2013. The hardwired difference between male and female brains could explain why men are “better at map reading.” http://www.independent.co.uk/life-style/the-hardwired-difference-between-male-and-female-brains-could-explain-why-men-are-better-at-map-reading-8978248.html (accessed March 4, 2014).Google Scholar
Crandall, Christian, Bahns, Angela, Warner, Ruth, and Schaller, Mark. 2011. Stereotypes as justifications of prejudice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 37 (11): 1488–98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gendler, Tamar Szabó. 2011. On the epistemic costs of implicit bias. Philosophical Studies 156 (1): 3363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldenberg, Suzanne. 2005. Why women are poor at science, by Harvard president. http://www.theguardian.com/science/2005/jan/18/educationsgendergap.genderissues (accessed March 4, 2014).Google Scholar
Leslie, Sarah‐Jane. 2012. Generics articulate default generalizations. Recherche Linguistiques de Vincennes 1 (41): 2544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. 1990. Science as social knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2005. “Ideal theory” as ideology. Hypatia 20 (3): 165–84.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2006. Commentary on Elizabeth Anderson's “Uses of value judgments in science.” Symposium on Gender, Race, and Philosophy 2 (1).Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2007. White ignorance. In Race and epistemologies of ignorance, ed. Sullivan, Shannon and Tuana, Nancy. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, Lynn Hankinson. 1993. A question of evidence. Hypatia 8 (2): 172–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, Lynn Hankinson. 1995. A feminist naturalized philosophy of science. Synthese 104 (3): 399421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, Richard E. 2005. Heredity, environment, and race difference in IQ. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 11 (2): 302–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Neill, Onora. 1987. Abstraction, idealization and ideology in ethics. Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 22: 5569.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Neill, Onora. 1990. Justice, gender, and international boundaries. British Journal of Political Science 20 (4): 439–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1951. Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review 60 (1): 2043.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman, and Ullian, J. S. 1970. The web of belief. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Rothbart, Myron, and Park, Bernadette. 1987. On the confirmability and disconfirmability of trait concepts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 50 (1): 131–42.Google Scholar
Rushton, J. Philippe, and Jensen, Arthur R. 2005a. Thirty years of research on race differences in cognitive ability. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 11 (2): 235–94.Google Scholar
Rushton, J. Philippe, and Jensen, Arthur R. 2005b. Wanted: More race realism, less moralistic fallacy. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 11 (2): 328–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schneider, David J. 2004. The psychology of stereotyping. New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, Miriam. 2012. The web of valief. In Out from the shadows: Analytical feminist contributions to traditional philosophy, ed. Crasnow, Sharon L. and Superson, Anita M.New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stewart, Abigail J., Copeland, Anne P., Chester, Nia Lane, Malley, Janet E., and Barenbaum, Nicole B. 1997. Separating together: How divorce transforms families. New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Suzuki, Lisa, and Aronson, Joshua. 2005. The cultural malleability of intelligence and its impact on the racial/ethnic hierarchy. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 11 (2): 320–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tetlock, Philip E., Kristel, Orie V., Olson, S. Beth, Green, Melanie C., and Lerner, Jennifer S. 2000. The psychology of the unthinkable: Taboo trade‐offs, forbidden base rates, and heretical counterfactuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 78 (5): 853–70.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yap, Audrey. 2010. Feminism and Carnap's principle of tolerance. Hypatia 25 (2): 437–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar