Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-05T22:52:05.538Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Administration as Democratic Trustee Representation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 January 2024

Katharine Jackson*
Affiliation:
University of Cincinnati College of Law, 2925 Campus Green Dr, Cincinnati, Ohio 45221-0040-513-556-6805, United States
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The “folk” theory of democracy that typically justifies the administrative state cannot help but lead to a discourse of constraint. If agency action is only legitimate when it mechanically applies the will of the voters as transposed by Congress through statutes, then the norms guiding that action will inevitably restrain agency discretion. As a result, attempts to establish the democratic credentials of the administrative state ironically obstruct the application of collective power. But this “folk” theory of democracy is bad theory. It is empirically incredible and, alarmingly, facilitates dangerous populist politics. Political theory instead suggests that a theory of democratic representation not only better explains legislative outcomes, but also deprives demagogues and deregulatory partisans of the fictions that prop up their agendas. After a brief survey of representative theory, this article will demonstrate that a model of trustee representation adequately describes administration, reinforces its democratic credentials and constitutes a space for politics in shaping the regulations that govern us all.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

I. Introduction

Scholars and jurists struggle to justify the policymaking power of the administrative state. Their theories most often rest upon a transmission beltFootnote 2 conception of democratic legitimacy. Simple and superficially appealing, this conception holds that democracy is vindicated by aggregating voter preferences through elections. The popular will is next transposed by members of Congress into statutes. Finally the popular will, now codified, is applied mechanically by administrative agencies who should, in the words of Justice Kavanaugh, “fill in the details” using their technical expertise.Footnote 3 Administration is to be a “machine without a mind”Footnote 4 that makes no value judgments. Thus, the people's will travels on the back of the franchise from voter to administrator with, it is hoped, little disfiguration. Woodrow Wilson, for example, imagined administration operating according to “nomothetic” law that would carry out the orders of democracy's “corporate, popular will.”Footnote 5 The nondelegation doctrine, which holds that federal lawmaking power is held exclusively by Congress, also makes use of the transmission belt model. If Congress delegates policymaking authority to bureaucratic agents, it interrupts the seamless transit of the popular will from voter to representative, from representative to statute, and, finally, from statute to administrative mechanism.

Many political theorists have likewise failed, as Foucault observed, to cut off the king's head. Like conservative jurists, they remain skeptical of any policymaking power that is not tied directly to the sovereign voters and their elected representatives. “There is a persistent tendency,” notes political philosopher Joseph Heath, “to imagine the state as a single vertically integrated hierarchy, in which all major decisions are taken at the apex of power.”Footnote 6 This idea “leads to an overwhelming emphasis on legislatures as the primary locus of public decision-making.”Footnote 7 Agencies are supposed to be the sovereign's Hobbesian “nerves and tendons,” not a mind capable of judgment.Footnote 8 Indeed, many follow Weber and identify democracy with “an imagined domain of rational deliberation, direct participation, or public reason that stands apart from and steers machine-like administrative structures.”Footnote 9

The transmission belt model leads to the conclusion that administration will lack democratic legitimacy unless some very specific conditions obtain: that there is a discernable popular will on a policy issue; that Congress accurately transcribes this will in sufficient detail; and that agencies implement it mechanically and straightforwardly. One upshot is that theoretical and doctrinal work addressing administrative legitimacy is often oriented around constraint: it asks how one might force the bureaucratic behemoth into its proper placement on the transmission belt. Some scholarship suggests methods that restrain the human beings tending the administrative apparatus when they might otherwise be tempted to use its powers for their own purposes.Footnote 10 Others address how best to get administrators to stick to their statutory mandates and how those mandates ought to be interpreted—and by whom.Footnote 11 Some scholarship even abandons the democratic justification of administrative power altogether. It concentrates instead on how to best reign in this inevitable, but normatively problematic, feature of the state. Conceding that administration will invariably make value-laden policy choices outside those contemplated by Congress, they will talk about how to temper administrative discretion by applying liberalFootnote 12 or fiduciaryFootnote 13 norms that courts might enforce. These scholars resign themselves to the expertocracy of administration, coldly comforted with an assurance that it might, at the very least, avoid violating liberal or fiduciary values.

Yet, when we see administration as a democratic embarrassment, we kneecap the project of collective governance. When the administrators tasked with protecting the environment and safeguarding public welfare dare reach beyond the clear, unambiguous meaning of an implementing statute, when they make judgments that cannot be derived directly from some tiny piece of codified text, they find themselves apologizing for their existence. Boxed in by the transmission belt theory, they must concede that their actions are undemocratic, but are nevertheless justified by necessity or pragmatism.

To be sure, if administrative decision-making power is not subject to any kind of democratic constraint, we will be shaken by the bureaucratic nightmares envisioned by theorists from Weber to Foucault to Habermas.Footnote 14 Our anxieties about “technocracy, the relentless conquest of instrumental rationality, and roads to future serfdom and despotism”Footnote 15 are not unfounded. Fortunately, the transmission belt model is not the only way to incorporate popular participation into administration.

In the following sections, I will demonstrate that the transmission belt model fails to provide a solid foundation for democratic legitimacy, let alone the legitimacy of the administrative state. Namely, it relies upon a conception of popular sovereignty that takes literally several fictions: first, that the people have an identifiable “will”; and second, that this will can be applied regularly and without controversy by administrators as they interpret and execute the law. As a result, critics of administration often ascribe to congressional lawmaking more democratic credentials than it deserves. But this failure does not mean that administration is doomed to democratic exile. Instead, like many other contemporary lawmaking institutions, it benefits from the democratic legitimacy derived from political representation. Accordingly, after briefly surveying a few models of democratic representation, I will make the case that the trustee model of democratic political representation provides a convincing standard by which to measure the democratic credentials of the administrative state. The article concludes by showing how some superficially undemocratic moves by agencies might indeed claim democratic legitimacy.

II. Disassembling the Transmission Belt

The transmission belt model relies upon a problematic organ-body conception of popular sovereignty: that there is a “people” with a “will” that can be captured in the statutes granting authority to agencies. The model posits that elected political representatives’ statutory control over agencies lends agencies democratic legitimacy because “agency policy decisions … will presumably reflect the will of the people and achieve the consent of the governed.”Footnote 16 This hierarchical conception of legitimate authority is an upshot of democratic legal positivism. If natural law or some other transcendental norm is not to govern, then polities are left only with the commands of their sovereign.Footnote 17 In a democracy, where kratos (power) is vested in the dêmos, that sovereign is the people itself.

The idea that the popular will is “transmitted” from dêmos to agency relies on several cascading fictions. First, that “the people” has a will; second, that Congress will reproduce this will; third, that Congress accurately transcribes it into statutes; and fourth, that agency officials straightforwardly apply it in their rulemaking and adjudications. Holding to these fictions requires acceptance of various implausible premises. For example, Congress—a collective body of diverse human beings—has no “intent,” at least as it may be understood as some kind of psychological state unique to human individuals.Footnote 18 As a result, courts reach to a variety of interpretive and substantive canonsFootnote 19 to lend it anthropomorphized motivations. The major questions doctrine is one example: it ascribes to Congress an intention not to delegate policy-making power over questions of major social and economic importance.Footnote 20 To be sure, there may be good reason to act as if Congress has such an intention, but that reason, under the transmission belt model, has to be because it somehow enables Congress to replicate the will of “the people.” Otherwise, it will be some outside rationale, not popular will, that shapes the law.

Legal scholars are familiar with the fictions used to attribute an intent to Congress when it passes laws. They are also familiar with the fiction of agencies’ role as statutory transcribers: administrators routinely make value-laden policy choices that cannot be directly identified within statutory text.Footnote 21 The Legal Realist insight that statutes are indeterminate (or underdeterminate)Footnote 22 is well received. Legal scholars are less familiar, however, with the fiction used to ascribe a will and an intent to “the people” itself. They take it as a given, as A.V. Dicey did, that a legislature would “produce coincidence between the wishes of the sovereign and the wishes of the subjects.”Footnote 23 For them, it is a matter of common sense: legislative primacy derives from legislators’ unique connection to the popular sovereign.Footnote 24 The problem is that it comes with some intractable empirical and normative challenges.

Empirically, it is absurd to believe that a country of hundreds of millions could agree to anything, and certainly not so much that they can act as a unitary macro-subject.Footnote 25 As political science research confirms time and again, citizens have no clear, identifiable policy preferences that are capable of aggregation into a coherent, collective purpose. Hannah Pitkin, a seminal theorist of democratic representation, noted decades ago that “a constituency is not a single unit with a ready-made will or opinion on every topic; a representative cannot simply reflect what is not there to be reflected.”Footnote 26 Often, voters only come to have opinions and beliefs about policy because representatives, activists, and other political entrepreneurs have won them over. Many cast ballots based on party identification alone. Further, citizens remain necessarily ignorant of most policy proposals and their consequences.Footnote 27 They instead rely entirely upon the judgment of lawmakers. Nowhere is this clearer than when Congress considers policy that lobbyists and staff scribe in backroom offices.Footnote 28 The vote, moreover, is a coarse tool for conveying information about voter preferences; survey answers change when questions are reworded.Footnote 29 Both the President and Congress claim electoral mandates. Yet both often disagree on policy. Whose views should take precedence is not obvious.Footnote 30

It is not clear, therefore, that lawmaking reflects the popular will and not the will of, for example, elites and manipulators. Especially given the sophisticated surveillance, targeted messaging, and misinformation applied by political actors, lawmaking outcomes beg more questions than they answer.Footnote 31 Yet, even if we concede that the political process forms or informs voters’ policy preferences, the problem remains. The populace is too diverse to achieve collectivized reason and consensus—and certainly not in fine legislative detail.Footnote 32 Everyone might agree, for example, that there should be freedom of speech. But because of the “inherently formal and indeterminate nature” of principles like freedom, there will be many reasonable but inconsistent elaborations.Footnote 33

Consequently, the principal–agent transmission belt model of popular sovereignty is, as political theorists David Runciman and Mónica Brito VieiraFootnote 34 describe it, plainly inadequate to describe what is going on. Voters do not behave in a way that makes them a plausible principal.Footnote 35 Yet pretending that they do yields disquieting implications. If anyone claims to have identified an intention that is shared by all, or even just a majority, one is not terribly likely to conclude that we have achieved social harmony. Rather, something more nefarious may be afoot. “The abstract idea of a sovereign people,” notes political theorist Bryan Garsten, “[tends] to become concrete in the form of demagogues claiming to rule in the name of the people.”Footnote 36 Attempts to establish mimetic identity between representative and represented is not the realization of democracy. Instead, as F.R. Ankersmit argues, it is an invitation to tyranny.Footnote 37 Closing the conceptual gap between ruler and ruled forecloses public contestation, effaces social difference, and gives politicians an excuse to engage in a “relentless and unchecked pursuit of their particular vision of the good.”Footnote 38 The fiction of organ-body popular sovereignty, if taken literally, therefore puts us “in the business of electing dictators who can rule by decree while hiding behind ‘the will of the people.’”Footnote 39 The idea that the people can be accurately represented is simply a lie. “[L]ike all such political lies, it [can] be maintained not only at the cost of truth but of blood as well.”Footnote 40

As a result, whatever it is that Congress is doing, it does not, and should not pretend to, literally translate the “will of the people” into law. The Schmittian temptation to equate the leader with the people applies not only to chief executives, but also to legislators. Much political theory accordingly assigns to legislative bodies a different function. While the function assigned varies widely, each deploys some model of democratic representation that preserves a space for legislators’ independent thinking and decision-making. For some, Congress should help resolve political conflict under decision-making procedures that give all citizens equal respect and concern.Footnote 41 For others, it should serve as a deliberative, and deliberately counter-majoritarian, body capable of identifying truths about what is in the general interest,Footnote 42 not uncommonly in a manner favorable to counterrevolutionary interests.Footnote 43

While many theorists would insist that the notion of popular sovereignty is a fiction, some suggest it might be a useful one. If we act as if the sovereign was popular, we might be encouraged to include those excluded from the political process and to attend to the interests of all.Footnote 44 If popular means everyone, then everyone counts. The dream of popular sovereignty is one where citizens all share a role in shaping the laws that bind them by, for example, expanding the franchise and equalizing political resources.Footnote 45 Further, the obvious fictionality of the idea is itself useful. It emphasizes the gap between the imaginary sovereign “people” and its real-life representatives. As a result, a government grounded in the idea popular sovereignty stirs up perpetual and interminable debates about who the people are, where their interests lie, and what it is they actually want.Footnote 46 Such debates don't just motor democratic discourse; they also ensure that any answer provided by any politician in power is always contingent. The obvious fictionality of popular sovereignty therefore helps preserve for future electorates access to collective decision-making. No one generation can credibly claim to reach the final answer to a polity's collective problems. Relatedly, if the place of sovereign power is conceptually empty—because its occupant does not, in fact, exist—then any claim to occupy it permanently is an undemocratic usurpation of power.Footnote 47

In light of these normative and empirical problems, the transmission belt model fails to legitimize administration. No matter how much the agency's discretion is constrained, no matter how “intelligible” the principle imparted might be, citizens will still experience regulation not as their own will, but instead as a rule imposed upon them. Claiming otherwise is itself an invitation to tyranny because it forecloses contestation: voters cannot complain because the agency is diligently filling in the mundane details of their own orders. The democratic justification of the administrative state, if there is any to be had, must lie elsewhere.

III. Democratic Political Representation

Fortunately, it can lie within a theory of democratic representation. Such a theory explains not only why any collective governance, including statutory lawmaking, can be democratic; it also demonstrates why the administrative state carries its own democratic credentials. I suggest that the trustee model of political representation provides a home for administration within representative democracy. The next section, after roughly defining democratic political representation and several models within it, offers a few justifications for this move.

A. Democratic Political Representation: A Summary

The “folk” understanding of representation often mimics the unfortunate transmission belt model.Footnote 48 The people, as principals, direct their agents, their elected representatives, to do their bidding. Representatives transmit exogenous citizen preferences, the “bedrock for social choice,” in a linear, bottom-up process that translates their preferences into law.Footnote 49 As a result, it is the task of political institutions to minimize the “agency costs” incurred when representatives disobey their orders—for example, through electoral sanctions.Footnote 50 When working properly, the individual human representative disappears, drowned out by the loud transmission of public opinion into legal authority. Although a significant amount of political science scholarship relies on this model,Footnote 51 it, as explained above, has both empirical and normative drawbacks. It does not—and cannot—describe what is actually going on. If democracy requires perfect congruence between voter preference and law, no actually existing democracy can claim to be democratic.Footnote 52

It is time to jettison the folktale. As political theorist Bryan Gartsen explains, “The impossibility of fully and completely representing the people's will is integral to the concept of representation itself.”Footnote 53 Although it provides a framework “for realizing the democratic ideal of giving kratos to the dêmos, power to the people,”Footnote 54 representation is not an institutional shorthand used only because direct, unmediated democracy is impracticable or otherwise undesirable.Footnote 55 Unmediated rule, which perfectly transcribes the “will of the people” into law, would indicate presence, not representation.Footnote 56 Instead, political representation is best understood as rule explicitly undertaken by and through mediators.

Although it does not promise that the will of the popular sovereign will govern, this scheme of institutional mediation can promise that decisions will be made by representatives acting in the name of allFootnote 57 rather than by someone imposing their personal judgments on everyone else. To accomplish this “omnilateral” orientation,Footnote 58 models of democratic political representation identify how citizens can participate in decision-making in a way that helps to (1) maintain the normative priority of the ruled over their rulers and (2) ensure that the ruled have some equally distributed role to play in their own governance. Thus, representative systems are often assessed according to how well they incorporate equal involvement in political decision-making—a fundamental norm that Urbinati and Warren call “democratic autonomy.”Footnote 59 Representation vindicates democratic autonomy by allowing the otherwise absent citizens to be present during decision-making in some sense—that is, to have their interests considered evenhandedly, to have their authorization solicited with equal vigor, to enjoy an equal chance to have their ex-post judgments registered, and so on. For example, Runciman and Brito Vieira explain that citizens can be present in lawmaking if they are able to object to what is being done by their rulers.Footnote 60 Representatives will decide in light of these possible objections, perhaps changing their choices and their behavior as a result. Citizens thus attend legislative sessions as specters to haunt the legislators.

There are many ways to accomplish citizen presence within the lawmaking process. Representation accommodates substantial institutional creativity.Footnote 61 The menu of techniques that can encourage citizen involvement and motivate lawmakers to take their citizens’ interests seriously is capacious. As a result, political theorists use a variety of models to describe democratic political representation. A successful representative democracy will exhibit many of them, often in combination and with overlap.Footnote 62 Shrewd institutional design will mix, match, and commingle different models to maximize democratic autonomy.

First, there is the “congruence,” “mandate,” “compliance,” or “principal–agent” model, which reproduces the transmission-belt theory addressed above. Sometimes, the best way to incorporate some citizens’ presence is to treat them and their representatives as principals and agents, their agency costs policed via electoral sanction. Yet it involves the issues addressed above.

Most other models, in contrast, make good use of the autonomous judgment deployed by representatives. Rather than deny representatives any independent causal role in governance, these models accept it. They prove particularly useful in circumstances where direct links between citizens and representatives, like regular voting, are difficult to operationalize. None of them, further, relies upon any pre-existing social consensus or homogeneous “popular will” to lend legitimacy to political decision-making. They also explain why the mere diversification of leadership positions—whether on the bench, in the boardroom, in the presidential cabinet, or in Congress—can be counted as a democratic improvement, all else being equal.

Descriptive representation holds, roughly, that “someone like me will pursue my interests.”Footnote 63 Selected because of the characteristics they share with citizens (e.g., gender identity, religious beliefs, class, race, sexual orientation), descriptive representatives are motivated by personal reasons, not by the possibility of electoral sanction or constituent instruction. These representatives are left to decide how their identities will express themselves in the lawmaking process. This model, however, has some drawbacks. It risks essentialismFootnote 64 and obscures the fact that interests can be endogenous to the political process rather than derived from exogenous empirical characteristics such as racial identity. Finally, any decision-making body that perfectly resembled the people would simply reproduce the people itself. It would not, therefore, be representation at all. Accordingly, some judgment must be exercised as to which people, which characteristics, and which interests merit descriptive representation. Those judgments are far from obvious and noncontroversial.

The gyroscopic model posits that citizens authorize representatives who can be trusted, without oversight or sanction, to pursue goals that the voters find attractive.Footnote 65 Gyroscopic representatives, who reliably “spin on their own axes,” are understood as honestly motivated, skilled advocates who are therefore given discretion to deploy their judgment as they see fit. To illustrate, Ohio voters concerned about commercial exploitation might find representation in Massachusetts Senator Elizabeth Warren, a banking and financial law expert with credible commitments to working-class and consumer interests. The risks include (1) short-shrifting commercial interests and (2) pleasing only a radical base of supporters.Footnote 66 Gyroscopic representation works best, therefore, in a system that draws representatives from many different viewpoints.

The trustee model of political representation, unlike the dyadic models described above, has a tripartite structure. It is, as a result, a highly mediated form of rule. A principal (party one) authorizes a trustee (party two) to act for a beneficiary (party three). For example, a voter may authorize a representative to use their best judgment while acting in the whole country's interest. This model, unlike the others, enables the representation of persons (both natural and fictitious) who cannot speak and act for themselves.Footnote 67 As a result, a trustee can, for example, be said to act for “the people”—“the people” who cannot, normatively and empirically, act for themselves. Arguably, all members of Congress are trustee representatives. They are elected (authorized) by a particular geographic constituency yet make decisions that hold for the entire country and do so in the form of laws that will hold for generations to come.Footnote 68

The absent beneficiary is made present (represented) through an obligation on the part of the trustee representative to act in its “best interests,” even when they conflict with the wishes of the authorizer.Footnote 69 Using some logical deduction, we might tentatively hold that to act in someone's “best interests” means to act carefully and with the subjective belief that the action is in the beneficiary's interest and is not, at the very least, self-serving.Footnote 70 Meanwhile, although the authorizing party can set the terms and scope of the trustee's authority, it retains no day-to-day control over them. As a result, the trustee enjoys an ominous amount of autonomyFootnote 71 when determining the beneficiary's best interests.

Admittedly, many associate trustee representation with the paternalism of Edmund BurkeFootnote 72 and James Madison.Footnote 73 After all, it concedes to the trustee the authority to make decisions on behalf of other human beings who are capable of deciding for thesmelves. But we should not be so quick to jettison the model. The autonomy granted a trustee representative can enhance democratic autonomy in a few ways. First, trustee representatives can provide presence to citizens who cannot speak and act for themselves. They can represent those not yet born, the disenfranchised, children, the incapacitated, and so on. Even if such voices cannot, as a matter of physics or legal right, be present, they can nonetheless play a role in collective decision-making if someone speaks and acts for them. Trustee representatives can also speak and act for those wrongfully shut out of the political process because of economic and social inequalities. When political resources are stacked in a lopsided manner, when the marginalized are so overburdened by the demands of ordinary life that they cannot speak for themselves, only a trustee can give the marginalized any (admittedly ventriloquized) voice at all.Footnote 74 Similarly, when matters are too complex for ordinary citizens to understand—let alone form a viewpoint about—only a trustee representative can act on their behalf.Footnote 75 Of course, many would rather citizens speak and act for themselves. But, in an imperfect and unequal world, the trustee model is more democratically appealing than a model that prioritizes the voices of those with outsized power, wealth, and influence. During collective decision-making, a trustee can prevent the effacement of ordinary citizens and their interests. Further, acts that a trustee representative might undertake in the interest of disempowered beneficiaries might enable them to participate on their own behalves in the future.Footnote 76

Moreover, the trustee model can, unlike other models of representation, provide an answer to what is, according to Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Williams,Footnote 77 the first question of politics. The trustee's duty to act in its beneficiary's “best interests” imposes on it a duty to establish some amount of security and safety. Although, as explained below, a “best interests” determination is always contestable, it assuredly includes this minimum. Yet it is not obvious that citizens always know which actions might successfully stifle the outbreak of a deadly virus or defend against violent invasion. Moreover, presuming that citizens do have such knowledge, it is not obvious that citizens will possess sufficient collective capacity to act on it. Other models of representation nevertheless suggest that leaders follow voters’ myopic preferences, even if they are epistemically unsound or prioritize conflicting policy goals. In contrast, a trustee model lets experts be experts. This is not to argue that experts should remain insulated from critique and contestation. Expert trustees’ claims to act in the public interest, because both interpretive in nature and reliant upon imperfect knowledge, should face and respond to the crucible of citizen objection.Footnote 78 Facts will always present with an Arendtian slipperiness;Footnote 79 truth claims can always be challenged. But a trustee does not need to apologize for “following the science.” Instead, it is probably a trustee representative's duty to do so.Footnote 80

Recently, representation has taken a constructivist turn.Footnote 81 Important scholars have now abandoned the idea that voters come to politics with ready-made preferences and interests. Instead, voters’ opinions are the result of successful appeals made by representatives. Representation is not a spatial concept, “re-presenting” voters located in geographical districts through appointed agents located in a governing body. Instead, representation is better understood as a communicative process whereby representatives call the represented into being by making claims that are accepted as representative by an audience. Emphasizing the tutelary aspect of democratic discourse,Footnote 82 a representative's claim to represent a constituency is considered successful if it is taken up by them by signaling their approval with a vote, a campaign contribution, and so on. Laudably, constructivists do not rely on organ-body sovereignty or the existence of a people with exogenous preferences or objective interests that a democracy should translate into law. Moreover, all theories of representation must involve some amount of interest construction as representatives predict how voters might respond to policies and craft their public appeals to secure citizens’ support. In particular, the trustee model, which counts on trustees to “interpret the group's interest, and in doing so put forth a claim to be representing it,”Footnote 83 has constructivist traits.

Unfortunately, though, constructivist theories lead one to a normative dead-end.Footnote 84 Either they are too relativist or they are too rationalist.Footnote 85 They provide no way to distinguish successful manipulation from ordinary representation without also relying on standards of judgment that are perfectionist—viz, whether a voter's decision to take up the representative's claim is rationally correct or made only after fulfilling certain deliberative desiderata.

B. Representation and Lawmaking

If successfully implemented, models of democratic representation lend legitimacy to the outcome of representatives’ decision-making. These outcomes, including legislation, will be authoritative because they are the result of processes that vindicate democratic autonomy: their creation involves citizens in some way and in a manner that prioritizes them (including their preferences and interests), not the lawmakers. Such outcomes deserve our respect to the extent that they are the expression of democratic autonomy. As a result, there is good democratic reason to treat congressional lawmaking as authoritative. Regular elections, a near-universal franchise right, protections for free speech, and an increasingly diverse legislature lend it democratic credentials.

But congressional lawmaking is not democratically legitimate merely because it is congressional; it is legitimate because the procedures that yield legislation reflect democratic autonomy. Accordingly, federal statutes may be more or less justified depending on how well their procedures perform. If representative processes are skewed, legislation is accordingly less democratic and less justified. For example, legislation carries less democratic weight if large portions of the dêmos are excluded from participation due to onerous voting requirements and extensive gerrymandering. Legislation will carry less democratic weight if corruption or supermajority rules persuade lawmakers to regularly prioritize a favored elite at the expense of others’ equal claims for attention.

Moreover, since Congress holds no monopoly on representative institutions, the outcomes of other decision-making procedures likewise carry democratic weight. Indeed, representative systems explicitly discard the “formalist vestiges of prerogative, sovereignty, and even lordship … framed primarily around juristic conceptions of delegation, the separation of powers, the rule of law, and constitutional limitations.”Footnote 86 Rather than locating power in a specific body, democratic representation permits the proliferation of rulemaking settings. State and local legislatures certainly enjoy democratic legitimacy. The processes used to select policy-setting executive leaders and judges may also respect democratic autonomy. If the standard is democratic legitimacy rather than constitutional formalism, Congress deserves primacy only if no other institution better instantiates democratic autonomy.

Moreover, if other representative institutions contribute to or elaborate upon its decisions, Congress's democratic credentials might grow even more authoritative. Congressional lawmaking in isolation does not maximize the amount of democratic autonomy that citizens might enjoy. Congress is but one (important) part of a representative system that includes both formal and informal representative processes occurring within and between multiple institutions.Footnote 87 Bicameralism and presentment, for example, weave together three different representative institutions in the creation of statutes. The result, one hopes, is a greater level of democratic autonomy than each would yield on its own. These statutes prompt further representative processes—for example, implementation at the state level through local representatives; appointment of reviewing judges; interpretation by chief executives; and, as explained below, elaboration within agencies. Meanwhile, many rest upon both formal and informal representative processes involved in the selection of intra-party candidates and policies. Each step in the life of a statute, from drafting to enforcement, provides an opportunity to enhance its democratic credentials. Thus, to the extent that there is any kind of popular macro-agent, it is not an organic popular sovereign, an identifiable group person with a will of its own. It is instead the ongoing and immanent production of decisions made through representative processes that help vindicate the norm of democratic autonomy.Footnote 88

Of course, those holding to a rigorous (idolatrous?)Footnote 89 separation of powers doctrine and a strict interpretation of the Vesting ClauseFootnote 90 will reject this intersection and accumulation of representative practices. But they can do so only at great cost. They must select from a set of undesirable conclusions. First, they could concede that Congress, although the only legitimate lawmaking power, may not be as democratic as one might like. Second, they could insist that Congress is maximally democratic, but only by adopting the unfortunate transmission belt model. This is the only model that attributes to Congress the power to speak full-throated with the “voice of the people.” Finally, they might prioritize the text of the Constitution (as they understand it) over democratic autonomy. This means that they must either (1) adopt a vulgar democratic legal positivism that prioritizes decisions made hundreds of years ago over those made in the present or (2) value the rights protected by constitutional constraints (like the separation of powers) over democracy itself.

C. Administration as a Representative Institution

Accordingly, representation can lend democratic legitimacy to all kinds of public decision-making, not just the laws passed by Congress—including actions taken by administrative agencies. There are a few reasons why this move makes sense. Administrators are part of a state conceived as separate from citizens, and the work they do is, at least notionally, on behalf of those citizens. As public policy scholar Anthony Bertelli puts it, “this is representation.”Footnote 91 Political representation makes space for administration's division of labor, a mediation that accommodates citizens’ expectation that an “intelligent, civic-minded state official [will] take care of problems.”Footnote 92 Those officials will invariably address questions of political import. Their decisions involve both “facts and value commitments, both ends and means”—all of which are “inextricably intertwined in political life.”Footnote 93 These are precisely the types of questions with which representation is designed to deal. There is a morphological fit, in other words, between models of political representation and the role played by administration in governance.

Theories of representation can also open new avenues for research and reform. One common critique of the administrative state is that it has a “democracy problem”: it makes value-laden policy choices without the popular consent implied by elections. Democratic representation preempts this complaint because it does not require—indeed, often conspicuously excludes— citizens’ knowing understanding and prior approval of everything an official does in their name. Instead, it uses indicia of democratic autonomy to assess the democratic quality of an institution's output. As shown above, the franchise is far from the only mechanism that can be used to accomplish this. Administration's so-called “democracy problem” might be mooted as a result of the considered use of, for example, descriptive, gyroscopic, and trustee representation in the design of administrative institutions. The next section will demonstrate the fruitfulness of this approach by applying a trustee model.

More specifically, many models of democratic representation avoid the transmission-belt theory's organ-body sovereignty conundrum. As a result, they can suggest something meaningful about the democratic legitimacy of administrative action beyond whether or not it carries out the orders of a Congressional principal who itself is thought to follow the orders of “the people.” A theory of representation therefore allows administrative law scholars to transcend interminable theoretical debates that focus narrowly on the proper constraints to place on administrators as they interpret and apply implementing statutes. It allows for the possibility that administrative action is the product of democratic representation and therefore legitimate even if there is no crystal-clear statutory directive to implement. As a result, it suggests that there are ways to democratize administration beyond, as the U.S. Supreme Court has recently implied,Footnote 94 holding Congress's feet to the fire and forcing it to codify policy in ever more exhaustive detail.

IV. Why the Trustee Model is Appropriate

The remainder of this article will suggest that administrative agencies can serve as democratically successful trustee representatives. This is not to argue that other models of representation are irrelevant or inapt. A central bank's democratic credentials, for example, might be improved if its significant offices are held by descriptive and gyroscopic representatives rather than by the designees of financial concerns. I select the trustee model, however, because of its tight fit to extant administrative practice. As a result, it can be used to assess administration's democratic quality as it currently functions. Second, its theoretical resonance with pathbreaking scholarship on fiduciary theories of government means that scholars applying it will be well served by an existing body of rich literature. Finally, the trustee model fills a normative vacuum left by other models of representation and boasts several features congenial to democratic autonomy.

A. Conceptual Fit

First, the trustee model's tripartite framework reasonably describes administration's legal infrastructure: the model suggests that an authorizer (e.g., Congress, through statutes) authorizes a trustee (the agency, understood as a collective body) to take care of the interests of a beneficiary regarding some delimited subject (e.g., the people's health and welfare, consumers, racial minorities, and so on).

Further, the model expressly contemplates that the beneficiary is unable, for one reason or another, to act for itself. When it comes to the regulation of complex financial schemes and scientifically intensive public health interventions, this is precisely the public's circumstances. When an agency looks out for the interests of political minorities and the economically disadvantaged, it is looking out for those citizens whose political voices are silenced. Many administrative agencies pursue the interests of those shut out of the political process. For example, the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (“EEOC”), the Department of Justice Civil Rights Division, the Federal Trade Commission (“FTC”), and the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau (“CFPB”) advocate on behalf of those subject to discrimination and without the resources necessary to mobilize on their own behalf. Relatedly, agencies can act for an entire country even though a country cannot, as a practical matter, act for itself. The model accommodates the constructivist and Hobbesian notion that there is no concept of “people” prior to politics.Footnote 95 An agency dedicated to defense and security, for example, may carry out tasks in the (loosely defined) “national interest.” There may be no “nation” that can speak for itself and its interests, but the Department of Defense can do so in its stead.

Moreover, baked into the trustee model is the inevitable discretion wielded by administrators as they interpret and apply their statutory mandates. There are a few reasons why administration's decision-making autonomy is inevitable. First, the inherent ambiguity of agencies’ organizing statutes will require interpretation and elaboration. No amount of rule-tightening or definitional glossaries will ever remove all ambiguity from the law.Footnote 96 Legal interpretations are commonly controversial and, even when the law's meaning is clear, how it ought to apply in unanticipated circumstances may not be obvious.Footnote 97 Appealing to legislative intent will not eradicate the ambiguity. Ascertaining legislative intentions, which requires ascribing intentions to a collective agent, is also a matter of interpretation—one that involves linguistic ambiguities, problems of systemic coherence, and so on.Footnote 98 And when law is indeterminate or underdeterminate,Footnote 99 agencies must exercise interpretive discretion that cannot help but prioritize some values at the expense of others.Footnote 100 A statutory instruction to evaluate drugs for safety and effectiveness doesn't tell administrators a lot about how much risk should be traded off for marginal increases in efficacy.

Second, given their expertise and experience, administrators will have greater understanding of the issues in question, and therefore enjoy an independent source of political influence over lawmakers.Footnote 101 Greater popular participation cannot expunge this source of autonomy. Citizens rarely know what regulations cover and consequently cannot evaluate them responsibly.Footnote 102 But their elected representatives may fare no better. Legislators’ capacity and incentive for oversight is limited, constrained to episodic formal investigations and debates focused on scandal rather than policymaking.Footnote 103 Politically appointed agency officers may enjoy only a limited understanding of their duties.Footnote 104 In contrast, agency officials’ expertise, connections to well-organized stakeholders, and reputation for effectiveness give them authority. They leverage this authority to shape the legislative process itself as they propose bills and amendments.Footnote 105 As political philospoher Joseph Heath observes, the civil service “is often the source of highly effective policy entrepreneurship.”Footnote 106

Finally, the model does not suppose that the beneficiary (e.g., the public) must vote for the trustee. The trustee's authority to decide on its behalf and in its interests is not necessarily electoral. Rather, it comes from a distinct party, one with authority to appoint the trustee. Administration's “unelected bureaucrats” can therefore find not exile from, but rather a home within, the trustee model.

B. Resonance with Fiduciary Theories of Government

In addition to the snug conceptual fit between the trustee model and actual administrative practice, extant literature applying fiduciary concepts to administration already exists.Footnote 107 The theoretical overlap between these fiduciary theories and political trusteeship not only gives scholars interested in trustee representation a head start, but also demonstrates the plausibility of the project. Indeed, some of this pathbreaking scholarship is cited below. However, the trustee model of democratic political representation—at least as it is deployed here—differs from such fiduciary theories. Most importantly, whether addressing administration, the U.S. Constitution,Footnote 108 the judiciary,Footnote 109 the executive,Footnote 110 or otherwise,Footnote 111 fiduciary theory does not attend to the justification of power as such.Footnote 112 Inspired by Locke's liberalism, many focus instead on how that power ought to be limited by the (judiciary's)Footnote 113 application of fiduciary duties. It is a fungible theory that, as its advocates put it, applies to any relation of authority,Footnote 114 regardless of how it comes about. As a result, it shares the same weaknesses of many liberal and republicanFootnote 115 theories of government mentioned in the introduction of this article: it leaves unexamined the constitution of collective power. This neglect implies that such power is, although perhaps inevitable, au fond unjustifiable—a beast to be captured. In contrast, the trustee model of political representation can be part of a political framework that expresses democratic political autonomy. As illustrated in Habermas's analogy of democracy with the two-headed Janus,Footnote 116 it is part of the left-facing constitution of collective decision-making. Fiduciary theories, like many republican and liberal theories, are part of the right-facing constraints on that decision-making. Many of its proponents invoke it precisely because they, equating democracy with consent, are skeptical of democracy itself.Footnote 117 As explained above, however, democratic representation requires no such consent. At the extreme, a democratic theory requiring universal consent is an invitation to populism—or worse.

C. A Stronger Model of Representation

To the extent that any model of political representation requires that representatives exercise their own judgment when constructing and interpreting constituent interests, a model that recognizes and addresses the autonomy implied by such construction is more empirically accurate.Footnote 118 Because it is more accurate, it can help scholars to examine the normative implications of this autonomy. The trustee model may, therefore, be a better model of representative democracy than the others. This is the third reason for the selection of the trustee model.

To explain, recall the tutelary character of constructivist models. They describe how representatives mobilize voters’ political interests into existence. Such mobilization requires a representative to think and act independently of the electorate because the electorate is not as yet aware of these interests. Descriptive models of representation may also require representatives to autonomously construct constituent interests as they decide which aspects of their group merit attention and which ones do not. Even mandate models must build in room for a representative's independent judgment. Representatives face votes only every few years, and that vote contains very little information about voters’ preferences on particular policy issues—even if a constituency could form a coherent unified preference.Footnote 119 Yet each of these models has very little to say about the inevitable discretion wielded by representatives. Ironically, they therefore have very little to say about how representatives ought to go about their jobs and how citizens ought to evaluate them.Footnote 120 The trustee model, however, is not so hobbled.

In fact, the obligation to act in the beneficiary's interest lays upon the representative a normative yardstick to measure how well representatives exercise their inevitable judgments. Recall that constructivist models’ desiderata fail to screen out successful voter manipulation. So long as voters seem to take up (or acquiesce to) the claims made, representation is judged a success. Similarly, a successful mandate representative will be judged a success upon election, even if they take up the most ill-advised and ill-informed voter preferences. A trustee model, on the other hand, might suggest that manipulation and blind obedience is a violation of the representative's duties to serve their beneficiaries’ interests. In failing to serve the public's interests, a representative is failing to represent the public. Whatever the representative is doing, it is not representation. The representative is instead perhaps acting in their own interests. Further, to assess the success of descriptive representatives beyond their descriptive characteristics, one cannot help but reach for the fiduciary standards suggested by trustee representation: Did they decide after proper research and investigation? Did they have good reasons? Did they try in good faith to articulate the interests of those like them, or did they act for self-interested or reckless reasons? Simply, the other-regarding duties laid on the representative are what makes them representative of others.

As a result, the trustee model furnishes a normative standard missing from other models of democratic representation. That standard should prove attractive to advocates of democracy. To illustrate its appeal, consider a trustee representative authorized to act on behalf of public health. Of course, the public interest, including the interest in public health, is subject to deep contestation. The notion of a public is fictional and socially constructed—but it is not entirely open-ended. Namely, it suggests that policymaking should not reflect the partial preferences of the few at the expense of the many.Footnote 121 Decisions have weaker claim to be in the public interest, and therefore to represent the public, if they reflect concern and respect only for a small portion of the population. In other words, the notion of the public interest is a principle of inclusion rather than exclusion.Footnote 122 As William Novak argues, the growth of government institutions oriented to the public welfare arose contemporaneously with the idea of universal citizenship ascribing equal rights to all.Footnote 123 Consequently, the trustee serving the public makes present a greater swath of the population than a mandate representative who openly serves partial interests. At the very least, a commitment to the public interest forbids highly resourced private parties from hijacking the collective decision-making process to serve their own ends.Footnote 124

The autonomy enjoyed by trustee representatives to decide and act in the beneficiary's interests brings additional democratic benefits. First, it respects the lack of consensus among the represented. It does not matter that citizens, both present and future, cannot form preferences regarding (or agree about) the actions that the representative should take. To act legitimately, it only matters that the trustee pursues their best interests as authorized (leaving aside, for the moment, how “best interests” and “authorization” are defined).Footnote 125 Especially in situations where it is not obvious that government inaction is any more democratic than government action, the trustee representative's autonomy unshackles public officials from dangerous gridlock or inertia.

Furthermore, the conspicuous tripartite distinction it draws between the authorizers, the trustee, and the beneficiary is appealing because it prevents trustee representatives from convincingly claiming to speak with the “voice of the people.” Unlike other models, which might condone any action taken by lawmakers so long as they garner popular support, a trustee model prevents a ruler from claiming an identityFootnote 126 with the ruled. As J.S. MillFootnote 127 and de TocquevilleFootnote 128 once pointed out, majority sentiment can quieten public debate. On the contrary, the trustee model emphasizes the non-identity between the ruling trustee and the governed beneficiary. It therefore invites constructive popular contestation where other models might smother it. Ironically, the thick institutional mediation separating the trustee representative and citizen beneficiary may encourage democratic feedback rather than suppress it. Of all the models of democratic representation discussed in this article, it is least susceptible to populist politics.

Representative independence from the electorate can also make them better advocates.Footnote 129 They can therefore lend citizens priority and presence in decision-making that they would not otherwise enjoy. An attorney presenting a case on behalf of her client, for example, is expected to use both their expertise and their experience to secure outcomes that are superior to those that clients might achieve on their own. As Dewey once observed, although the man who wears the shoe knows best that it pinches and where it pinches, it is the shoemaker who can best judge how the trouble is to be remedied.Footnote 130 Likewise, a trustee advocate within a legislative body, exercising independent judgment and expertise, can press the interests of a constituency more effectively than it can itself.

Finally, a trustee's obligation to pursue the public interest should gratify scholars with deliberative commitments. The idea of the public, a multitude of human beings existing coherently together, attends to the ways individual experience affects, and is affected by, broader social and economic conditions. It evokes the fact of human interdependence and, as a result, suggests that public norms should reflect the same kind of reflexivity and generality championed by social contract philosophers from Kant to Habermas. In any event, many participatory and deliberative models of democracy tacitly rely upon a version of the trustee model. Theories that promote the use of deliberative mini-publics, for instance, ascribe to them the kind of autonomy, informed advocacy, and other-regarding cognitive orientation attributed to trustees.Footnote 131 These bodies, acting for the population at large, deliberate and decide on which actions will be taken on its behalf. Members are instructed not to parrot popular views or pursue naked self-interest, but instead to bend their views according to the unforced force of the better argument.Footnote 132 They must imagine what the interests of others might be and how a proposed rule might impact them. And members are encouraged to endorse decisions that, thanks to deliberation's generality and reflexivity desiderata, articulate some notion of the public good. Some theories of legal interpretation would likewise find friendship with a trustee model of representation. Those that lean on deliberative norms rather than popular participation require decision-making officers to take everyone into account and give meaningful weight to their different points of view,Footnote 133 or give “reasons calling on some understandable vision of the public welfare or purpose” and reasoned responses to public objections.Footnote 134

Unlike deliberative theories of democracy, however, the trustee model incorporates the idea of the public interest without making any commitment either to its precise content or the acceptable ways in which contributors might participate in public reasoning. First, the trustee model is less sanguine about the possibility that trustees land on some rationally correct or unanimous answer to the question of the common good. A trustee's claim to authoritatively speak in the beneficiary's best interests is always provisional. Indeed, as explained in the next section, the idea of “the public interest” in trustee representation is a political, not a juridical, question. It accepts that citizens may object to, and should have the means to object to, the trustee's interpretation. A trustee is no Judge Hercules.Footnote 135 Second, the idea of the public interest accepts reasons that are both “communicative” and “instrumental,” both value-based and technical. It therefore subjects both science and norms to political judgment. Further, the trustee model does not require that that the only reasons acceptable in the justification of collective decision-making are those that each and every citizen might or should accept. As a result, the trustee model may appeal to those skeptical of the legitimizing power of public reason.Footnote 136

V. Unpacking Some Definitions

Accordingly, the trustee model of political representation should provide some traction into the democratic legitimacy of administrative agencies. Before applying the model, however, it is worth unpacking a few of its elements and addressing some potential objections.

A. The Bounded Autonomy of the Trustee Representative

As mentioned above, a trustee representative enjoys autonomy in its decision-making. The trustee does not, however, operate without any constraints whatsoever. On the contrary, it is bound to act in the interests of its beneficiary.Footnote 137 Only then can the trustee claim to give presence to the beneficiary in its decision-making. Some minimal, but meaningful, substantive conditions can be deduced from this basic obligation. First, as fiduciary theorists point out, the trustee cannot act in its own self-interest.Footnote 138 If trustee representation consists of acting on behalf of another, trustees cannot act only for themselves. For example, the Social Security Administration, as a trustee, cannot steal resources set aside for entitlements in order to build lavish offices. Second, a trustee cannot act in such a way that no one could ever believe that it is acting in the beneficiary's best interests. The Center for Disease Control (CDC), as a trustee of the public health, cannot pour deadly poison into the public water supply. Third, the trustee must in good faith (actually) believe that the actions it is taking are in the beneficiary's interests. The Open Markets Committee of the U.S. Federal Reserve cannot unthinkingly and substantially increase interest rates without any reason to believe that its intervention will either stabilize prices or increase employment rates. Whatever good faith means, it is certainly not intentional or reckless disregard of the beneficiary's interests.

These sorts of obligations, under private fiduciary law, are typically enforced by courts in lawsuits. The Delaware Court of Chancery, for example, specializes in holding fiduciaries to their duties of loyalty (including good faith) and care.Footnote 139 While courts may therefore be competent to police the political trustee's similar duties, there is reason for some skepticism. First, institutions more permeable to democratic participation might also enforce them—for example, electoral sanctions, legislative investigations, administrative ombudsmen, and so on.Footnote 140 To the extent that a strict interpretation and application of these duties import a judge's personal values in a way that shapes outcomes, using these mechanisms may be more democratically desirable. There is no reason to believe, moreover, that courts are better placed than an expertly staffed review panel to assess the quality of care taken by a trustee making policy under conditions of economic, social, or scientific complexity.Footnote 141 Accordingly, if judicial review is appropriate, it probably should be deferential. The Delaware Courts themselves recognize their own lack of business acumen, for example, by implementing a highly deferential “business judgment rule.”Footnote 142 They refuse to intervene with corporate decision-making unless it is plainly reckless or self-serving. Furthermore, prophylactic measures might be taken to prevent the breach of such duties. “Good types” or “gyroscopes,” unlikely to breach, might be authorized as trustees through the use civil service tests, professional vetting, and so on.

B. Politicizing the Public and Its Interest

Notwithstanding these minimal constraints, the duty to act in the beneficiary's interest is left open. Indeed, the parameters are so vague that many might reject the trustee model at the outset because it does little more than encourage paternalistic policymaking by electorally unaccountable officials. As hinted at above, the notion of the “public” and its “interest” are indeed fictions, and the business of defining them might be monopolized by powerful actors. Further, both representatives’ and citizens’ honest beliefs about what serves the public's best interest routinely conflict. The open-endedness of the “best interests” calculation even drives some scholars to spurn fiduciary theories of government because it lends too much power to the institution granted the authority to define it.Footnote 143 There is good reason, according to critics, for colonizers to have justified their colonization using fiduciary excuses.Footnote 144 They also complain that it provides little traction into the question of what public officials ought to do.Footnote 145 A procedural question about how much deference to lend the trustee is often really a substantive question about how the trustee ought to act.Footnote 146

I suggest that this open-endedness is a feature, not a bug. This is because what is in a beneficiary's best interests is subject to construction and contestation; it is always permeable to democratic politics. Determinations about what's in the “public interest” is a constructed product of politics, not a precondition that establishes the need for politics.Footnote 147 Contests about who ought to be included in the dêmos, where its interests lie, and how best to achieve them are the fuel that motor political discourse. Especially in conjunction with the highly mediated tripartite trustee model, citizens’ democratic instincts will accordingly drive them to critique trustees’ best interest determinations. To illustrate, consider an agency tasked to promote public education. Debates will arise over who, exactly, is included in this public and what, exactly, its best interests are.Footnote 148 Is the public interest best served by targeting the education of minor children or adults? Is it best served by prioritizing elementary education or higher education? The maths and sciences or the humanities? The determination of “interest” is not the only thing politics needs to construct. It also needs to construct what it means by “public.” Indeed, “the functioning of representative democracy depends upon politicians being able to offer competing visions of the people to the people.”Footnote 149 Are we a technologically advanced society dedicated to industrial innovation, or a society of letters and literature? Are we an agricultural heartleand or a cosmopolitan center of commerce? Often, our competing answers to these questions map on to our partisan cleavages. For example, are immigrants included in the dêmos? Is it in the interest of the dêmos to ensure a minimum standard for all students, or should we prioritize choice and competitive merit? Will we best achieve these goals through privatization or by funding public schools? Finally, because interests cantilever between objectivity and subjectivity, they require construction by political actors who can and should be challenged within democratic politics.Footnote 150 The agency on public education might prioritize high-level reading skills because, objectively, reading is a prerequisite to satisfying and remunerative employment. But what about those who prefer working with their hands?

Stated more directly, the bests interests calculation is a political question, not a legal one. It should not be surprising, therefore, that the democratic politics surrounding administrative policymaking erupts during presidential elections. Selecting a president becomes a proxy for selecting, for example, the best interests of the public when it comes to immigration policy, climate policy, competition policy, and so on. So long as the trustee representative obeys its minimum substantive duties, courts should avoid interfering. Meanwhile, like most political questions, there is room for democratizing the answers. Additional institutions can lend citizens and their interests more presence within a trustee representative's decision-making. For example, trustees can accept public feedback and respond to public objections. Their decisions can be made transparent and publicly available. Further, if the trustee is not an individual, but a body, that body might be staffed by elected, gyroscopic or descriptive representatives. Using carefully designed representative systems, unlike direct participation mechanisms, can help ensure that proceedings remain efficient and elude capture by well-resourced interests.Footnote 151

C. Trustee Authorization

Finally, it is important to make clear what authorization purports to do—and what it does not. From Hobbes,Footnote 152 we know that authority is conferred by an author, the person who has the right to act. Within the context of trustee representation, this authorizer is recognized as having legitimate power to appoint a trustee to care for the interests of a beneficiary. It is also recognized as having the legitimate power to define the scope of a trustee's duties: to determine what is ultra vires and thus not an act of representation.Footnote 153 Sometimes this legitimacy arises from a pre-existing normative relationship between the authorizer and beneficiary.Footnote 154 For example, a parent might authorize a fiduciary to invest funds on behalf of a minor child. Unlike in a principal–agent model, this relationship is not identity: there is reason to treat authorizers as distinct moral agents whose interests may diverge from those of the beneficiary.Footnote 155 Despite the relationship between parent and child, the trustee is not the parent's agent. In fact, to fulfill its duties, a trustee might find itself acting against the parent's express wishes. The parent might want the trustee to contribute trust funds to her pyramid scheme. The trustee, duty bound to act in the child's best interests, should refuse.Footnote 156

Within the context of democratic politics, the capacity to authorize a trustee representative is usually attributed to a sovereign “people,” sometimes through a founding constitutional document.Footnote 157 Of course, as Hobbes pointed out, “the people” does not exist prior to its representation. There is only the multitude.Footnote 158 As a result, his analytical scheme of political legitimacy required the concurrent appointment of a representative and the creation of the people through that representative.Footnote 159 A more democratically appealing option is for individual voters, each of whom has a claim to be part of “the people,” to authorize trustees by participating in elections.Footnote 160 Specific individual voters jointly authorize members of Congress and the President, as trustee representatives, to decide collectively on the laws that best serve the people-as-beneficiary. Moreover, the model recognizes that the-people-as-beneficiary is a moral agent distinct from the-people-as-authorizers. As a result, these representatives might provide for the interests of those who cannot vote, those who voted for someone else, those who are not yet born, and so on. This gap also opens up space for various trustees’ rival claims to represent the interests of the people-as-beneficiaries. It thus is congenial to a constitution that separates powers and facilitates political opposition. For example, particular subsets of the population elect members of Congress. Another distinct subset elects the President. Both Congress and the President have authority to represent the people-as-beneficiaries, whose interests cannot be reduced to those of their (distinct) authorizers.

Of course, the boundaries of a trustee's authority are not always clear. Congress may be authorized by “the people,” acting through the Constitution, to regulate interstate commerce,Footnote 161 but hesitate over whether its authority includes firearm regulations that protect victims of domestic violence. At this point, one observation should be clear. Given the autonomy ascribed to the trustee, it should not simply take the authorizer's interpretation at face value. Its duty is owed to the beneficiary, not the authorizer. After all, the trustee representative is not representing the authorizer. It is representing the beneficiary. And the authorizer may have interests that conflict with those of the beneficiary. Because the trustee is duty bound to wield its authority in the beneficiary's best interests, it should reject any instructions that do not serve those interests. Accordingly, from the trustee's viewpoint, the question of authority often resolves, like any best interests determination, into a political question—not a legal one.

VI. Agencies are Trustee Representatives

With the parameters of the trustee model defined, it can now be applied to administration. Here, I argue that administration can be understood as a form of democratic trustee representation. Presuming that the model lends legitimacy to political decision-making by helping to establish democratic autonomy, there is consequently good reason to believe that administrative agencies enjoy a source of democratic legitimacy—even if they fail to follow the precise marching orders of a Congressional principal. Furthermore, applying the model to administration explains why certain superficially undemocratic agency actions can nonetheless claim democratic credentials.

A. Coherence with Administrative Practice

The idea that an administrative agency is a trustee representative acting in the public interest fits comfortably with actual administrative practice. As Joseph Heath observes, “there is little disagreement that the civil servant should be committed to serving ‘the public interest,’ or ‘the general good’.”Footnote 162 The Interstate Commerce Commission, established in 1887, was charged by statute with “protecting and promoting the public interest” by establishing “reasonable and just” and non-discriminatory railway rates.Footnote 163 Historically, courts have afforded autonomy to civil servants because they worked within institutions designed to evade capture by private, special, or pecuniary interests.Footnote 164 Unlike courts, agencies self-consciously engage in general, all-things-considered policymaking that impacts a broad group of individuals rather than opine, as courts do, on the rights of particular parties.Footnote 165 Furthermore, the development of public administration within the United States developed concurrently with social sciences that articulated a concept of public welfare and the public good.Footnote 166

The case that administrative agencies are successful democratic trustee representatives is elaborated in more detail below.

1. Agencies Act in the Public Interest

As noted above, a trustee representative has a duty to act in the public interest. The notion of the public and its interest promotes in trustee representatives an inclusive cognitive orientation that is congenial to democratic autonomy. Historically, agencies have fulfilled this duty. In fact, it is this inclusive cognitive orientation that made independent administrative agencies so attractive to early twentieth century progressives. Believing that political decision-making too often followed the preferences of big business “plutocrats,” they suggested the use of independent commissions charged with acting in the “public interest” precisely because they could give voice to the voiceless.Footnote 167 For example, the Interstate Commerce Commission assessed the impact of railroad monopoly rates on disempowered Midwest farmers. To help justify the government setting of prices, Congress characterized railroads as public utilities. Moreover, formally enslaved people, having been shut out of electoral politics, found presence in the Reconstruction era Freedman's Bureau.Footnote 168

Also consistent with the model, there is no reason to characterize administrators as Platonic guardians of a justiciable public good. As Klein,Footnote 169 Emerson,Footnote 170 and Rahman and GilmanFootnote 171 argue, administration opens up a space for democratic evaluation, debate and judgment. Happily, there are many points of entry for citizens, or their representatives, to intervene in agency decisions about the nature of the public and its interest. One such entry point is the politics surrounding the presidency. As remarked earlier, presidential elections often center upon agency policy: how much pollution the Environmental Protection Agency (“EPA”) should eliminate; how much commerce the FTC should regulate, and so on. Hoping to secure electoral support, presidential candidates will mobilize voters by deploying competing policy visions. Once in office, more democratic doorways open as cabinet officials are nominated, vetted by both Congress and the press, and appointed. Meanwhile, appointees themselves serve as successful descriptive or gyroscopic representatives.Footnote 172 Each step involved in the election and operation of a presidential administration thus provides opportunities not only for citizens to participate, but also for an administration to prioritize their interests. Presidential influence in agency policymaking is one way whereby elections “mean something,” giving citizens a cognizable role to play in shaping the regulations that bind them by, for example, voting, surveilling, and objecting. Popular demands for civil rights protections and pollution control percolate into executive orders commanding agencies to assess the costs of discrimination and climate change. It also vindicates democratic autonomy when it is suffocated elsewhere—for example, if Congressional action is gridlocked or disfigured by gerrymanders, filibusters, and other antimajoritarian obstacles.

Of course, the President cannot speak with the “voice of the people” any more than Congress can. Presidential influence always flirts with Schmittian decisionism. Moreover, given the complexity of policy, voters are vulnerable to manipulation by an enterprising chief executive who convinces them, for example, that “building a wall” will solve immigration issues. Regardless, extant law tempers the possibility of presidential diktat by forcing agencies to address and incorporate other voices while basing their decisions on research and evidence. In other words, it forces agencies to act like trustees, not like hirelings and toadies. The Administrative Procedure Act (APA)Footnote 173 not only requires agencies to solicit public comment for formal rulemaking, but also to provide reasoned responses and cogent explanations for its actions.Footnote 174 They compel agencies to expose their reasoning process to the public as early as possible to facilitate dialogue and objection.Footnote 175 Concomitantly, it forbids ex parte communications between the President and the agency during formal rulemaking,Footnote 176 and the justifications provided by agencies must be public-regarding, based on claims that incorporate some understandable vision of the public welfare or public purposes.Footnote 177 Meanwhile, Congress retains someFootnote 178 power to insulate agency decision-making from executive control. The Pendleton Civil Service ActFootnote 179 and the Civil Service Reform Act,Footnote 180for example, require that positions within administration should be distributed based on merit, not through political patronage. Congress might improve upon these populist prophylactics by, for example, demanding that agency decision-making bodies be staffed by gyroscopic and descriptive representatives that are likely to keep faith with their statutory mandates. Finally, courts ensure that agencies do not, at presidential behest, interpret their statutory authority beyond reason.

2. Agency Authorization is Trustee Authorization

The trustee model coheres with administrative practice for another reason. Under the model, a trustee representative must be authorized by a party with the right to act in relation to the beneficiary. In current practice, the agency's authority to act has statutory provenance.Footnote 181 As explained above, congressional statutes command authority because, and to the extent that they, result from processes that vindicate the democratic autonomy enjoyed by the populace. Congress, using the procedures of bicameralism and presentment, entrusts administrative agencies to care for the interests of beneficiaries identified within organizing statutes that establish and define the duties of, for instance, the FTCFootnote 182 and the Securities Exchange Commission (SEC).Footnote 183 The “intelligible principle”Footnote 184 provided by statutory language, presuming it is so provided, lays out the scope of the agency's authority. This authorization procedure respects the idea that authority derives from by the people by incorporating democratic presence indirectly, via the election of lawmakers, and directly, by virtue of any public debates that shape the statute's content.

Although the statutory authorization of administrative agencies is not an explicit component of the trustee model of representation, the two share many characteristics. First, the original trustee model likewise contemplates the use of a binding text: the Constitution. Elected lawmakers, like trustee administrators, must also point to codified authority. Second, agencies’ implementing statutes are not precise marching orders provided by a principal to an obedient agent, as a transmission belt theory might imply. Rather, they are consistent with the autonomy afforded a trustee representative. Despite their “intelligible principles,” agencies’ organizing laws are often open-ended and vague, resembling more closely a deed of trust than a system of command-and-control. Indeed, many organizing statutes explicitly contemplate that agencies will promulgate binding rules as they undertake their duties. For example, under the Federal Trade Commission Act, the FTC may “prescribe (A) interpretive rules and general statements of policy with respect to unfair or deceptive acts or practices … and (b) rules which define with specificity acts or practices which are unfair or deceptive.”Footnote 185 Although a trustee may not act beyond the scope of its authorization, the parameters of its authorization are often underdeterminate or indeterminate. Which practices are “unfair,” and thus subject to FTC rulemaking, is far from obvious. Questions about the scope of an agency's authority thus become questions of statutory interpretation. So, according to the model, how should a statute be interpreted and who should interpret it?

First, an agency need not wait upon Congress for further instruction that may never issue forth. If an agency is a trustee, it is not an agent of Congress. As trustees, agencies are bound instead to act on behalf of and in the interest of the beneficiaries identified in their authorizing statutes. Consequently, questions about what Congress intended, or would have intended, had it considered the specific issue at hand are largely irrelevant from the trustee's point of view. Instead, the agency trustee must interpret and implement an indeterminate statute in a manner that best serves its beneficiary's interest—subject to the minimum constraints set forth above (diligence, good faith, care, and so on). Of course, this conclusion resonates with the deferential Chevron doctrine,Footnote 186 whereby courts would yield to agencies’ interpretations of their own authority so long as they are not “arbitrary, capricious, or manifestly contrary to the statute.” These features provide a third reason why statutory authorization comports with the trustee model.

Before moving on, it is useful to note that empowering agencies to interpret their own authority need not be seen as antidemocratic. Recall that democratic congressional authority is not sui generis; it is legitimate only to the extent that it exhibits democratic autonomy. Recall also that other representative processes can likewise express democratic autonomy. As a result, there is no reason to think that only Congress, through bicameralism and presentment, can make democratically legitimate policy—including the policymaking inherent to statutory interpretation. Further, as argued above, administrative agencies are commonly obliged to act on behalf of beneficiaries that are politically disempowered vis-à-vis other citizens. If these agencies interpret their own authorizing statutes, they can therefore ameliorate political inequalities within other decision-making venues. To illustrate, citizens suffering from socio-economic hardships might find democratic representation in the EEOC's interpretation of its own statute, especially when judicial intervention or congressional influence might prove hostile to their interests. Agency interpretation is also helpful when a mechanical application of statutes works against the public interest. Even street-level bureaucrats will better serve the public if they bend a few rules.Footnote 187 Nor is there a compelling reason to wait for Congress to elaborate upon the meaning of an ambiguous statute. Agency inaction may be the least democratic action available because it preserves a status quo that many citizens might find untenable.

This approach has, at least, more democratic appeal than delegating to courts the duty to provide determinative interpretations of indeterminate authorizing statutes. When a court, for example, forces an agency to wait for further congressional orders, it swaps the agency's interpretation for its own by holding that what is clear to the agency is not, in fact, clear to the court.Footnote 188 Given agencies’ expertise and experience, they are better placed to interpret in a manner that serves the public interest in a way that recognizes the interests of many. Courts, of course, may only recognize the interests of litigants sub judice and can deploy no special expertise in determining their decision's social and political knock-on effects.Footnote 189

3. The Autonomy of Agencies is the Autonomy of a Trustee

Administrative agencies, as explained at the outset of this article, invariably enjoy decision-making autonomy. Unlike the transmission belt model, the trustee model of representation can accommodate it without logical gymnastics and a naïve belief in fantastic fictions. Instead, it is part and parcel of successful trustee representation: a trustee independent of both authorizer and beneficiary can represent persons and interests overlooked by other representative institutions.

4. Agency Legal Constraints are Trustee Constraints

As alluded to earlier in this section, the trustee model and administrative law also correspond in the constraints they each impose on officials’ decision-making. First, agencies, like trustees, must be authorized to act. In each context, reviewing courts can play a role in guarding against actions taken ultra vires. Meanwhile, the scope of agency authorization is often indeterminate, involving political choices best left to political institutions. The intelligible principle and Chevron doctrinesFootnote 190 capture this notion neatly.

Furthermore, to act in the beneficiary's best interests, and therefore provide representation to that beneficiary, a trustee must assume several derivative duties: care, loyalty, and good faith. Fortunately for the success of the trustee model, these normative benchmarks parallel extant legal rules governing administrative decision-making. Administrative officers, for example, cannot be reckless in their conclusions nor act through blatant self-interest. Under the APA, courts may invalidate actions that are arbitrary, capricious, or an abuse of discretion.Footnote 191 A CDC official cannot, in good faith, claim how to address contagious disease without any supporting research or investigation. They should base decisions on facts, not fairy tales.Footnote 192 The APA's formal rulemaking requirements,Footnote 193 which require a judicially enforced, trial-type evidentiary hearing, enforce a duty of care and diligence.Footnote 194 Like private fiduciary duties, judicial review of agency decisions can be more or less deferential. In fact, courts seem to be moving in an invasive direction, demanding “that agencies provide increasingly detailed and persuasive justifications for their discretionary policy decisions.”Footnote 195 This movement is uncongenial to the politics-friendly trustee model discussed here.

5. A Tripartite Model for a Tripartite Practice

Finally, the model's separation of administrative trustee from both authorizer and beneficiary mirrors common understandings of how administration ought to operate.Footnote 196 Namely, administrators are not employees of their authorizers. They are servants of the public. The U.S. Federal Reserve System does not take marching orders from elected representatives who hope that a little inflation might improve their chances at the voting booth. Instead, an independent board must attempt to “maintain long run growth of the monetary and credit aggregates commensurate with the economy's long run potential to increase production, so as to promote effectively the goals of maximum employment, stable prices, and moderate long-term interest rates.”Footnote 197 The CDC's job is not care for the health of voters living in 1946, when it was established, but care for the populace as it exists today and will exist tomorrow.

B. The Benefits of the Trustee Model

Thus, the trustee model of political representation reasonably describes and therefore lends democratic credentials to administrative agencies. Citizens have “presence” within agencies not only because agencies respect their duty to act in citizen beneficiaries’ interests, but because extant law and culture encourage them to do so. Further, agencies’ best interests determinations are appropriately politicized, permeable to the input of citizens and their representatives. Moreover, citizens enjoy presence in the lawmaking process that results in agencies’ statutory authorization. One upshot of this conclusion is that it can explain why some agency actions that appear to be undemocratic may not be undemocratic at all.

Agency officials occasionally find themselves confronting elected lawmakers hostile to their mandates. The EPA, authorized to protect the public from pollution, might face representatives who would rather scrap its regulations because of the onerous burden they place upon businesses and landowners. Industry-aligned presidential political appointees might mobilize to erase EPA policy, and congressional hearings might commence with the aim to embarrass and delegitimize the EPA before the public. Driven by a democratic instinct, one might conclude that the EPA should capitulate. If this is the direction that popular winds blow, who is an unelected agency official to object? The trustee model explains why it should not—and why its refusal is democratic. The EPA, as a trustee representative, is no presidential mouthpiece. Nor is it the appointed agent of any particular congressional representative—or their wealthy constituents. The EPA is instead a trustee representative duty bound to serve the public interest identified in its statutory mandate. One reason that this kind of representation is so appealing is precisely because it stands firm in the face of both changeable popular opinion and the pressure applied by a highly resourced, self-interested minority. It provides a bulwark against populist inclinations. It provides representation for beneficiaries whose voices are not adequately represented by congressional and presidential politics. Thus, to radically undermine EPA policy (or burn it to the ground), lawmakers have to pass new legislation.

Another benefit of the model is that it suggests agencies are at least sometimes permitted to make policy that lacks clear statutory provenance. To illustrate, the Department of Education might implement a universal student loan forgiveness plan under a statute meant to address national economic emergencies. It does so knowing that a powerful industry lobby, using its plentiful cash reserves, routinely convinces lawmakers to block any and all legislation related to forgiving the debt of ordinary consumers. Rather than conclude that the Department's plan is egregious executive overreach, we might also consider that the agency attended to interests of those illegitimately excluded from a corrupt legislative process. As Emerson notes, proponents of New Deal agencies promoted them because they could protect people who, as a result of the complexity and inequality intrinsic in the modern economy, could not initiate action to protect themselves.Footnote 198 “[G]iven the constant inequality generating pressures of the capitalist economy,” notes political theorist Kevin Olson, administration may be “required to maintain the conditions under which the sovereignty of citizens can be fairly and accurately translated into law.”Footnote 199

Finally, administrative agencies can help to maintain constitutional representative democracy itself. Consider a scenario where a single party captures the executive and the legislature. That party then seeks to change election rules in its favor, securing power for years to come. An agency committed to civil rights might step in to protect the franchise, even if it seems to do so against democratic currents and even if such questions are deemed nonjusticiable “political” questions.Footnote 200 The trustee model can tell us why agency intervention is nevertheless democratic: it protects democratic autonomy, securing representation for those excluded from the political process. Consider also a U.S. Attorney General, a political appointee, countermanding the orders of a president to weaponize the Department of Justice in a bid to overturn the results of an election. Despite the President's appointment power, the U.S. Attorney General is not his personal lawyer. The Attorney General, rather, is authorized by the Judiciary Act of 1789 to represent “the people.” The U.S. Attorney General, if abiding by his duty to serve the people and its interest, can refuse and still deserve to be called democratic.

VI. Conclusion

Much of modern administration, given the democratic credentials lent it by the trustee model of representation, is likely legitimate. It facilitates democratic autonomy by giving citizens presence in decisions that, by their nature, elide direct participation. It is, of course, unlikely that courts hostile to administrative policymaking will take seriously the public trust held by administrators. But for political and legal theorists, thinking of agencies as trustee representatives invites us to consider that agencies, far from being embarrassing leviathans requiring restraint, might be part and parcel of a system of collective, democratic power.

Footnotes

Assistant Professor of Law, University of Cincinnati College of Law, United States. I give my hearty thanks to Professors Blake Emerson (UCLA), Robert L. Goodman (Toronto Metropolitan University), Luke Herrine (University of Alabama) and Turkuler Isiksel (Columbia University) for their invaluable feedback, discussions, and support. I also extend my thanks to the anonymous reviewers whose comments significantly shaped and improved my arguments. All mistakes are my own. Versions of my argument have also benefited from the comments of Professor Mark Seidenfeld (Michigan State) and the generous faculty members of the University of Cincinnati College of Law.

References

2 Seidenfeld, Mark, The Role of Politics in a Deliberative Model of the Administrative State, 81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 1397, 1403 (2013)Google Scholar; Stewart, Richard B., The Reformation of American Administrative Law, 88 Harv. L. Rev. 1667, 1675 (1975)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Gundy v. United States, 139 S. Ct. 2116, 2136 (2019 (Gorsuch, J., dissenting).

4 Brugué, Quim & Gallego, Raquel, A Democratic Public Administration?, 5 Pub. Mgmt. Rev. 425, 426 (2003)Google Scholar; Pierre Rosanvallon, Good Government: Democracy Beyond Elections 26 (Malcolm DeBevoise trans., 2018).

5 Wilson, Woodrow, The Study of Administration, 2 Pol. Sci. Q. 197, 212 (1887)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Joseph Heath, The Machinery of Government: Public Administration and the Liberal State 17 (2020).

7 Ibid.; see also Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule, The Executive Unbound: After the Madisonian Republic 8 (2010). Posner and Vermuele 2011, 8; Baumann, Beau J., Americana Administrative Law, 111 Geo. L.J. 465, 471–73 (2023)Google Scholar.

8 Chiara Cordelli, The Privatized State 85 (2020).

9 Steven Klein, The Work of Politics: Making a Democratic Welfare State 172 (2020). See also Bernardo Zacka, When the State Meets the Street: Public Service and Moral Agency 23 (2017) (observing that “‘street-level bureaucrat[s]’ … belong to both the ‘Left hand’ of the state, the one that delivers social services, and to the ‘Right hand,’ [of the state,] which enforces order and economic discipline”).

10 E.g., William Niskanen, Bureaucracy and Representative Government (1971).

11 E.g., Goodin, Robert E., Welfare, Rights and Discretion, 6 Oxford J. Leg. Stud. 232, 250–53 (1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Christiano, Thomas, Democracy and Bureaucracy, 71 Phil. & Phenomenological Rsch. 211 (2005)Google Scholar

12 E.g., Health, supra note 6; Cordelli, supra note 8.

13 E.g., Evan J. Criddle, Fiduciary Administration: Rethinking Popular Representation in Agency Rulemaking, 88 Tex. L. Rev. 441 (2010).

14 Jürgen Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society 233–35 (Thomas Burger & Frederick Lawrence trans., 1989) (1962) [hereinafter Habermas (1962)]; Max Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism 34–38 (Talcott Parsons trans., 2005) (1930). See also Max Weber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology (Guenther Roth & Claus Wittich eds., 1978) (1968) [hereinafter Weber (1968)] (describing how economics, politics, and social interaction shape society); Jürgen Habermas, Legitimation Crisis 101–02 (Thomas McCarthy trans., 1975) (1973) [hereinafter Habermas (1973)] (discussing the difficulties of legitimacy and governance faced by contemporary societies).

15 William J. Novak, New Democracy: The Creation of the Modern American State 233 (2022).

16 Glen Staszewski, Political Reasons, Deliberative Democracy, and Administrative Law, 97 Iowa L. Rev. 849, 856 (2012); see also Criddle, supra note 13, at 450; Industrial Union Department, AFL-CIO v. American Petroleum Institute, 480 US 607, 685 (1980) (Rehnquist, J.)).

17 Klein, supra note 9, at 93 (citing Weber).

18 E.g., Frank H. Easterbrook, What Does Legislative History Tell Us?, 66 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 441, 441 (1990) (given work in public choice, it is “misleading to speak of ‘the legislature’ as an entity with a mind or purpose or intent”); cf. Christian List & Philip Pettit, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents 59 (2011) (arguing, in contrast, that group agents like Congress can have an intention that “supervenes” on the intentions of group members. They, however, distance themselves from the more organic conception of group (corporate) personality espoused by Maitland, Figgis, Laski and other turn-of-the-century pluralists).

19 E.g., “original public meaning,” purposivisim, textualism, constitutional avoidance, the mischief theory, etc.

20 Blake Emerson, Administrative Answers to Major Questions: On the Democratic Legitimacy of Agency Statutory Interpretation, 102 Minn. L. Rev. 2019. 2044 (2018).

21 E.g., Id., 2074; Henry S. Richardson, Democratic Autonomy: Public Reasoning About the Ends of Policy 116 (2002); Jerry L. Mashaw, Reasoned Administration and Democratic Legitimacy: How Administrative Law Supports Democratic Government (2018); Klein, supra note 9.

22 See, e.g., Brian Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered, 111 Ethics 278, 295–96 (2001); Posner & Vermeule, supra note 7, at 13–14; Ronald Dworkin, Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution 8–9 (1996); Christopher F. Zurn, Deliberative Democracy and Constitutional Review, 21 L. & Phil. 467, 478–79 (2002); The Federalist No. 37 (James Madison).

23 A.V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution 81 (8th ed. 1915) (1885).

24 E.g., Bryan Garsten, Representative Government and Popular Sovereignty, in Political Representation 90, 90 (Ian Shapiro, Susan C. Stokes, Elisabeth Jean Wood & Alexander Kirschner eds., 2009).

25 E.g., Criddle, supra note 13, at 457; Hannah Fenichel Pitkin, The Concept of Representation 215 (1967) 215; Andreas Kalyvas, Popular Sovereignty, Democracy, and the Constituent Power, 12 Constellations 223, 224 (2005); see generally Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (Harper Perennial Modern Thought ed., 2008) (1942).

26 Pitkin, supra note 25 at 147.

27 Id., 215; Jeffrey Edward Green, The Eyes of the People: Democracy in an Age of Spectatorship 33 (2010); André Blais & Robert Young, Why Do People Vote? An Experiment in Rationality, 99 Pub. Choice 39, 43 (1999); Martin A. Maldonado, Voter Apathy, in Encyclopedia of U.S. Campaigns, Elections, and Electoral Behavior 829–31 (Kenneth F. Warren ed., 2008); Schumpeter, supra note 25, at 251; Jud Mathews, Minimally Democratic Administrative Law, 68 Admin. L. Rev. 605, 637 (2016).

28 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 170.

29 E.g. Heath, supra note 6, at 64.

30 Garsten, supra note 24, at 90; Bruce Ackerman, The New Separation of Powers, 113 Harv. L. Rev. 633, 656 (2000); Mashaw, supra note 21, at 170.

31 See generally Robert L. Goodman, Words on Fire (2021).

32 Mónica Brito Vieira & David Runciman, Representation 138 (2008) 95; Richard Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism: A Republican Defence of the Constitutionality of Democracy 54–55 (2007); Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement 277 (1999).

33 Cordelli, supra note 8, at 57.

34 Vieira, supra note 32, at 138.

35 One response is to conclude that most lawmaking lacks democratic legitimacy. Rousseau argued that laws should be simple, general, and obvious. Many conservative jurists—including Justice Gorsuch—might agree. Voters are only able to consent, en masse, to these types of law. This outcome is not, however, straightforwardly democratic. Where the state does not rule, powerful private actors will rule instead. Brian Hutler & Anne Barnhill, SNAP Exclusions and the Role of Citizen Participation in Policy-Making, 38 Soc. Phil. & Pol'y 266, 286–87 (2021). Further, if laws are vague and general, unelected judges will inevitably fill in the regulatory blanks. Daniel R. Ernst, Tocqueville's Nightmare: The Administrative State Emerges in America 13 (2014); Novak, supra note 15. Moreover, legal complexity is a result of democratic demands for market intervention. Norberto Bobbio, The Future of Democracy 38 (Richard Bellamy ed., Roger Griffin trans., 1987) (1984); Blake Emerson, The Public's Law: Origins and Architecture of Progressive Democracy (2019). In any event, it is notable that Rousseau himself leaned heavily on expert government ministers that, like a travel agent, were to present legislation to the sovereign for approval. Nadia Urbinati, Continuity and Rupture: The Power of Judgment in Democratic Representation, 12 Constellations 194, 207 (2005).

36 Garsten, supra note 24, at 99.

37 F.R. Ankersmit, Aesthetic Politics: Political Philosophy Beyond Fact and Value 104 (1996).

38 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 11.

39 Id.

40 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 43.

41 Bellamy, supra note 32, at 4; Waldron, supra note 32.

42 See Pitkin, supra note 25, at 195 (discussing Burke and The Federalist authors’ views on congressional involvement and balancing popular interest); Glen Staszewski, Rejecting the Myth of Popular Sovereignty and Applying an Agency Model to Direct Democracy, 56 Vand. L. Rev., 395, 398 (2003). Chief Justice Roberts adopts this version in Seila Law, LLC v. Consumer Fin. Prot. Bureau, 140 S. Ct. 2183, 2203 (2020) (citing The Federalist No. 70 (Alexander Hamilton)).

43 Franz Neumann, Types of Natural Law, in The Democratic and The Authoritarian State 69, 89 (Herbert Marcuse ed., 1957). See also Gundy v. United States, 139 S. Ct. 2116, 2133 (2019) (Gorsuch, J., dissenting) (discussing his theory of nondelegation); Klein, supra note 9, at 85 note 52 (summarizing Weber's relationship to the refeudalization thesis).

44 Cordelli, supra note 8, at 139.

45 Ibid. at 138.

46 Garsten, supra note 24, at 104.

47 Cordelli, supra note 8, at 62.

48 Andrew Sabl, The Two Cultures of Democratic Theory: Responsiveness, Democratic Quality, and the Empirical-Normative Divide, 13 Perspective on Politics 345 (2017).

49 Lisa Disch, Toward a Mobilization Conception of Democratic Representation, 105 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 100, 101 (2011).

50 Jane Mansbridge, Rethinking Representation, 97 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 516 (2003).

51 Sabl, supra note 48, at 346.

52 Ibid. at 347.

53 Garsten, supra note 24, at 105.

54 Philip Pettit, Varieties of Public Representation, in Political Representation 61 (Ian Shapiro, Susan C. Stokes, Elisabeth Jean Wood & Alexander S. Kirschner eds., 2009).

55 Urbinati, supra note 35, at 196; Pitkin, supra note 25, at 191; Mansbridge, supra note 50, at 515; David Plotke, Representation is Democracy, 4 Constellations 19 (1997); The Federalist No. 52 (Alexander Hamilton or James Madison).

56 Pitkin, supra note 25, at 170; Garsten, supra note 24, at 105.

57 Cordelli, supra note 8, at 11, 67.

58 Ibid. at 62.

59 Nadia Urbinati & Mark E. Warren, The Concept of Representation in Contemporary Democratic Theory, 11 Ann. Rev. Pol. Sci. 387, 395 (2008).

60 Supra note 32; see also Anthony Michael Bertelli, Democracy Administered: How Public Administration Shapes Representative Government 13 (2021). See generally Robert A. Dahl, Myth of the Presidential Mandate, 105 Pol. Sci. Q. 355, 362–64 (1990). For a similar account, see Daniel E. Walters, The Administrative Agon: A Democratic Theory for a Conflictual Regulatory State, 132 Yale L.J. 1, 37 (2022) (democratic values are best instantiated when citizens have an opportunity to resist political settlement).

61 Paul Miller attributes this institutional flexibility to the capacious generalizability to the theory of representation created by Thomas Hobbes. Paul B. Miller, Fiduciary Representation, in Fiduciary Government 36, 43–45 (Evan J. Criddle, Evan Fox-Decent, Andrew S. Gold, Sung Kim & Paul B. Miller eds., 2018).

62 Mansbridge, supra note 50, at 515 (introducing several different forms of representation); Pitkin, supra note 25, at 11–12 (likewise introducing several different conceptions of representation).

63 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 111–12 (“Representation by someone who is ‘one of us’ therefore works as a kind of cognitive division of [labor].”); Clarissa Rile Hayward, Making Interest: On Representation and Democratic Legitimacy, in Political Representation, 111, 114 (Ian Shapiro, Susan C. Stokes, Elisabeth Jean Wood & Alexander S. Kirschner eds., 2009).

64 Hayward, supra note 63, at 115.

65 Mansbridge, supra note 50, at 520.

66 Ibid., 522.

67 Pitkin supra note 25, at 127–129.

68 Compare this conception of Congressional representation from the principal–agent model, which may yield constituency-specific benefits—that is, “pork” politics.

69 Criddle, supra note 13, at 471.

70 Ibid.

71 See, e.g., Joseph Emmanuel Sieyès, Political Writings 13 (Michael Sonenscher, trans., 2003)

72 Pitkin supra note 25, at 169.

73 The Federalist No. 10 (James Madison).

74 Ackerman, supra note 30, at 24; Runciman and Vieira, supra note 32, at 163. This argument reflects Federalists’ counterintuitive point that by limiting the type of and number of individuals who might serve as representatives (here, that such representatives act as good faith, loyal and diligent fiduciaries of the public) could expand the means by which the people could be represented as a whole. See Runciman & Vieira, supra note 30, at 40. It also resonates with Burke's idea of “virtual” representation, whereby representatives act on behalf of the disenfranchised.

75 See Criddle, supra note 13, at 471.

76 Kevin Olson, Reflexive Democracy: Political Equality and the Welfare State 108, 122 (2006).

77 Bernard Williams, In the Beginning was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument 3 (Geoffrey Hawthorn ed., 2005) (“the ‘first’ political question is posed in Hobbesian terms as the securing of order, protection, safety, trust, and the conditions of cooperation.”)

78 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 101.

79 Hannah Arendt, Truth and Politics, New Yorker, Feb. 25, 1967, at 49.

80 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 60.

81 See, e.g., Michael Saward, The Representative Claim, 5 Contemp. Pol. Theory 297, 309–10 (2006); Lisa Disch, The “Constructivist Turn” in Democratic Representation: A Normative Dead-End?, 22 Constellations 487, 488 (2015); Andrew Rehfeld, Towards a General Theory of Political Representation, 68 J. Pol. 1, 2 (2006).

82 E.g., Rehfeld, supra note 81, at 13–17. See also Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 101 (describing that the political trustee representation mimics constructivist accounts: groups “rely on their representatives … [to] interpret the group's interest, and in so doing put forth a claim to be representing it. This claim, by its very interpretative nature, is open to be challenged by rival claims of different representatives”).

83 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 101.

84 Disch, supra note 82, at 493.

85 Monica Brito Vieira, Introduction, in Reclaiming Representation: Contemporary Advances in the Theory of Political Representation 1, 15 (Mónica B. Vieira ed., 2017).

86 Novak, supra note 15, at 220.

87 Cordelli, supra note 8, at 199; see generally Filipe Rey, The Representative System, 26 Crit. Rev. of Int'l Social & Political Phil. 831 (2020).

88 This idea approaches List and Pettit's notion of “supervenience,” whereby the actions of the group agent are attributable, but not reducible, to the contributions of the group's individual members. Christian List & Philip Pettit, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents 59 (2011).

89 Adrian Vermuele, Law's Abnegation (2016) (providing an argument rejecting a stricting separation of powers and labelling adherence to the doctrine “idolatrous”).

90 See Richard Primus, Herein of ‘Herein Granted”: Why Article I's Vesting Clause Does Not Support the Doctrine of Enumerated Powers, 35 Const. Commentary 310 (2020) for an argument rejecting the Vesting Clause and the enumerated powers doctrine.

91 Anthony Michael Bertelli, Democracy Administered: How Public Administration Shapes Representative Government 13 (2021).

92 Heath, supra note 6, at 76; Bernardo Zacka, Political Theory Rediscovers Public Administration, 25 Ann. Rev. Pol. Sci. 21, 29 (2022).

93 Pitkin, supra note 25, at 212. Accord Richardson, supra note 21, at 116; Samuel DeCanio, Efficiency, Legitimacy, and the Administrative State, 38 Soc. Phil. & Pol'y 198, 204 (2021).

94 Recent opinions applying the major questions doctrine include Texas v. United States, 809 F.3d 134, 181 (5th Cir. 2015), aff'd, 136 S. Ct. 2271 (2016) (despite an explicit grant of policymaking discretion to the agency, the Court used the MQD to deny it); Nat'l Fed'n of Indep. Bus. v. Dep't of Labor, 142 S. Ct. 661 (2022) (vaccine-or-test mandate application); Ala. Ass'n of Realtors v. Dep't of Health & Hum. Servs., 141 S. Ct. 2485 (2021) (describing its application during an eviction moratorium); West Virginia v. Env't Prot. Agency, 142 S. Ct. 2587 (2022) (generation-shifting climate regulation); King v. Burwell, 576 U.S. 473 (2015) (reviewing tax credits pertaining to the Affordable Care Act). See also Ronald J. Pestritto, Constitutional and Legal Challenges in the Administrative State, 38 Soc. Phil. Pol'y 6, 18 (2021) (explaining that the “[FDA v. Brown] Court finds it implausible that Congress would intend to make major policy determinations by means of saying nothing about such determinations in a statute”).

95 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 26.

96 Bellamy, supra note 32, at 72. None other than Friedrich Hayek has noted the inherent ambiguity in law. Indeed, he even speculates that this ambiguity may often be purposeful: by agreeing to abstract rules, citizens can paper over their disagreements. F.A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty 12 (1976). See also M.J.C. Vile, Constitutionalism and the Separation of Powers 27–28 (1967) (discussing law's inherent ambiguous generality in the context of Aristotle); The Federalist No. 37 (James Madison).

97 Ibid. at 54–55.

98 Ibid. at 55.

99 See Leiter, supra note 22, at 295–296.

100 Richardson, supra note 21, at 63; Bellamy, supra note 32, at 59–66; Christopher F. Zurn, Deliberative Democracy and Constitutional Review, 21 L. & Phil. 467, 528 (2002).

101 Heath, supra note 6, at 13, 47.

102 Criddle, supra note 13, at 475.

103 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 87.

104 Heath, supra note 6, at 29–30.

105 Ibid. at 11, 59.

106 Ibid. at 47. Novak, supra note 15, at 209, notes that early FTC investigations “led to significant subsequent legislation and administrative regulation as in the passage of the Packers and Stockyards Act of 1921, the establishment of the Federal Oil Conservation Board in 1924, and the Robinson-Patman Act in 1936. Kessler shows the role played by administrators in forming policy on civil liberties and the First Amendment as the struggled over the problem of the conscientious objectors. Jeremy K. Kessler, The Administrative Origins of Modern Civil Liberties Law, 114 Colum. L. Rev. 1083, 1160 (2014).

107 Evan J. Criddle, Evan Fox-Decent, Andrew S. Gold, Sung Hui Kim, and Paul B. Miller, eds., Fiduciary Government (2018).

108 Jed Handelsman Shugerman and Ethan J. Leib, Fiduciary Constitutionalism: Implications for Self-Pardons and Non-Delegation, 17 Geo. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 463 (2019).

109 Ethan J. Leib, David L. Ponet, and Michael Serota, A Fiduciary Theory of Judging, 101 Calif. L. Rev. 699 2013).

110 Andrew Kent, Ethan J. Leib, and Jed Handelsman Shugerman, Faithful Execution and Article II, 132 Harv. L. Rev. 2111 (2019).

111 Bruce A. Green and Rebecca Roiphe, A Fiduciary Theory of Prosecution, 69 Am. U. L. Rev. 805 (2020) (applying fiduciary theory to prosecutorial discretion).

112 Criddle, supra note 13, is an outlier: he couches fiduciaries as democratic representatives.

113 Davis critiques such theories because it facilitates intrusive judicial intervention. Seth Davis, The False Promise of Fiduciary Government, 89 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1145 (2014).

114 See Stephen R. Galoob and Ethan J. Leib, Fiduciary Political Theory and Legitimacy, in Fiduciary Government 168, 176 (Evan J. Criddle, Evan Fox-Decent, Andrew S. Gold, Sung Hui Kim and Paul B. Miller, eds., 2018).

115 Some fiduciary theories explicitly piggyback on republican theories of non-domination. See Galoob & Leib, supra note 115, at 176; Laura Underkuffler, Fiduciary Theory: The Missing Piece for Positive Rights, in Fiduciary Government 96, 109 (Evan J. Criddle, Evan Fox-Decent, Andrew S. Gold, Sung Hui Kim and Paul B. Miller, eds., 2018).

116 Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (William Rehg trans., 1996).

117 See Criddle et al., supra note 109, at 5.

118 See Criddle, supra note 13, at 475; Dmitrios Kyritsis, Representation and Waldron's Objection to Judicial Review, 26 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 733, 743 (2006).

119 Hayward, supra note 63, at 118.

120 Instead, political theorists find themselves reaching to theories outside representation, like ethics, to discuss the duties and responsibilities of representatives. See, e.g., Suzanne Dovi, The Good Representative (2006).

121 Cordelli, supra note 8, at 104; Mashaw, supra note 21, at 57; Pitkin, supra note 25, at 117–118.

122 For a convincing argument that the goal of representative is this kind of inclusion, see Plotke, supra note 55.

123 Novak, supra note 15, at 58.

124 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 53.

125 Criddle, supra note 13, at 473; Kyritsis, supra note 120, at 743.

126 See Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy 25–32 (Ellen Kennedy trans., 1985) (1923).

127 J.S. Mill, On Liberty 7 (1859(2011) (Project Gutenburg eBook).

128 Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America: Historical-Critical Edition, vol. 2 Ch. 7 (1835) (OLL edition).

129 See Nadia Urbinati's conception of representation as advocacy, which combines a strong to commitment to cause and an independent capacity for judgment. This requires not “existential identification” between representative and represented, but instead “an identity of ideals and projects.” Nadia Urbinati, Representation as Advocacy: A Study of Democratic Deliberation, 28 Pol. Theory 758, 773–777 (2000).

130 John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action 154 (2000) (mirroring Edmund Burke, who argued “[t]he most poor, illiterate, and uninformed creatures upon earth are the judges of a practical oppression. It is a matter of feeling…But for the real cause, or the appropriate remedy, they ought never to be called into council”) (quoted in Pitkin, supra note 25, at 183).

131 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 133.

132 Habermas, supra note 119, at 164.

133 Bellamy, supra note 32, at 73–74.

134 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 158.

135 Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire 239 (1986).

136 Daniel E. Walters, The Administrative Agon: A Democratic Theory for a Conflictual Regulatory State, 132 Yale L.J. 1, 39–40 (2022).

137 This is why even the Hobbesian sovereign might be understood to be bound: it acts not for itself, but for the state, and thus he is “not his own man.” Pitkin, supra note 25, at ch. 1.

138 See, e.g., Timothy Endicott, The Public Trust, in Fiduciary Government 306 (Evan J. Criddle, Evan Fox-Decent, Andrew S. Gold, Sung Hui Kim and Paul B. Miller, eds., 2018); Criddle, supra note 13.

139 E.g., Smith v. Van Gorkum, 488 A.2d 858, 872 (Del. Ch. 1985) (“In carrying out their managerial roles, directors are charged with an unyielding fiduciary duty to the corporation and its shareholders.”); In re Caremark Int'l Inc. Derivative Litig., 698 A.2d 959, 967 (1996) (discussing fiduciary breach given reckless oversight); In re Oracle Corp. Derivative Litig., 824 A.2d 917, 936–937 (Del. Ch. 2003) (conflicts of interest); In re Walt Disney Co. Derivative Litig., 907 A.2d 693, 753 (Del. Ch. 2005) (conflicts of interest); Stone v. Ritter, 911 A.2d 362 (Del. 2006) (conflicts of interest); Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co., 493 A.2d 946, 955 (Del. 1985) (conflicts of interest).

140 Samuel L. Bray & Paul B. Miller, Against Fiduciary Constitutionalism, 106 Va. L. Rev. 1479, 1495 (2020).

141 Paul Finn, Public Trusts, Public Fiduciaries, 38 Fed. L. Rev. 335, 336 (2010).

142 E.g., Aronson v. Lewis, 473 A.3d 805 (Del. 1984); Gagliardi v. Trifoods Int'l Inc., 683 A.2d 1049 (Del. Ch. 1996); Smith v. Van Gorkom, 488 A.2d 858, 872–873 (Del. 1985). There is a notable conceptual overlap between corporation law's “business judgment” and administrative law's “policy” and “discretion,” as both are black-boxed by the courts as an area of unreviewable prerogative by legally authorized decision-makers.

143 Davis, supra note 116, at 1150.

144 Seth Davis, Pluralism and the Public Trust, in Fiduciary Government 288 (Evan J. Criddle, Evan Fox-Decent, Andrew S. Gold, Sung Kim & Paul B. Miller eds., 2018).

145 Ibid.

146 See generally, e.g., Gregory A. Elinson and Jonathan S Gould, The Politics of Deference, 75 Vanderbilt L. Rev. 475 (2022); Julian Davis Mortenson & Nicholas Bagley, Delegation at the Founding, 121 Colum. L. Rev. 277, 283–284 (2021).

147 Ibid. at 138; Klein, supra note 9, at 113; Garsten, supra note 24, at 91.

148 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 77.

149 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 141.

150 Pitkin, supra note 25, at 156–161; Mansbridge, supra note 50, at 520.

151 See, e.g., Ailsa Chang, When Lobbyists Literally Write the Bill, Nat'l Pub. Radio (Nov. 11, 2013, 2:03 PM), https://www.npr.org/sections/itsallpolitics/2013/11/11/243973620/when-lobbyists-literally-write-the-bill (describing circumstances where lobbyists write legislation); Disch, supra note 82, at 490 (de facto representation will inevitably emerge in all but the smallest of groups). See generally Theodore J. Lowi, The End of Liberalism: Ideology, Policy, and the Crisis of Public Authority (1969).

152 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan 227-28 (C.B. MacPherson ed., Penguin Books 1985) (1651); see generally Quentin Skinner, Hobbes and the Purely Artificial Person of the State, 7 J. Pol. Phil. 1, 24 (1999) (explaining the corporate conception of the state as both human and corporate (artificial) person).

153 Pitkin, supra note 25, at 19–20.

154 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 190.

155 Runciman & Vieira, supra note 32, at 78.

156 A similar logic underpins the law of private trusts in relation to irrevocable trusts. A trustee must disregard a settlor's instructions if they do not serve the beneficiary's best interests—even as the court must interpret the trust instrument according to the settlor's intentions. See, e.g., Fulp v. Gilliand, 998 N.E.2d 204 (Ind. 2013) (discussing in relation to revocable trusts).

157 Pettit, supra note 54, at 61; see also See also, e.g., Bruce Ackerman, We the People: Transformations 280–81 (1998); U.S. Const. Preamble.

158 Hobbes, supra note 155, at 227.

159 Pitkin, supra note 25 at 30–31.

160 Pitkin, supra note 25, at 43; U.S. Const, art. I, §1 (“All legislative Powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress of the United States[.]”); Wayman v. Southard, 23 U.S. 1, 42–43 (1825).

161 U.S. Const. Art. 1 §8.

162 Heath, supra note 93, at 48; see also Novak, supra note 15, at 225.

163 Novak, supra note 15, at 225.

164 Ibid. at 221.

165 Blake Emerson, Policy in the Administrative Procedure Act: Implications for Delegation, Deference, and Democracy, 97 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 113, 127 (2022).

166 Novak, supra note 15, at 226–227, 258.

167 Ibid. at 235–239; Mashaw, supra note 21, at 166; Emerson, supra note 35, at 2061; Woodrow Wilson, The Study of Administration, 2 Pol. Sci. Q. 197, 205 (1887).

168 Emerson, supra note 35, at 64.

169 Klein, supra note 9, at 128.

170 Emerson, supra note 9, at 65.

171 K. Sabeel Rahman & Hollie Russon Gilman, Civic Power: Rebuilding American Democracy in an Era of Crisis 13–16, 41–42 (2019).

172 President Biden's administration is, for example, lauded at the most diverse in history. Alana Wise, Biden Pledged Historic Cabinet Diversity. Here's How His Nominees Stack Up, NPR.org (Feb. 2, 2021).

173 5 U.S.C. §§551–559.

174 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 40.

175 Ibid., at 51–52.

176 5 U.S.C. §§556(a), 557(d).

177 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 158.

178 The presidential appointment and removal power is undergoing some flux in favor of the presidency. See, e.g., Seila Law, LLC v. Consumer Fin. Prot. Bureau, 140 S. Ct. 2183, 2203 (2020). Given the democratic benefits of congressional involvement in defining the role of the President in agency decision-making, the democratic credentials of agencies themselves, and the populist risks of a powerful presidency, I am skeptical of these changes. I am all the more skeptical because Congress often insulates agencies entrusted to regulate powerful economic and political interests—interests that might capture a presidency more easily than a Congress. A full analysis of the role the presidency in administrative decision-making is, however, outside the scope of this article.

179 Pendleton Civil Service Act, Pub. L. No. 47-27, §27, 22 Stat. 403, 403–07 (1883).

180 Pub. L. No. 95-454, 92 Stat. 1111 (1978).

181 Cordelli, supra note 8, at 99; Criddle, supra note 13, at 475.

182 15 U.S.C. §41 et seq.

183 15 U.S.C. §78a et seq.

184 J.W. Hampton, Jr. & Co. v. United States, 276 U.S. 394, 409 (1928) (laying down the intelligible principle doctrine).

185 15 U.S.C §57.

186 Chevron, U.S.A. v. Nat'l Res. Def. Council, 467 U.S. 837, 842–43 (1984).

187 Zacka, supra note 93, at 37; Heath, supra note 93, at 259; Bellamy, supra note 32, at 59.

188 Mortenson & Bagley, supra note 149, at 283–284.

189 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 70.

190 J.W. Hampton, Jr. & Co. v. United States, 276 U.S. 394 (1928) (intelligible principle); Chevron, U.S.A. v. Nat'l Res. Def. Council, 467 U.S. 837, 842–44 (1984).

191 5 U.S.C §706(2)(A).

192 Mashaw, supra note 21, at 60.

193 5 U.S.C. §§556–557.

194 Criddle, supra note 13, at 479.

195 Criddle, Evan J., Fiduciary Foundations of Administrative Law, 54 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 117, 118 (2006)Google Scholar.

196 Criddle, supra note 13, at 475.

197 12 U.S.C. §225a.

198 Emerson, supra note 168, at 126.

199 Olson, supra note 76, at 108, 122.

200 See Rucho v. Common Cause, 588 U.S. __ (2019).