Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-01T05:43:28.471Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Contractualism, exclusionary reasons and the moral argument for theism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 February 2022

Aaron Rizzieri*
Affiliation:
Department of Arts and Sciences, Coconino Community College, Flagstaff, AZ, 86001, USA

Abstract

Moral reasons take precedence over non-moral reasons either by outweighing non-moral practical reasons, or by excluding such reasons. Several prominent defenders of the moral argument for theism have incorporated the outweighing thesis. They claim we have categorically binding moral duties only if we always have most reason to be ethical. Furthermore, we always have most reason to be ethical only if theism is true. On the contrary, I argue that the excluding reasons thesis is correct and that this undermines a key premise in moral arguments developed by C. Stephen Evans, C. Stephen Layman, and William Lane Craig.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, R (1987) The Virtue of Faith and Other Essays in Philosophical Theology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Adams, R (1999) Finite and Infinite Goods. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baggett, D and Walls, JL (2019) The Moral Argument: A History. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brink, DO (1992) A puzzle about the rational authority of morality. Philosophical Perspectives 6, 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, WL and Kurtz, P (2009) The Kurtz/Craig Debate: Is Goodness Without God Good Enough? In Garcia, RK and King, NL (eds), Is Goodness Without God Good Enough? Lanham, MD: Rowan and Littlefield, pp. 25–48.Google Scholar
Craig, WL and Sinnot-Armstrong, W (2004) God?: A Debate Between a Christian and an Atheist. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S (2006) The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard university Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S (2013 a) Morality, Authority, and Law: Essays in Second Personal Ethics I. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, S (2013 b) Honor, History, and Relationship: Essays in Second Personal Ethics II. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, CS (2013) God and Moral Obligations. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P (1972) Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. The Philosophical Review 81, 303316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankena, W (1974) Sidgwick and the dualism of practical reason. The Monist 58, 449467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumerton, R (1990) Reason and Morality: A Defense of the Egocentric Perspective. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, R (1998) The Myth of Morality. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C (1996) The Sources of Normativity. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Layman, CS (2002) God and the moral order. Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers 19, 304316.Google Scholar
Layman, CS (2006) God and the moral order: replies to objections. Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers 23, 209212.Google Scholar
Layman, CS (2009) A moral argument for the existence of God. In Garcia, RK and King, NL (eds), Is Goodness Without God Good Enough? Lanham, MD: Rowan and Littlefield, pp. 4966.Google Scholar
Mackie, JL (1977) Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York, NY: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
McPherson, T (2011) Against quietist normative realism. Philosophical Studies 154, 223240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, JS (1861/2001) Utilitarianism, 2nd edn. Sher G (ed.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Miller, C (2013) Moral Character: An Empirical Theory. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, W (2012) God and the ontological foundations of morality. Religious Studies 48, 1534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D (2011) On What Matters, vol. 1. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, J (2007) The Emotional Construction of Morals. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, TM (1998) What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M (2007) Slaves of the Passions. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, M (2008) Having reasons. Philosophical Studies 139, 5771.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M (1991) The Moral Problem. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, PF (1962) Freedom and resentment. Proceeding of the British Academy 48, 125.Google Scholar
Street, S (2008) Constructivism about reasons. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 3, 207245.Google Scholar
Wallace, RJ (1994) Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wallace, RJ (2019) The Moral Nexus. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wielenberg, EJ (2014) Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B (1981) Moral Luck. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolterstorff, N (2008) Justice: Rights and Wrongs. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar