Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-19T14:19:00.447Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rationality and Presocratic cosmology in Sophocles’ Antigone

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 March 2023

Tom Mackenzie*
Affiliation:
University College London
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Scholars have occasionally noted that the Antigone’s abundant images of polar opposition bear resemblance to the fragments of Heraclitus and his doctrine of the ‘unity of opposites’. The present essay develops this comparison and explores its implications for our interpretation of the play, presenting a test case for the value of the Presocratics in the study of Attic tragedy. It argues that Heraclitus’ surviving work provides a valuable resource for elucidating the play’s ‘cosmology’, a term here used in its anthropological sense to refer to presuppositions, rather than explicitly articulated theories, concerning the structure of the universe and humanity’s place within it. This endeavour can affect our understanding of two points of intense interpretative disagreement: the rationality of the central protagonists and the role of polar oppositions in the play. A culturally sensitive evaluation of the characters’ rationality must take account of the rules of the cosmos they inhabit. The polar oppositions hint at a regular and systematic cosmology, but its finer details are ultimately kept obscure to the audience, and only Teiresias displays a substantial understanding of this underlying framework. Heraclitus thus enriches our understanding of the epistemological predicament in which the characters find themselves.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

It is the story of the clash of opposites: male versus female, age versus youth, religion versus secularism, to list but a few.Footnote 1

Wouldn’t it be liberating to live in a world in which plays that represent complex webs of human interaction were not reduced to the interplay of abstract categories?Footnote 2

I. Introduction

For many critics, the Antigone primarily concerns a conflict between opposing, mutually exclusive, abstract forces.Footnote 3 An important objection to this reading is that it tends to underestimate the complexity of Sophocles’ characterization and his finely constructed plot.Footnote 4 But if some readers have been too eager to paint the play’s events in terms of polar opposites, they take their cue from the characters themselves. Even by the standards of Classical Greek literature, Antigone’s language is rife with the imagery of oppositions.Footnote 5 It has occasionally been noted in passing that this use of imagery recalls the fragments of Heraclitus, and his notorious doctrine of the unity of opposites.Footnote 6 The present essay aims to develop this suggestion and to explore its implications for our reading of Sophocles’ play, joining a burgeoning interest in the relationship between tragedy and Presocratic philosophy.Footnote 7 Antigone can serve as a test case for the value of the Presocratics in the study of Attic tragedy. I shall argue that the context of Presocratic cosmological speculation, as manifest above all in Heraclitus, can elucidate two of Antigone’s most contested interpretative problems: the role of opposite forces, and the rationality of the protagonists. I contend that the imagery of opposites hints at an overarching cosmology that governs the world of the play, and that it is within the context of this cosmology that the rationality of the characters’ decisions should be evaluated. Before substantiating these suggestions with analysis of the evidence, it will first be necessary to clarify my use of the central terms.

II. Cosmology and rationality

Classical scholars and historians of philosophy habitually characterize the Presocratics as ‘cosmologists’ and their work as ‘cosmology’ in reference to their occupation with questions concerning the origins, structure and mechanisms of the universe, though it should be noted that the application of these terms is a modern phenomenon.Footnote 8 The usage serves to distinguish Presocratic philosophy both from what came before and from what followed. ‘Cosmology’, with its connotations of regularity and order, is often used in such a manner as to exclude the mythological stories of earlier poets.Footnote 9 At the other end of the timescale, the term has the effect of isolating Presocratic investigations from what might be termed the ‘philosophy of humanity’: according to a tradition which goes back to Plato and Xenophon, Socrates first introduced the question of how one ought to live one’s life as a topic for philosophy after growing dissatisfied with the speculations concerning the composition of the universe that had preoccupied earlier thinkers.Footnote 10 ‘Cosmology’, when used in this way, denotes both a method and a topic of enquiry, a proto-scientific investigation into the composition of the universe that assumes regularity and knowability. By contrast, and without wishing to deny the important differences between the Presocratics and earlier or later thinkers, I use ‘cosmology’ here in the much broader, anthropological sense of ‘any set of beliefs and assumptions concerning the structure of the universe and humanity’s place within it’.Footnote 11 According to this sense, Hesiod’s conception of a universe deriving from the often arbitrary sexual dalliances of anthropomorphic deities is no less a cosmology than the more regular worlds propounded by Anaximander or Empedocles. Almost any text may be used as evidence for cosmological attitudes, and such attitudes often fall under the category of the ‘philosophy of humanity’: the nature of a ‘cosmos’ may determine our obligations and the value of our actions, for instance if it features gods who are owed sacrifice and who punish impiety. Rather than treating ‘cosmology’ as a label that may or may not apply to any given text, I use it as a lens through which to read the evidence in order to bring certain aspects into focus. This approach has the advantage of facilitating comparison between the explicitly articulated cosmological views of the Presocratics and those which are presupposed in the world of a non-philosophical text such as a tragedy.

When discussing the varied evidence for cosmological attitudes within a particular culture, one can choose to stress the commonalities it presents in an attempt to identify an overarching system of popular belief, or one can choose instead to explore the distinctive features of each item, in order to interpret its significance within that context.Footnote 12 My present endeavour fits into the latter category.Footnote 13 To borrow the words of one distinguished anthropological theorist, my focus is ‘on cosmology as a living tradition of knowledge—not as a set of abstract ideas enshrined in collective representations’.Footnote 14 As far as we can tell, Antigone does not adhere doctrinally to a theory of the universe advocated by any particular cosmologist; nor does it transparently reflect the popular beliefs of Sophocles’ audience. After all, as has been widely noted, its central moral, that Polyneices should be buried, seems to run counter to contemporary Athenian legislation concerning the burial of traitors.Footnote 15 Rather, its cosmology is a unique permutation of some of the same, central components evident elsewhere in early Greek texts. Since the Presocratics present near-contemporary cosmological theories explicitly, they are a useful context against which to expose the ways in which Antigone creatively adapts existing cosmological ideas.

This approach can help to historicize the contested issue of the characters’ rationality. Scholars vehemently disagree over the extent to which we should regard the actions and self-justifications of Creon and Antigone as ‘rational’.Footnote 16 We have no reason to suspect that ancient audiences would have been any less divided than modern scholars over these points. But one difficulty for any modern attempt to reconstruct how they could have responded is the slipperiness of the vocabulary. After all, the Latinate term ‘rationality’, when applied to fifth-century Greece, is an ‘etic’ one; that is, one used by modern scholars, rather than by the culture under investigation.Footnote 17 If we are to proceed with caution, we should not assume a priori that Sophocles had a distinct concept that would map on to the modern terminology.

In English, to be rational is to possess ‘reason’ (for example, OED s.v.), but this can apply to a range of activities. As the Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy puts it:

Pieces of behaviour, beliefs, arguments, policies, and other exercises of the human mind may all be described as rational. To accept something as rational is to accept it as making sense, as appropriate, or required, or in accordance with some acknowledged goal, such as aiming at truth or aiming at the good.Footnote 18

On this basis, ‘rationality’ would appear to be the somewhat vague quality of possessing good judgement, and such a general notion is in evidence from the time of our earliest Greek texts, denoted by such vocabulary as sophia, mētis and the like. Yet those who discuss the rationality of Creon or Antigone tend to apply the term in a more restricted sense by which it refers to the quality of deriving from logical ratiocination as opposed to emotions, instincts or unwarranted presuppositions.Footnote 19 Such a conception of rationality is familiar from later philosophy, notably in Plato’s theory of a ‘rational’ (logistikon) part of the soul, distinct from more emotional, irrational part(s), which may guide or fail to guide our actions by working out syllogisms and correcting mistaken first impressions (for example, Resp. 4.439d). Some regard this conception of rationality as a philosophical construct that only emerged in the later fifth century,Footnote 20 but outside of philosophical discourse, there is good evidence for the existence in Classical Greece of a widespread vernacular notion that an individual’s deliberative faculties are distinct from their emotions, and that the former are to be valued over the latter.Footnote 21 Already in Homer, the thumos distinguishes an emotional component of the self which can recommend courses of action that are then rejected through deliberation.Footnote 22 The attempt to identify a distinction between emotionally and rationally motivated behaviour in a fifth-century tragedy, then, is historically grounded. But one must be careful with the application of this language, as what would constitute a valid process of reasoning to fifth-century Athenians may look highly irrational or illogical from a modern philosophical or scientific perspective. It is ahistorical to argue that Antigone’s concern for her brother’s burial represents irrationality in contrast to Creon’s rational arguments for civic justice simply because it derives from a belief in a supernatural framework to which modern readers would not subscribe:Footnote 23 a fifth-century Athenian audience is hardly likely to have distinguished arguments or dispositions that assume such a framework as ipso facto occupying a realm of the ‘irrational’ or failing to display sound judgement. As intellectual historians of ancient Greece have increasingly come to appreciate in recent decades, the new argumentative structures which come into view at the hands of Presocratic philosophers, Sophists, medical writers and orators, that is to say, the types of discourse which used to be taken as indicative of the triumph of ‘reason’ or logos, in no way involve a rejection of the divine.Footnote 24

Sophocles certainly presents models of deliberation and good judgement. He occasionally uses logos in cases where ‘reason’ or ‘rational reflection’ seem appropriate translations, although not in Antigone.Footnote 25 More commonly, mental actions or qualities such as gnomē, phronēma, nous and their cognates are evaluated as good or bad throughout the corpus. This is especially the case in Antigone:Footnote 26 euboulia, ‘good counsel’, is repeatedly touted as a virtue (1050, 1098), with dusboulia, ‘bad counsel’ or ‘folly’ a vice (95, 1269). I take it, then, that we can legitimately talk about a conception of ‘rationality’ within the play, provided it is understood, initially, in the somewhat vague, vernacular sense of ‘good thought’ or ‘judgement’, though I shall proceed to argue that Antigone models a more precise form of good judgement which has much in common with Heraclitus’ epistemology. Since different cultures regard different ends as ‘good’ and believe different things to be true, discussion of the rationality of characters in an ancient drama runs the risk of imposing values that would have been unfamiliar to author and audience. The evaluation of particular judgements and decisions depends on the rules of the cosmos one inhabits. A culturally sensitive analysis of the ‘rationality’ of the characters in Antigone, then, must take account of their understanding of how the play’s cosmology works.

III. The Antigone’s cosmology and the Presocratics

The Antigone presents a world in which the exposure of a corpse sets in motion a chain of causation that leads to the pollution of a city and the destruction of a family. Though the gods never appear openly onstage, the influence of supernatural forces on these events is palpable, in the guard’s report that Polyneices’ body has, miraculously, not decomposed (257–58), in the numinous whirlwind that accompanies Antigone’s return to the corpse (417–21) and in the fact that Teiresias is able to divine accurately the consequences of the exposure.Footnote 27 Furthermore, Teiresias’ comment that the city is ‘sick’ as a consequence of Creon’s decision (νοσϵῖ πόλις, 1015) may imply that it suffers some disease or pestilence, as it does in the Oedipus Tyrannus, especially given these other supernatural details.Footnote 28 But the events do not appear as a result of the capricious whim of erratic deities. This cosmos is rule-governed: Antigone famously claims that there are unwritten, divine nomima (454–55), ‘established laws’,Footnote 29 which prevail over mortal nomoi, and her claim is vindicated in the course of the narrative (cf. 1114–15). These nomima concern, at the most obvious level, the status of Polyneices’ corpse. In many respects, this cosmological framework resembles the cosmologies advanced by Heraclitus and other Presocratics, though it also presents some conspicuous points of contrast. I outline here four salient points of comparison. To be clear from the outset, I do not wish to posit that Antigone alludes directly to Heraclitus; only that it reflects certain patterns of thinking, specifically concerning rationality and cosmology, of which Heraclitus is, for us, a relatively copious and explicit source.

i. Law and justice

The emphasis on nomoi/nomima and the repeated occurrences of dikē render justice one of the play’s major themes. Its system of divine laws can determine natural phenomena, such as the pestilence in the city and the miraculous preservation of Polyneices’ corpse. Although this is an old idea, already evident in early hexameter poetry, it is expanded and developed by the Presocratics, whose treatments of the theme bear some more specific points of comparison with Antigone.

In Homer and Hesiod, dikē is a feature of relations among humans and gods. Other living things or what we would classify as inanimate objects are only incidentally involved as the instruments by which the gods reward and punish, for instance, by bringing plenteous harvests or ruinous floods.Footnote 30 With Anaximander, on the other hand, natural phenomena become agents which may themselves be guilty of injustice (D6 = B1):

The things out of which birth happens for beings, into these too their destruction happens according to obligation: for they pay the penalty (δίκην) and retribution (τίσιν) to each other for their injustice (τῆς ἀδικίας) according to the order of time.

According to the most plausible interpretation, ‘the things out of which birth happens’ are, or at least predominately comprise, opposite qualities such as the wet and the dry, the hot and the cold and so on (D12 = A13).Footnote 31 Here, dikē has the sense of ‘penalty’ or ‘retribution’.

The use of the term for a wider system of ‘cosmic justice’, involving natural phenomena as agents, comes into view in Heraclitus D63 = B80, a fragment some regard as a response to Anaximander:Footnote 32

ϵἰδέναι δὲ χρὴ τὸν πόλϵμον ἐόντα iυνόν, καὶ δίκην ἔριν, καὶ γινόμϵνα πάντα κατ’ ἔριν καὶ χρϵών.

One ought to know that war is common, and dikē strife, and all things happen [or ‘come into being’] according to strife and necessity.

Dikē is identified with ‘strife’, something according to which ‘all things happen’ or ‘come to be’. The other surviving fragments shed some light on this claim. Warfare and conflict serve as symbols for the notorious doctrine of the ‘unity of opposites’,Footnote 33 that is, ostensibly opposite items are in fact somehow unified or even identical. Thus, the ‘road up and the road down is one and the same’ (ὁδὸς ἄνω κάτω μία καὶ ὡυτή, D51 = B60) and ‘the sea is the purest and the most polluted water, drinkable and life-preserving for fish, but for humans undrinkable and destructive’ (D78 = B61). The unity of opposites is, on any account, a pervasive and central feature of Heraclitus’ cosmology. For this reason, all things ‘happen’ or ‘come to be’ in accordance with conflict qua unity of opposites, and conflict is the dikē of the cosmos. In fact, the identification of dikē with eris is itself a unity of opposites, since civic strife can be a manifestation of adikia (Solon 4.7, 32–3 W).Footnote 34 Heraclitus is able to make the paradoxical claim that ‘justice’ is ‘strife’ because of the breadth of meaning of dikē. From Homer onwards, the term can either have normative value, in the sense of ‘right’ or ‘what is fitting’ (for example, Il. 16.388, 19.180), or more neutrally refer simply to ‘custom’ or ‘usage’ (Od. 11.218, 24.225). Dikē qua justice is, by popular accord, opposed to strife, but dikē qua custom, in the broadest sense of the custom of the universe, consists of strife.

By the time of Antigone, then, the definition of dikē had become a topic of theoretical debate, one which would continue among the sophists.Footnote 35 The chorus’ conclusive remark, during the closing kommos, that Creon ‘seems to have recognized justice (τὴν δίκην) too late’ (1270), suggests that the play has provided an insight into the workings of dikē, so that it, too, can be read as a contribution to this discussion. The basic details of the narrative conform to the Homeric and Hesiodic usages of the term: natural phenomena, the pestilence in the city and the miraculous preservation of Polyneices, are the instruments of divine justice rather than agents. At no point is dikē used in the sense of an overriding system of cosmic justice that imposes obligations on inanimate objects.Footnote 36 But in two respects the treatment of justice in the play resembles that of the Presocratics rather than the earlier poets. First, both Heraclitus and Antigone regard the universe as regulated by divine law, a higher authority than mortal laws. Thus, according to Heraclitus (D105 = B114):

Those who speak with their mind must rely on what is in common for all, just as a city does on its law (νόμωι), and much more strongly [i.e. than a city]. For all human laws (πάντϵς οἱ ἀνθρώπϵιοι νόμοι) are nourished by one law, the divine one (ὑπὸ ἑνὸς τοῦ θϵίου): for it dominates as much as it wants to, and it suffices for all, and there is some left over.Footnote 37

To be sure, Heraclitus did not invent the idea of divine law. Already in Hesiod, Zeus ‘distributed laws to the immortals’ (Theog. 74). But Antigone’s stark statement of the distinction between mortal laws and divine, unwritten nomima (454–55) recalls Heraclitus’ fragment more closely than anything in Homer or Hesiod. This parallel is corroborated by the fact that both Heraclitus and Antigone present divine law as maintained by the Erinyes (D89 = B94; Soph. Ant. 603, 1075). The second respect in which Antigone’s justice resembles that of the Presocratics is in the role of opposites, which merits a more extensive discussion.

ii. Opposites and their unity

Part of the dikē that Creon must recognize requires, among other things, the appropriate arrangement of opposites. This much is suggested by Teiresias’ accusation at 1068–71:

ἔχϵις μὲν τῶν ἄνω βαλὼν κάτω,

ψυχήν τ’ ἀτίμως ἐν τάφῳ κατώικισας,

ἔχϵις δὲ τῶν κάτωθϵν ἐνθάδ’ αὖ θϵῶν

ἄμοιρον, ἀκτέριστον, ἀνόσιον νέκυν.

You have cast below one of those above,

And housed a soul dishonourably in a tomb,

And you have here, in turn, a corpse that belongs to the gods below

Without its due share, without funeral rites, unholy.

Creon’s mistake involves confusing opposite categories, in particular that which belongs above and below, a geometrical opposition that corresponds to the living and the dead. The centrality of this particular opposition is evinced both by its occurrence at this revelatory point in the drama and by the fact that it has been foreshadowed earlier on, in Haimon’s image of the unyielding steersman whose ship ends up ‘with its benches’ (the part which should be on top) ‘upside-down, underneath’ (ὑπτίοις κάτω … σέλμασιν, 716–17). In Teiresias’ speech, the opposition is emphatically illustrated by verbal antithesis (ἄνω … κάτω, τάφῳ κατώικισας, κάτωθϵν ἐνθάδ’), and by the symmetrical sentence structure, with its contrasting anaphora (ἔχϵις μὲν τῶν ἄνω … ἔχϵις δὲ τῶν κάτωθϵν). The confusion of opposites will rebound back on Creon, when he becomes, in the words of the messenger, a ‘living corpse’ (1167). The image has already been used of Antigone herself who, according to the chorus, ‘living, alone of mortals, will go down to Hades’ (821–22), and is spoken of by Creon as ‘living entombed’ (888). The fusion of life and death is also implicit in the repeated notion that Antigone’s death is a marriage, her tomb a bridal chamber (810–16, 891): she will not be going to this place for the inauguration of new life,Footnote 38 but to end her own. Of course, the application of this image to the situations of both Antigone and Creon implies that the latter is the result of the former.Footnote 39

This central opposition, between above and below, or the living and the dead, is one among many thematic oppositions that critics tend to identify within the play, such as male and female, age and youth or philoi and echthroi.Footnote 40 We are primed to identify these thematic oppositions in part by the abundant use of polar expressions, which occur in the language of all speaking characters apart from the briefly appearing Eurydice.Footnote 41 For instance, in addition to the Teiresias example quoted above, Antigone states that Ismene may be a ‘bad woman from good ancestors’ (ἐσθλῶν κακή, 38); Ismene describes Antigone as having ‘a hot heart at cold matters’ (θϵρμὴν ἐπὶ ψυχροῖσι, 88); the guard considers it ‘most pleasant’ to have escaped from ills but at the same time, ‘painful to lead friends to ill’ (ἥδιστον … ἀλγϵινόν, contrastingly placed at the start of successive lines, 438–39); Creon sees money as teaching ‘fine men to attend to shameful deeds’ (χρηστὰς πρὸς αἰσχρὰ, 299); and the chorus describes man as ‘all-inventive, uninventive at nothing that might occur’ (παντοπόρος· ἄπορος, 360) before contrasting (in the same metrical position in the subsequent antistrophe) the man who is ‘high-in-his-city’ with the one who is ‘city-less’ (ὑψίπολις· ἄπολις, 370). Expressions of this type are a familiar stylistic feature throughout Greek literature, but in this play they assume a more than rhetorical force, reflecting on a formal level the notion of polar opposition that is central to the plot. The cumulative effect of these linguistic antitheses is, I suggest, to create the impression of a world divided not only into the major thematic oppositions of philoi and echthroi or oikos and polis, but also into more mundane and physical oppositions, such as hot and cold, pleasure and pain, or up and down.

Opposition itself, then, is a major theme of the play, and if I am right in arguing that Creon’s recognition of dikē must involve a recognition of the correct arrangement of opposites, then in this respect, too, the play’s justice resembles that of the Presocratics. As we have noted, Anaximander presents opposite qualities paying penalties for acts of injustice, while the most conspicuous feature of Heraclitus’ nomoi-governed universe is the abundance of polar oppositions that are in fact somehow united in a manner that normally goes unnoticed by humanity at large. Indeed, it seems likely that Heraclitus’ ‘road’ fragment (D51 = B60, quoted above) refers not only to an actual road on a gradient, but also to the road into life on birth and the katabatic road on death: these roads are ‘the same’ since the soul enters the body on birth and departs it on death as part of the same never-ending, cyclical journey.Footnote 42 Thus, the central opposition that Creon fails to understand also crops up in Heraclitus, where ‘up’ and ‘down’, as in Antigone, correspond symbolically to the domains of the living and the dead, and, as in Antigone, there is a fusion of these two opposites. But whereas for Heraclitus the unity of opposites is an ineluctable feature of the universe (albeit one that most mortals fail to recognize), in Sophocles’ tragedy it is an indication of a perverted state of affairs and cosmic disruption. Creon’s ignorance manifests in his confusion of opposites which, in contrast to Heraclitus’ cosmos, brings extraordinary disaster.

Moreover, in both cases, the system of opposites is presented in financial terms. Heraclitus sees the change in perceptible circumstances as an exchange of money or gold (D87 = B90): ‘All things are in exchange (ἀνταμοιβή) for fire, and fire for all things, just like goods for gold and gold for goods’. Teiresias prophesies that Creon will redress the imbalance caused by his fusion of opposites by making an exchange, when declaring that ‘you will have given in exchange (ἀμοιβὸν ἀντιδοὺς ἔσῃ) one corpse for corpses’ (1066–67). This is the climax of the financial imagery that recurs throughout the play, above all in Creon’s ungrounded assumptions that his opponents act through desire for kerdos, ‘gain’ or ‘profit’ (222, 310–12, 326, 1047, 1061): Creon may be obsessed with gain, but he does not understand the real ‘balance sheet’ that underlies his actions.Footnote 43

iii. The language of the cosmos

Both Antigone and Heraclitus present sensory phenomena as a language, or at least a system of signs. In what may be Heraclitus’ most famous statement (D41 = B93), ‘the lord whose oracle is the one in Delphi neither speaks nor hides but gives signs (σημαίνϵι)’. The fragment is programmatic of Heraclitus’ notoriously ‘oracular’ style, but that style itself reflects the obscurity of the laws of his cosmology, a quality encapsulated by his use of the term logos, which seems to refer both to Heraclitus’ text and to the objective ‘account’ or rules of the cosmos.Footnote 44 Thus, people are forever uncomprehending of his account (D1 = B1) even though it is ‘common to all’ (D2 = B2). The rules of the Heraclitean cosmos, then, are figured as a kind of language which the masses do not understand. This seems to be the significance of D33 = B107: ‘Bad witnesses for humans are the eyes and ears of those who possess barbarian souls (βαρβάρους ψυχάς)’, that is, souls that do not understand Greek, or rather the ‘common tongue’ of the logos.Footnote 45 The laws of Heraclitus’ cosmos, as manifest in our sensory experience, are, for most people, like a foreign language, or like oracular utterances, in being hard to interpret. In Antigone, the prophet Teiresias is, like Heraclitus, able to understand the ‘signs’ of the cosmos: the birds have ceased to make ‘comprehensible noises’ (ϵὐσήμους … βοάς, 1021), and the rites are now ‘non-signifying’ (ἀσήμων, 1013). As Kamerbeek comments, ‘the failing of the sign is itself a sign’,Footnote 46 and Teiresias correctly infers the reasons behind this ‘failure’ of his usual means of prophecy. Both Heraclitus and Teiresias, then, are able to decode the sēmata that the cosmos presents to them.

iv. Dionysus

One final parallel is less distinctive but, I shall argue, is instructive as to how these points of similarity can affect an interpretation of the play. Both texts feature a prominent engagement with Dionysus. The god appears in three of Antigone’s choral odes.Footnote 47 First, the parodos describes Kapaneus as βακχϵύων (‘raging’, 136).Footnote 48 Its main, hymnic section closes with a call for choral celebration (152–54) and a prayer that ‘the Bacchic earth-shaker rule over Thebes’ (153–54). Second, after Antigone’s final appearance, the fourth stasimon recounts three mythological narratives in which someone is imprisoned, including the story of Lycurgus who, like Pentheus, tried to prevent the worship of Dionysus at Thrace. According to other sources, he was consequently driven mad, murdered his son (Apollod. Bibl. 3.5.1) and wife (LIMC s.v. ‘Lykourgos’), and was eventually blinded (Il. 6.130–43) or torn apart by horses (Apollod. Bibl. 3.5.1). Here, he is imprisoned in a cave (955–58; perhaps a Sophoclean invention to create a parallel with Antigone)Footnote 49 where the madness ‘drips out’ of him (959–60) before he ‘came to recognize the god, as in his madness he was violating him with his taunting tongue’.Footnote 50 Although the immediate parallel is with the imprisoned Antigone, the tradition of the filicide,Footnote 51 as well as the detail that Lycurgus ‘recognized’ the god (too late?), associate him with Creon, who achieves recognition late in the play after suffering (cf. 1095). Third, just after the exchange with Teiresias, when Creon has decided to release Antigone, in the fifth stasimon the chorus sing a kletic hymn to Dionysus in which they address him as the patron deity of Thebes (1121–25), but also as the one ‘who watches over Italy and rules in the all-receiving vales of Eleusinian Deo’ (1118–21), an address that hints at his associations both with Italian Dionysiac mystery cults and with the mysteries of Demeter and Persephone at Eleusis.Footnote 52 They then relate his peculiar birth from the union of Zeus and Semele (1126–39), and request that he come with a ‘purifying foot’ to the city afflicted with a ‘violent disease’ (1140–41). In all three instances, Dionysus is associated with madness, whether of Kapaneus (135), Lycurgus (959) or of his dancing choruses (1151): madness is a quality of both his victims and his celebrants.

One surviving fragment of Heraclitus makes explicit reference to the god (D16 = B15):

D16 = B15 ϵἰ μὴ γὰρ Διονύσωι πομπὴν ἐποιοῦντο καὶ ὕμνϵον ἆισμα αἰδοίοισιν, ἀναιδέστατα ϵἴργαστ’ ἄν· ὡυτὸς δὲ Ἀίδης καὶ Διόνυσος, ὅτϵωι μαίνονται καὶ ληναΐζουσιν.

For if they were not making a procession to Dionysus and singing a hymn to genitals [i.e., phallic images], they would be acting most shamelessly. But Hades and Dionysus are the same, him for whom they rave and celebrate the Leneia.

The fragment features a neat wordplay: people would act ἀναιδέστατα (‘most shamelessly’) by singing to αἰδοῖα, genitals, or more literally, ‘things-to-be-ashamed-at’. The aid- syllable also occurs in Hades, implicitly associating the god of death with the reproductive organs. As Kahn succinctly puts it, ‘[t]he most obviously correct interpretation takes Hades here as representative of death and the phallic Dionysus as representative of sexual vitality’.Footnote 53 The fragment, then, pronounces on the unity of life and death that we observed in other fragments (D45 = B32; D53 = B48; D68 = B88; D70 = B62). Most probably, it is critical of the traditional religious practices. Heraclitus elsewhere denounces the excessive consumption of alcohol (i.e. Dionysus’ wine, D104 = B117), which he may equate to a death of the soul.Footnote 54 This would be one reason why Dionysus/wine and Hades/death are ‘the same’ and celebrants of Dionysus are ‘mad’. Elsewhere, traditional forms of initiation and purification are faulted.Footnote 55 In D18 = B14, ‘night-wanderers, Magi, Bacchants, Maenads, and initiates … are initiated impiously into the mysteries that are recognised among men’.Footnote 56 D15 = B5 likens purification through blood to a muddy person attempting to clean himself with mud, another case of madness (μαίνϵσθαι).

Dionysus in Heraclitus, as in Antigone, is associated with madness, initiation and possibly purification. The fact that both texts feature a union of life and death may be a further Dionysiac parallel, given the god’s eschatological associations. There are some hints (but no more than that) that Dionysus may be at work in Creon’s fate:Footnote 57 his situation is comparable to that of the Dionysus-denying Lycurgus and, like Dionysus’ victims and celebrants, he is ‘mad’ (765). It is consonant with these Dionysian intimations that he comes to unite life and death as a ‘living corpse’ (1167).

IV. Cosmology, language, rationality and initiation

How, then, could these parallels affect our reading of Antigone? It might immediately be objected that they are too generic to be significant. Dikē is a prominent theme throughout Archaic and Classical Greek literature. The ‘justice of opposites’ reflects a wider tendency in Greek cosmological thought, evident also in medical and other non-philosophical sources, and so would not have called to mind Heraclitus or the Presocratics in particular. Thus, the fifth-century physician and astronomer Alcmaeon of Croton saw disease as caused by an imbalance of the opposite qualities within the body, the moist and dry, the cold and hot, the bitter and sweet, and so on (D30 = B4 = Aëtius 5.30.1). Similar theories abound in the Hippocratic corpus (for example, VM 14; De natura hominis 4).Footnote 58 These may have developed from more traditional views, such as the polar opposition between Olympian and Chthonic deities which was symbolized by the practice of sacrificing white animals to the former and black ones to the latter.Footnote 59 Moreover, the two engagements with Dionysus share features that are more widely attested in portrayals of the god: he typically brings madness (for example, Eur. Bacch. 326; Pl. Phdr. 265), and his connection with the cycle of life and death is attested in one of the mysterious bone tablets from Olbia (Orphicorum fragmenta 564–66 Bernabé), one of which is inscribed with the words ‘Death life death’, ‘Truth’, ‘Dio[nysos?]’, ‘Orphic[s?]’, and has been dated to the fifth century.Footnote 60 The fact that Heraclitus and Sophocles both refer to the god in the context of the relationship between life and death need hardly result from a direct connection, since the god more generally has eschatological associations. Nevertheless, I want to suggest that the type of cosmological speculation that Heraclitus represents can shed light on the meaning and effects of Sophocles’ drama. The basic fact that there is this particular confluence of various points of similarity is noteworthy; not all Archaic or Classical Greek texts display these different features (contrast genres such as iambic, comedy or rhetoric). The comparison exposes the way in which the play touches on cosmological questions that had been explicitly addressed by thinkers such as Heraclitus, concerning the wider unseen forces that frame both human behaviour and the natural world.

More specifically, the parallels with Heraclitus, when bolstered by other contextual evidence, have some implications for our interpretation of Sophocles’ language and of the model of rationality Antigone propounds. I have argued that both Heraclitus and Sophocles present sensory phenomena as a kind of language or semiotic system. For Heraclitus, this ‘cosmic’ language is also evident in normal human speech. Names express only one side to the coin, one opposite that is in fact somehow unified with its converse. The bow’s name, bios, hints at life, but its function is death (D53 = B48). One wise thing ‘is both willing and unwilling to be spoken of by the name of Zeus’ (οὐκ ἐθέλϵι καὶ ἐθέλϵι Ζηνὸς ὄνομα, D45 = B32), probably because Zeus signifies life, an entity that, for Heraclitus, is indissolubly connected to its opposite, death (cf. D68 = B88; D70 = B62).Footnote 61

Language, for Heraclitus, is thus a natural phenomenon that warrants the same sort of analysis as other sensory experience (cf. also D55 = B23). In Antigone, there are grounds for suspecting that the ‘language’ or ‘signs’ of the cosmos are also manifest in the actual language of the characters. Teiresias ‘reads’ the behaviour of birds, but the imagery of bird cries has occurred elsewhere: the chorus compare Polyneices to an eagle (112) and, in the famous first stasimon, celebrate humanity’s ability to hunt birds (342); the guard likens Antigone’s cry on discovering the uncovered Polyneices (424–28) to that of a bird. It is a truism of Sophoclean criticism that his characters are often unaware of the full significance of their speech.Footnote 62 Thus, the chorus and the guard do not realize that their language, along with that of Teiresias, forms part of a pattern of imagery which hints at a web of causation linking Polyneices’ invasion, Antigone’s burial and the pollution of Teiresias’ altar. A further respect in which Antigone’s characters conform to this principle is in their use of oppositions and antitheses that hint at a world structured by polar opposites. Language, in this play, reveals the workings of the cosmos, even unbeknownst to its speakers. In both Heraclitus’ cosmos and the world of Sophocles’ play, mortal language, if interpreted correctly, reveals something about the underlying structure of the universe, even though its speakers may be unaware of the fact. In this respect, the parallel of Heraclitus provides an insight into the use of dramatic irony in the play, one of the most widely celebrated features of Sophoclean dramatic technique: it is not simply an artificial dramatic device, but a function of a particular cosmological outlook.

If this analysis is along the right lines, then Antigone, like Heraclitus, presents a world in which rationality consists of an understanding of the underlying cosmic framework, one which is generally unknown to mortals but can be manifest in their language. Teiresias, who values euboulia above all other possessions (1050), is the one character who conspicuously displays this quality. Unlike Aeschylus’ Cassandra, his powers of divination do not consist in divine rapture, but are a result of his ‘skill’, technē (998), which enables him, like Heraclitus, to decode the signs of the cosmos and live in accordance with its rules. His ‘good judgement’ does not consist in logical deduction or, unlike some Classical Greek texts, in command of his emotions (note his anger at 1064–90). His model of wisdom contrasts pointedly with that presented in the first stasimon (332–75), which extols the practical skills of hunting animals and governing cities. Such skills seem insufficient in light of the play’s course of events, which implies that our actions have a deeper significance. Polyneices’ exposure is not only wrong because it brings personal dishonour to Antigone and her family; it has physical consequences (the crying of the birds at 1001–04; the failure of the altars to ignite at 1005–13; the sickness of the city at 1015) that are governed by the rules of the cosmos into which Teiresias has some insight.

The references to Dionysus are also suggestive of this model of rationality. This is above all evident from his appearance in the fifth stasimon, where we noted that his address as the one ‘who watches over Italy and rules in the all-receiving vales of Eleusinian Deo’ (1118–21) calls to mind his associations with Italian and Eleusinian mysteries. Mystic initiates are often characterized as those who ‘know’,Footnote 63 and appear as privy to cosmological knowledge that remains hidden to the uninitiated. Among other examples, this tendency is most conspicuous from the Derveni papyrus, whose author wrote an explanation of the hidden meanings of an Orphic theogony, probably as a means to provide a ‘true’ initiation in competition against the other initiators he rails against (col. XX).Footnote 64 The association between mystic initiation and wider theogonical/cosmological explanation is one reason why Heraclitus singles out mystic initiates for criticism when promoting his own cosmology, and also why Parmenides and Empedocles use initiation as a metaphor for the process of getting to understand their explanations of the world.Footnote 65

In Antigone, the cosmological associations of Dionysiac initiation are activated by the description of the god ‘leading a chorus of fire-breathing stars’ (1146–47), as if he governs the movement of the constellations and the cycle of the seasons.Footnote 66 There are even indications that the acquisition of cosmological knowledge is a form of initiation, in particular concerning Creon’s education. The chorus express reluctance to state openly that Creon himself has made a mistake with the conditional, ‘if it is right to speak’ (ϵἰ θέμις ϵἰπϵῖν, 1259), a locution that recalls the formulaic preface for speech that was reserved for the initiated: ‘I will speak to those for whom it is right’ (φθέγiομαι οἷς θέμις ἐστί).Footnote 67 The quality of Creon’s actions thus takes on the status of a truth preserved for initiates. Creon himself, in the process of discovering the misguided nature of his actions, undergoes a kind of initiation: like initiates of various kinds, including those at Eleusis, he has to enter a cavernous space to acquire a life-changing revelation.Footnote 68 Only, instead of encountering the goddess Persephone/Kore,Footnote 69 he finds the mortal Antigone who, in being ‘married’ to an underworld deity (816), has taken on Persephone’s role in perverse fashion.Footnote 70 Like an initiate, Creon acquires knowledge, but it is the terrible realization that he is responsible for his son’s death. Appropriately for this initiatory framework, Dionysus may indeed bring a ‘purification’, just as the Chorus request (1144), but this is a purification in blood.Footnote 71 Creon, like the initiates, and like the students of Parmenides and Empedocles, gains cosmological insight concerning the distinction between the realm of the living and the realm of the dead, but unlike them he does so at immense personal expense.

How, then, does Antigone herself stack up against this model? She is proven right in her judgement of the situation, but her judgement is an intuitive one, and she expresses uncertainty as to whether it is correct (521, 925–28). In a speech that has seemed most problematic to scholars, she claims at 905–15 that she would not have disobeyed Creon’s edict for a child or a husband, since she could find another husband or conceive another child, but that, with her parents deceased, she could have no other brother (909–10).Footnote 72 Some have argued that this speech conflicts with her previous assertions that she buried Polyneices in order to obey divine laws (especially 450–60, 519; cf. 24, 74, 77), thereby betraying her true motivation: her emotional attachment to her brother. On this interpretation, it is an irrational, post hoc attempt to justify her burial of Polyneices.Footnote 73 However, as Foley has pointed out, obedience to divine laws does not conflict with, and may consist in, the personal commitment to bury Polyneices, and Antigone may stress different (though equally valid) reasons to different addressees for rhetorical purposes.Footnote 74 Of course, part of the point of the passage may be to raise precisely these questions, to prompt discussion of Antigone’s motivations and whether they constitute good judgement. I want to propose that one of the ways in which it does this is by situating her scenario within a wider cosmological framework. Like Intaphrenes’ wife in Herodotus’ account (3.119), which this speech closely resembles and to which it may allude,Footnote 75 Antigone provides an impressive argument, appealing to principles that had not been taken into consideration by her male addressees. Her speech reveals that she values the maintenance of a certain cosmic balance: her children or her husband would be replaceable (909–10), but her brother cannot be replaced and therefore must be buried in the appropriate manner. The tacit premise is that the irreplaceable dead must be placed where they belong. What matters is not the individual, whether, say, Antigone was particularly fond of Polyneices or her putative son, but his place in the family structure. To this extent, she shows an awareness that her actions are enmeshed within a wider cosmic framework.

However, the play does not supply an obvious answer to the major questions her speech raises, of whether, if this were a husband or child, she would lack equivalent obligations, or, more generally, whether a woman’s loyalty rests with her natal or her marital family.Footnote 76 She provides a glimpse of an overarching cosmology, but without elaborating or elucidating it. In fact, the details of the play’s cosmology are, like that of Heraclitus, hard to grasp: aside from the basic point that even the corpses of traitors deserve burial, a point which is not immediately obvious and only emerges through the course of the drama, its details are kept obscure to the audience. Antigone’s speech is one component, along with the patterns of imagery and linguistic antitheses, that conveys the suggestion of a coherent cosmological framework underlying the events of the play, a framework which would allow the characters to evaluate their actions successfully, if only they had access to it. The long-standing view that Creon and Antigone represent, respectively, the polis and oikos, may fail to do justice to the complexity of two fully fleshed-out individuals who are entangled in a complex web of relationships and competing responsibilities; this is not simply ‘the story of the clash of opposites: male versus female, age versus youth, religion versus secularism’.Footnote 77 Yet the characters inhabit a world that appears to be governed by such opposing forces as had been shaped neatly into coherent cosmologies by Heraclitus and other near-contemporary thinkers. The play does not offer an explicit and readily comprehensible cosmological system to compete with those of the Presocratics, but it tantalizes us with the possibility of one, an understanding of the workings of the universe and the repercussions of our actions that is always just beyond our grasp.

V. Conclusion

Adopting an anthropological conception of cosmology, I have tried to demonstrate some of the benefits of reading Attic tragedy against the context of the Presocratics. I have refrained from the traditional intertextual approach of hunting for allusions to, or direct influences of, particular theories, since such points of contact are usually very hard to verify.Footnote 78 Instead, my contention is that the Presocratics are a valuable context because they provide explicitly articulated theories of cosmology and epistemology that emerge from roughly the same cultural context as fifth-century Athens. They can therefore throw into relief some of the ways in which this particular Sophoclean tragedy hints at an overarching cosmology, and can flesh out our understanding of the predicaments in which the characters find themselves. According to both Heraclitus and the Antigone, there is a systematic, overarching cosmological framework that is manifest in sensory phenomena, and against which mortal actions should be evaluated. In both cases, this is a framework that is hard for the masses to comprehend, and consequently mortals fall into folly. But there is an important, general contrast in the way this folly is treated. Heraclitus shows utter contempt for mortals’ inability to grasp the overarching framework (for example, D1 = B1, D2 < B2, D3 = B17, D4 = B34, D5 = B19): they are ‘uncomprehending when they have heard, like deaf people’ (D4 = B34) and their opinions are ‘children’s toys’ (D6 < B70). Sophocles, however, in giving voice to one who, disastrously, only comes to a late and partial cosmological understanding, provokes sympathy. Though Creon is in an extraordinary situation, as the head of a household with responsibilities for his dependants, he is more of an ‘everyman’ than the hermitic Teiresias. Part of the force of the play, then, is in revealing how our cosmological convictions may fail, with disastrous consequences, to accord with the wider principles of the cosmos. If tragedy does indeed elicit sympathy for characters in such situations as we might find ourselves, then in Creon’s case, this is not because we might actually make an authoritarian edict that turns out to have disastrous consequences, nor because we may unwittingly irritate the gods and suffer their punishment; it is rather that we recognize what it is like to have our once firmly held assumptions retrospectively proven false or inadequate by the course of events. Antigone is not only ‘philosophical’ in the ethical problems it poses; it shares with the Presocratics an epistemological and metaphysical concern for the gap between being and seeming.

Acknowledgements

This essay has developed from ideas first presented as a pre-performance lecture for UCL’s 2017 undergraduate production of Antigone, and then at a 2018 conference at Agnes Scott College, Philosophy beyond the Philosophers, organized by Scarlett Kingsley, Harald Thorsrud and Joshua Billings. I am immensely grateful to both audiences for stimulating questions and criticisms. I am also indebted to Fiachra Mac Góráin for astute comments on an earlier draft of the written version, and to JHS’s editor and two anonymous reviewers. Remaining failings are mine alone.

Footnotes

2 Heath (Reference Heath2018) 244.

3 This position can be traced back to Hegel’s view that the tragedy is a conflict of polis and oikos (Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion 2.3; Lectures on Aesthetics 2.2). Scholars have often endorsed Hegel’s view (for example, Knox (Reference Knox1964) 62–90; Reinhardt (Reference Reinhardt1979) 65–66; Winnington-Ingram (Reference Winnington-Ingram1980) 119–20; Liapis (Reference Liapis and Cairns2013) 107) or seen the play more generally as presenting, in some form, a conflict between abstract oppositions (Segal (Reference Segal1981) 152–206; Goldhill (Reference Goldhill1986), 79–106; Griffith (Reference Griffith1999) 43–54; Stuttard (Reference Stuttard and Stuttard2017) 1). The idea that Greek tragedy in general consists of conflicts and exchanges between opposites was influentially articulated by Vernant in Vernant and Vidal-Naquet (Reference Vernant and Vidal-Naquet1988) 23–48 (originally published 1972). As Cairns (Reference Cairns2016) 124–27 shows, Hegel’s views were more complex than is usually acknowledged.

4 Hester (Reference Hester1971) 14–17; Sourvinou-Inwood (Reference Sourvinou-Inwood1989) 139–40; Cairns (Reference Cairns2016), 111–13; Heath (Reference Heath2018) 244. Foley (Reference Foley2001) 172–200 tends in this direction.

5 On Greek polar expressions, see Kemmer (Reference Kemmer1903). On the figure in tragedy, see Rutherford (Reference Rutherford2012) 74, 207, 388, 389, 391. On the polar oppositions in Antigone, see section III.ii.

6 Seaford (Reference Seaford2004) 312; Seaford (Reference Seaford2012) 331; Cairns (Reference Cairns and Cairns2013) xxxvi–xxxvii. From the other direction, Granger (Reference Granger, Sider and Obbink2013) 188–89, on Heraclitus, briefly draws the contrast between D119 = B96 and the plot of the play.

7 Crucial, here, is the work of Richard Seaford (Reference Seaford2003), (Reference Seaford2004), (Reference Seaford2012), though I do not share his strongly Marxist framework that leads him to posit a close connection between Presocratic philosophy and monetization. See also Scapin (Reference Scapin2020) and the overview of Allan (Reference Allan and Gregory2007). For an early, and somewhat sceptical, contribution, see Rösler (Reference Rösler1970). On Sophocles in particular, see Arp (Reference Arp2006).

8 For example, Kahn (Reference Kahn1960); Furley (Reference Furley1987); Lloyd (Reference Lloyd1991). Ion of Chios is credited with writing a work entitled Κοσμολογικός (schol. ad Ar. Pax 835) and Democritus, according to Diogenes Laertius (9.46), wrote a Κοσμογραφίη, but no such word as *κοσμολογία is attested in ancient or Byzantine Greek, nor does *cosmologia appear in any of the classical, medieval or Renaissance Latin dictionaries. The earliest English examples provided by the OED date to the 17th century.

9 Lloyd (Reference Lloyd1991) 146, ‘in Greece, there is nothing we can describe as cosmology in the strictest and fullest sense before the philosophers’. Note also Kahn (Reference Kahn1960) 94–98, 133–63. Furley’s The Greek Cosmologists opens its cosmological narrative with the Milesians.

10 For example, Pl. Ap. 19a8–d7, Phd. 96a5–100e4; Xen. Mem. 1.1.11; Diog. Laert. 1.18, 2.16, 2.20–22; Cic. Tusc. 5.10–11. On this tradition in both antiquity and modernity, see Laks (Reference Laks2018) 1–34, who refers to it as the ‘philosophy of man’.

11 For the recent resurgence of the term in anthropology, see the collection Abramson and Holbraad (Reference Abramson and Holbraad2014) and the overview, Abramson (Reference Abramson and Callan2018). For the most sustained application of this concept to Antigone, see Oudemans and Lardinois (Reference Oudemans and Lardinois1987), though I differ from them in regarding the Antigone not as a product of a largely static Greek cosmology, but as a dynamic intervention within a complex contemporary cosmological discourse. Derron (Reference Derron2015) applies a broad sense of the term to the ancient world.

12 On this distinction, see Barth (Reference Barth1987). It is far beyond the scope of this article to determine the precise extent to which we can identify a level of systematicity in Greek religious beliefs, but on this issue see Versnel (Reference Versnel2011) 23–150.

13 In this respect, I differ from Oudemans and Lardinois (Reference Oudemans and Lardinois1987), who regard Antigone as ‘a typical product of Greek culture in that it is permeated with dichotomies and structural polarities’ (pp. 13–14). I aim to be more precise in investigating the use Sophocles makes of such ‘dichotomies and structural polarities’.

14 Barth (Reference Barth1987) 84. As he later writes, ‘creativity can only be understood as an interaction between the parts of a dynamic system; and nothing can be expected to spring ready-made from the forehead of the philosopher’ (p. 87), or, in my case, playwright. In this respect I differ from the heavily structuralist approach of Segal (Reference Segal1981).

15 For a full discussion of this issue, see Cerri (Reference Cerri1979) 17–32. This point forms the basis of Sourvinou-Inwood’s (Reference Sourvinou-Inwood1989) argument that Creon’s exposure of Polyneices would not be regarded as wrong by the audience. As Cairns (Reference Cairns2016) 38–44 argues, the audience is unlikely to have been unanimous on this issue.

16 For example, Blundell (Reference Blundell1989) 130–48 sees passion overriding reason in both Creon and Antigone. Nussbaum (Reference Nussbaum2001) 51–82 argues that both Creon and Antigone display defective powers of practical reasoning. Foley (Reference Foley2001) 172–83 defends Antigone’s rationality. Most recently, Scodel (Reference Scodel and Stuttard2017) has applied ‘attribution theory’ to argue that Antigone presents herself as rational to her addressees, though Scodel does not commit herself to a position on whether Antigone is actually rational. Segal (Reference Segal1981) 152–206 argues that Creon represents (ultimately inadequate) masculine rationality against Antigone’s feminine religion.

17 The anthropological terms ‘etic’ and its antonym ‘emic’ were coined by Kenneth Pike in 1954. See further Harris (Reference Harris1976) and the methodological discussion of Geertz (Reference Geertz, Schweder and Levine1984). For discussion of the cultural contingency of conceptions rationality, see, within Classics, Lloyd (Reference Lloyd1990) and Frede (Reference Frede, Frede and Striker1996); in anthropology more generally, Tambiah (Reference Tambiah1990); and in intellectual history, most recently, Smith (Reference Smith2019).

18 Blackburn (Reference Blackburn2016) s.v.

19 See n.16.

20 Explicitly, Frede (Reference Frede, Frede and Striker1996) 5–19. Long (Reference Long, Frede and Reis2009) sees Heraclitus as playing a crucial role in the articulation of the concept of rationality. The view that ‘reason’ only emerged in sixth- or fifth-century Greece was a cornerstone of the now-debunked scholarly narrative of a steady progression from ‘muthos to logos’, that is, from mythological to rational forms of explanation, propounded by Nestle (Reference Nestle1942), Snell (Reference Snell1953) and Fränkel (Reference Fränkel1975); for criticisms, see Buxton (Reference Buxton1999) and for a recent reassessment of the terms muthos and logos, see Fowler (Reference Fowler2011).

21 Dover (Reference Dover1974) 116–26 discusses vernacular conceptions of practical reasoning in Classical Athens. For emotions defeating good judgement, note Antiph. 5.71; Lys. 3.4, 31; Isoc. 15.221; Isae. 1.13; Dem. 45.14.

22 Il. 11.401–13, 17.90–107, 21.552–72, 22.98–131. Note also instances in which a hero ‘yields’ to his thumos in spite of good advice to the contrary: Il. 9.109–11, 24.40–42. On this much-discussed topic see, especially, Gill (Reference Gill1996) 46–60 and Cairns (Reference Cairns2014) §3.2, who discusses earlier scholarship.

23 Thus, Segal (Reference Segal1981) 152–206.

24 See, in general Lloyd (Reference Lloyd1987), and on the Presocratics in particular, Broadie (Reference Broadie and Long1999); Trépanier (Reference Trépanier, Erskine and Bremmer2010); Tor (Reference Tor2017), although note already Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1947).

25 Note El. 466, and the related sense of ‘value’ or ‘price’ at Aj. 477 and OC 1163. One potential instance in Antigone is 603, where the chorus mention λόγου τ’ ἄνοια καὶ φρϵνῶν Ἐρινύς as a cause of the destruction of the house of the Labdacids, but there commentators are unanimous in regarding the first part of the expression as referring to the ‘madness’ of someone’s (probably Antigone’s) ‘speech’. See, for example, Jebb (Reference Jebb1900) ad loc.; Long (Reference Long1968) 109; Griffith (Reference Griffith1999) ad loc.; Cairns (Reference Cairns2016) 69. The absence of any clear instance of logos in the sense of ‘reason’ undermines the suggestion of Segal (Reference Segal1981) 165 that logos conflicts with muthos in the play.

26 The examples are ubiquitous. For analysis, see Long (Reference Long1968) 49–54, 82–86.

27 Cf. the similar remarks of Parker (Reference Parker1983) 33.

28 Scullion (Reference Scullion1998) 114–22 argues that this ‘sickness’ refers specifically to a wider ‘mental distress’ that afflicts the city, but this seems to me too restrictive: the nature of the sickness is ominously unspecified, and we are left to ponder what wider repercussions the exposure and Antigone’s execution may engender. Creon’s pointedly mistaken understanding of miasma (776, 1042–43) may further lead us to speculate whether the nosos he causes is a physical disease.

29 On this term, see Griffith (Reference Griffith1999) ad loc. Knox (Reference Knox1964) 97 argues that nomima means ‘customary rites’ rather than ‘laws’, but whilst the distinction between nomima and nomoi seems significant here, the former evidently conveyed legal implications to Aristotle (Rh. 137b4–11).

30 For example, the locus classicus, Il. 16.384–93; Hes. Op. 225–47. Note that at Op. 276–79 there is no justice among animals.

31 See, for example, Vlastos (Reference Vlastos1947) 168–72; Kahn (Reference Kahn1960) 119–66; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 119–20, 128–30; Graham (Reference Graham2006) 39–44.

32 Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 207; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 194; Scapin (Reference Scapin2020) 134. On this development in the use of the term, see Vlastos (Reference Vlastos1947) and Havelock (Reference Havelock1978) 263–71.

33 Thus, Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 206; Graham (Reference Graham2006) 144 (who sees it as an ‘exchange’ rather than a unity of opposites); Scapin (Reference Scapin2020) 133.

34 This particular unity of opposites also emerges from D55 = B23, ‘they would not know the name of justice (ίκης ὄνομα) if these things were not’. As Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 185 argues, ‘these things’ are probably ‘unjust things’, so that knowledge of the name of justice depends upon the existence of injustice.

35 Note, for example, Antiphon D38 = B44 and the debates with Thrasymachus and Callicles reimagined by Plato in Republic book 1 and the Gorgias.

36 The word occurs ten times in the play: three times in the δίκην διδόναι idiom (228, 303, 459); twice in reference to the ‘dikē of the gods’ from which one may depart (368, 921); twice in the dative in the sense of ‘with dikē’ or ‘rightly’ (23, assuming Schütz’s emendation for the sense, and 94); once with the connotation of ‘legal dispute’ (742 with Griffith (Reference Griffith1999) ad loc.; cf. T.6.60); once, personified (854, the ‘pedestal’ or ‘throne of Dike’); and finally the dikē that Creon recognizes (1270).

37 Tr. Laks and Most (Reference Laks and Most2016).

38 The recognized function of marriage, as is clear from the betrothal formula, is that the bride is given ‘for the bearing [literally, “ploughing”] of lawful children’ (Men. Sam. 727, Pk. 1010, Dys. 842, fr. 682).

39 Thus, Knox (Reference Knox1964) 116; Oudemans and Lardinois (Reference Oudemans and Lardinois1987) 197–98.

40 In addition to the quotation at the start of this essay, see the representative overview of Griffith (Reference Griffith1999) 43–54. On philoi and echthroi, see Goldhill (Reference Goldhill1986) 79–106; Blundell (Reference Blundell1989), 106–15; and Nussbaum (Reference Nussbaum2001) 54–55.

41 The section above documents examples spoken by Antigone, Ismene, Creon, Teiresias and the Chorus, but note also, for example, 232, 276, 438–39 spoken by the Guard; 695, 731, perhaps 757 spoken by Haimon; 1157, 1158, 1159 spoken by the Messenger.

42 Thus Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 240. This interpretation of the fragment goes back at least as far as Plotinus (4.8.1.11–18 = R88). Cf. Pl. Grg. 493a for ἄνω κάτω in reference to the journey of the soul.

43 Cf. Antigone’s appropriation of the word at 462–64, and the Chorus’ ironic comment at 1326. On the significance of kerdos in the play, see Goheen (Reference Goheen1951) 14–19; Segal (Reference Segal1964) 48.

44 On this, see Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 96–100.

45 For this interpretation, see Hussey (Reference Hussey, Schofield and Nussbaum1982) and Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) ad loc. Cf. also D4 = B34, D22 = B56.

46 Kamerbeek (Reference Kamerbeek1978) ad loc.

47 On Dionysus in these odes, see Winnington-Ingram (Reference Winnington-Ingram1980) 91–116; Bierl (Reference Bierl1989); and Henrichs (Reference Henrichs1994) 75–79. On the fifth stasimon, a kletic hymn to the god, see Henrichs (Reference Henrichs, Mastronarde and Griffith1990) 265–70; Scullion (Reference Scullion1998); Cullyer (Reference Cullyer2005); Macedo (Reference Macedo2011).

48 Griffiths (Reference Griffith1999) ad loc. glosses as ‘“raging”, here, as often, with no specifically Dionysiac reference’, but this seems reductive given that Dionysus crops up at the end of the ode, as the ‘Bacchic earth-shaker’.

49 Thus, Gantz (Reference Gantz1993) 113.

50 Translation here adapted from the interpretation of Griffiths (Reference Griffith1999) ad loc.

51 Winnington-Ingram (Reference Winnington-Ingram1980) 102–03.

52 As Griffith (Reference Griffith1999) 318–19 notes. On the relationship between this passage and Eleusinian ritual, see Seaford (Reference Seaford1994a) 381–82. On ‘salvationist’ mystery cults in Magna Graecia, see Henrichs (Reference Henrichs, Mastronarde and Griffith1990) 267–69; Parker (Reference Parker and Powell1995); and Casadio and Johnston (Reference Casadio and Johnston2009). Though there appears to have been no specific cult of Dionysus at Eleusis, aspects of divinity associated with him (Zagreus, Iakchos, Orpheus) are prominent. See Burkert (Reference Burkert1985) 287, 296–300; Graf (Reference Graf1974) 46–69.

53 Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 264.

54 This equation is made explicit if we accept either Diels’ or Kranz’s proposed emendations for D101 = B77. In any case it seems implicit in D100 = B36, whilst D103 = B118 states that ‘a dry soul [i.e. not drunk], wisest and best’. In favour of this interpretation, see Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 264; Granger (Reference Granger, Sider and Obbink2013) 190.

55 Most (Reference Most2013) discusses Heraclitus on religion and provides a critical overview of earlier interpretations.

56 Text and tr. here from Laks and Most (Reference Laks and Most2016). For discussion of the fragment, see Most (Reference Most2013) 160–61.

57 Pace Scullion (Reference Scullion1998) 119, the claim that ‘nothing in the text suggests that Dionysos is in any way interested or involved in what is happening’ seems to me to place too-stringent conditions on what would have to ‘suggest’ a god’s involvement in a Sophoclean tragedy. On Dionysus in the odes, see further Winnington-Ingram (Reference Winnington-Ingram1980) 91–116.

58 See further Lloyd (Reference Lloyd1966), 20–24.

59 See Burkert (Reference Burkert1985) 199–200, and also, on Greek religious polar oppositions more generally, Lloyd (Reference Lloyd1966) 41–48.

60 On the bone tablets, first published in 1978, see M. West (Reference West1983) 17–18, 19 fig. 1, pl. 1.

61 Note the etymological play with the old poetic form Ζηνός recalling its folk etymology with the verb ζῆν, ‘to live’ (cf. Aesch. Supp. 584–85; Pl. Cra. 396a7). See Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 270–71 and Tor (Reference Tor2017) 103–04.

62 Cf. Winnington-Ingram (Reference Winnington-Ingram1980) 97: ‘it is characteristic of the odes of this play that they tend, ironically, to carry a secondary reference to Creon which cannot be in the minds of the singers’.

63 Initiates as those ‘who know’ or ‘understand’: Pind. fr. 137; Eur. Bacch. 73; Thuc. 3.53.4; Orphicorum fragmenta 1a Bernabé.

64 For this communis opinio, see Betegh (Reference Betegh2004) 349–72; Graf (Reference Graf, Papadopoulou and Muellner2014); and, now, Piano (Reference Piano2016) 107–11. For alternative (and to my mind less persuasive) views, see Janko (Reference Janko1997) and Kouremenos et al. (Reference Kouremenos, Parássoglou and Tsantsanoglou2006) 52–59. For other instances where initiation seems to involve the acquisition of cosmological/theogonical knowledge, see, on the ‘Orphic’ gold tablets, Bernabé and Jiménez San Cristóbal (Reference Bernabé and Jiménez San Cristóbal2008) 41–42 and Graf and Johnston (Reference Graf and Johnston2013) 113–14; and the explanations of Eleusinian initiation espoused, for instance, by Richardson (Reference Richardson1974) 24–28 and Bremmer (Reference Bremmer2014) 11–16.

65 On the initiatory language in Parmenides’ proem (D4 = B1), see Burkert (Reference Burkert1969) especially 3–5; on Empedocles D257 = B110, see Willi (Reference Willi2008) 236–37. For Empedocles’ connections to Orphic-Bacchic mystery cult more generally, see Riedweg (Reference Riedweg1995) and Rodríguez (Reference Rodríguez2005).

66 According to a scholiast ad loc., he is called chorus-leader of the stars ‘according to a mystic formula (μυστικὸν λόγον)’.

67 Orphicorum fragmenta 1b Bernabé, with similar expressions at Empedocles D44 = B3.4; Eur. Bacch. 474. For further allusions to Eleusinian ritual at this point in the play, see Seaford (Reference Seaford1990) 87–89 and (Reference Seaford1994a) 381–82. On Sophocles and mystery cult more generally, see Seaford (Reference Seaford1994b).

68 See Ustinova (Reference Ustinova2009) especially 232–55. At Eleusis the appearance of Persephone seems to have been staged in the cave.

69 For the process of initiation at Eleusis, involving a blindfolded search for Persephone and her ultimate appearance, see Clinton (Reference Clinton and Cosmopoulos2003) and Bremmer (Reference Bremmer2014) 1–20.

70 Goldhill (Reference Goldhill1986) 102.

71 As Oudemans and Lardinois (Reference Oudemans and Lardinois1987) 159 and Bierl (Reference Bierl1989) argue, pace Henrichs (Reference Henrichs, Mastronarde and Griffith1990) 264–69 and (Reference Henrichs1994) 77; Scullion (Reference Scullion1998) persuasively argues that Dionysus’ ‘purificatory foot’ refers to ritual dancing, a homeopathic cure for madness, but we need not deny further connotations to this highly charged term, and its proximity to an Eleusinian reference is suggestive of the purificatory rituals in initiation ceremonies, for which see Bremmer (Reference Bremmer2014) 5 and note, for example, Pl. Resp. 2.364b2–365a3, and the ‘pure from the pure’ expression in some of the gold tablets, OF 488–49.

72 I follow the recent consensus that these lines are genuine, and not a later interpolation, as has sometimes been thought (for example, Winnington-Ingram (Reference Winnington-Ingram1980) 145). In their favour, see Griffith (Reference Griffith1999) ad loc.

73 Thus, Blundell (Reference Blundell1989) 134; Garvie (Reference Garvie and Stuttard2017) 20–21. See also n.13 above.

74 Foley (Reference Foley2001) 172–83.

75 On this issue, see the full discussion of West (Reference West and Griffin1999).

76 For Foley (Reference Foley2001) 179, Antigone’s argument ‘relies on the point that there is no other family member left to perform obligations for her blood kin’, but if that is so, it is not a point she makes explicitly. For further criticism of Foley’s interpretation, see Trapp (Reference Trapp and Silk1996).

78 Contrast the intertextual approach of Arp (Reference Arp2006), and the focus of Allan (Reference Allan and Gregory2007) on ‘the influence of early Greek philosophical thought on tragedy’ (p. 71). Whilst such an influence can hardly be doubted, it is hard to pinpoint with much precision. For the possibility that Heraclitus influenced Philoctetes, see Goldhill (Reference Goldhill2012) 34 n.45.

References

Abramson, A. (2018) ‘Cosmologies’, in Callan, H. (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Anthropology (Hoboken) https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781118924396.wbiea2223 Google Scholar
Abramson, A. and Holbraad, M. (eds) (2014). Framing Cosmologies (Manchester)Google Scholar
Allan, W. (2007) ‘Tragedy and the early Greek philosophical tradition’, in Gregory, J. (ed.), A Companion to Greek Tragedy (Oxford and Malden) 7182 Google Scholar
Arp, M.J. (2006) Pre-Socratic Thought in Sophoclean Tragedy (Ph.D. Diss. University of Pennsylvania)Google Scholar
Barth, F. (1987) Cosmologies in the Making: A Generative Approach to Cultural Variation in Inner New Guinea (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511607707CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernabé, A. and Jiménez San Cristóbal, A.I. (2008) Instructions for the Netherworld: The Orphic Gold Tablets (Leiden)Google Scholar
Betegh, G. (2004) The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511584435CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bierl, A. (1989) ‘Was hat Tragödie mit Dionysos zu tun? Rolle und Funktion des Dionysos am Beispiel der “Antigone” des Sophocles’, WJA 15, 4358 Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. (2016) The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (3rd edition) (Oxford)10.1093/acref/9780198735304.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blundell, M.W. (1989) Helping Friends and Harming Enemies: A Study in Sophocles and Greek Ethics (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511586170CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bremmer, J. (2014) Initiation into the Mysteries of the Ancient World (Berlin)10.1515/9783110299557CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. (1999) ‘Rational theology’, in Long, A.A. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge) 205–2410.1017/CCOL0521441226.010CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burkert, W. (1969) ‘Das Proömium des Parmenides und die Katabasis des Pythagoras’. Phronesis 14, 130 Google Scholar
Burkert, W. (1985). Greek Religion (tr. J. Raffan) (Oxford)Google Scholar
Buxton, R. (ed.) (1999). From Myth to Reason? Studies in the Development of Greek Thought (Oxford)Google Scholar
Cairns, D.L. (2013) ‘Introduction: archaic thought and tragic interpretation’, in Cairns, D.L. (ed.), Tragedy and Archaic Greek Thought (Swansea) ixliv 10.2307/j.ctvvnb06.4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cairns, D.L. (2014). ‘Ψυχή, θυμός, and metaphor in Homer and Plato’, EPlaton 11, 141 https://journals.openedition.org/etudesplatoniciennes/566 Google Scholar
Cairns, D.L. (2016) Sophocles: Antigone (London)Google Scholar
Casadio, G. and Johnston, P.A. (eds) (2009) Mystic Cults in Magna Graecia (Austin)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cerri, G. (1979) Legislazione orale e tragedia greca. Studi sull’ Antigone e sulle Supplici ii Euripide (Naples)Google Scholar
Clinton, K. (2003) ‘Stages of initiation into the Eleusinian and Samothracian Mysteries’, in Cosmopoulos, M.B. (ed.), Greek Mysteries: The Archaeology and Ritual of Ancient Greek Secret Cults (London) 5078 Google Scholar
Cullyer, H. (2005) ‘A wind that blows from Thrace: Dionysus in the fifth stasimon of Sophocles’ “Antigone”’, CW 99, 320 Google Scholar
Derron, P. (ed.) (2015) Cosmologies et cosmogonies dans la littérature antique (Geneva)Google Scholar
Dover, K.J. (1974) Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle (Oxford)Google Scholar
Foley, H.P. (2001) Female Acts in Greek Tragedy (Princeton)Google Scholar
Fowler, R.L. (2011) ‘Mythos and logos’, JHS 131, 4566 10.1017/S0075426911000048CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fränkel, H. (1975) Early Greek Poetry and Philosophy (tr. M. Hadas and J. Willis) (Oxford)Google Scholar
Frede, M. (1996) ‘Introduction’, in Frede, M. and Striker, G. (eds), Rationality in Greek Thought (Oxford) 128 Google Scholar
Furley, D. (1987) The Greek Cosmologists (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511552540CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gantz, T. (1993) Early Greek Myth: A Guide to Literary and Artistic Sources (Baltimore)Google Scholar
Garvie, A.F. (2017) ‘Antigone: Right or Wrong?’, in Stuttard, D. (ed.), Looking at Antigone (London) 1124 Google Scholar
Geertz, C. (1984) ‘“From the native’s point of view”: on the nature of anthropological understanding’, in Schweder, R. and Levine, R. (eds), Culture Theory: Essays on Minds, Self, and Emotion (Cambridge) 123–36Google Scholar
Gill, C. (1996) Personality in Greek Epic, Tragedy, and Philosophy: The Self in Dialogue (Oxford).Google Scholar
Goheen, R.F. (1951) The Imagery of Sophocles’ Antigone: A Study of Poetic Language and Structure (Princeton)Google Scholar
Goldhill, S. (1986) Reading Greek Tragedy (Cambridge)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldhill, S. (2012) Sophocles and the Language of Tragedy (Oxford)10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199796274.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graf, F. (1974) Eleusis und die orphische Dichtung Athens in vorhellenistischer Zeit (Berlin)10.1515/9783110856576CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graf, F. (2014) ‘Derveni and ritual’, in Papadopoulou, I. and Muellner, L. (eds), Poetry as Initiation: The Center for Hellenic Studies Symposium on the Derveni Papyrus (Cambridge MA) 6788 Google Scholar
Graf, F. and Johnston, S.I. (2013) Ritual Texts for the Afterlife: Orpheus and the Bacchic Gold Tablets (2nd edition) London CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, D.W. (2006) Explaining the Cosmos: The Ionian Tradition of Scientific Philosophy (Princeton)Google Scholar
Granger, H. (2013) ‘Early natural theology: the purification of the divine nature’, in Sider, D. and Obbink, D. (eds), Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras (Berlin) 163200 10.1515/9783110331370.163CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffith, M. (1999) Sophocles: Antigone (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Harris, M. (1976) ‘History and significance of the EMIC/ETIC distinction’, Annual Review of Anthropology 5, 329–5010.1146/annurev.an.05.100176.001553CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Havelock, E.A. (1978) The Greek Concept of Justice (Cambridge MA)10.4159/harvard.9780674183513CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, M. (2018) ‘Subject review: Greek literature’, G&R 65, 242–47Google Scholar
Henrichs, A. (1990) ‘Between country and city: cultic dimensions of Dionysus in Athens and Attica’, in Mastronarde, D.J. and Griffith, M. (eds), Cabinet of the Muses: Essays on Classical and Comparative Literature in Honor of Thomas G. Rosenmeyer (Berkeley) 257–77Google Scholar
Henrichs, A. (1994) ‘“Why should I dance?”: choral self-referentiality in Greek tragedy’, Arion 3, 56111 Google Scholar
Hester, D.A. (1971) ‘Sophocles the unphilosophical. A study in the Antigone ’, Mnemosyne 24, 1159 10.1163/156852571X00451CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hussey, E. (1982) ‘Epistemology and meaning in Heraclitus’, in Schofield, M. and Nussbaum, M.C. (eds), Language and Logos (Cambridge) 3359 10.1017/CBO9780511550874.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaeger, W. (1947) The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers (tr. E.S. Robinson) (Oxford)Google Scholar
Janko, R. (1997) ‘The physicist as hierophant: Aristophanes, Socrates and the authorship of the Derveni Papyrus’, ZPE 118, 6194 Google Scholar
Jebb, R. (1900) Sophocles: Antigone (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Kahn, C.H. (1960) Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology (New York)10.7312/kahn90334CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahn, C.H. (1979) The Art and Thought of Heraclitus: An Edition of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Kamerbeek, J.C. (1978) The Plays of Sophocles: The Antigone (Leiden)Google Scholar
Kemmer, E. (1903) Die polare Ausdrucksweise in der Griechischen Literatur (Würzburg)Google Scholar
Kirk, G.S, Raven, J. and Schofield, M. (1983) The Presocratic Philosophers (2nd edition) Cambridge 10.1017/CBO9780511813375CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knox, B.M. (1964) The Heroic Temper: Studies in Sophoclean Tragedy (Berkeley)Google Scholar
Kouremenos, T., Parássoglou, G.M. and Tsantsanoglou, K. (2006) The Derveni Papyrus (Florence)Google Scholar
Laks, A. (2018) The Concept of Presocratic Philosophy (tr. G.M. Most) (Princeton)Google Scholar
Laks, A. and Most, G.M. (2016) Early Greek Philosophy (9 vols) (Cambridge MA)Google Scholar
Liapis, V. (2013) ‘Creon the Labdacid: political confrontation and the doomed oikos in Sophocles’ Antigone ’, in Cairns, D.L. (ed.), Tragedy and Archaic Greek Thought, (Swansea) 81118 10.2307/j.ctvvnb06.8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, G.E.R. (1966) Polarity and Analogy: Two Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Lloyd, G.E.R. (1987) The Revolutions of Wisdom: Studies in the Claims and Practice of Ancient Greek Science (Berkeley)Google Scholar
Lloyd, G.E.R. (1990) Demystifying Mentalities (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511607691CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, G.E.R. (1991) ‘Greek cosmologies’, in Methods and Problems in Greek Science: Selected Papers (Cambridge) 141–63 Originally published 1975 in C. Blacker and M. Loewe (eds), Ancient Cosmologies (London) 198–224Google Scholar
Long, A.A. (1968) Language and Thought in Sophocles (London)Google Scholar
Long, A.A. (2009) ‘Heraclitus on measure and the explicit emergence of rationality’, in Frede, D. and Reis, B. (eds), Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy (Berlin) 87109 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macedo, J.M. (2011) ‘In between poetry and ritual: the Hymn to Dionysus in Sophocles’ Antigone (1115–54)’, CQ 61, 402–1110.1017/S0009838811000346CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Most, G.W. (2013) ‘Heraclitus on religion’, Rhizomata 1, 153–6710.1515/rhiz-2013-0007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nestle, W. (1942) Vom Mythos Zum Logos (Stuttgart)Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M.C. (2001) The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (2nd edition) (Cambridge)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oudemans, T.C.W. and Lardinois, A.P.M.H. (1987) Tragic Ambiguity: Anthropology, Philosophy and Sophocles Antigone (Leiden)10.1163/9789004246539CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parker, R. (1983) Miasma: Pollution and Purification in Early Greek Religion (Oxford)Google Scholar
Parker, R. (1995) ‘Early Orphism’, in Powell, A. (ed.), The Greek World (London) 483510 Google Scholar
Piano, V. (2016) Il Papiro di Derveni tra Religione e Filosofia (Florence)10.2307/j.ctt1tqx8j9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinhardt, K. (1979) Sophocles (tr. H. Harvey and D. Harvey) (Oxford)Google Scholar
Richardson, N. (1974) The Homeric Hymn to Demeter (Oxford)Google Scholar
Riedweg, C. (1995) ‘Orphisches bei Empedokles’, A&A 41, 3459 Google Scholar
Rodríguez, C.M. (2005) Orfeo y el orfismo en la poesía de Empedocles (Madrid)Google Scholar
Rösler, W. (1970) Reflexe Vorsokratischen Denkens bei Aischylos (Meisenheim am Glan)Google Scholar
Rutherford, R.B. (2012) Greek Tragic Style: Form, Language and Interpretation (Cambridge)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scodel, R. (2017) ‘Antigone’s change of heart’, in Stuttard, D. (ed.), Looking at Antigone (London) 7992 Google Scholar
Scullion, S. (1998) ‘Dionysos and katharsis in Antigone ’, ClAnt 17, 96122 Google Scholar
Seaford, R. (1990) ‘The imprisonment of women in Greek tragedy’, JHS 110, 7690 10.2307/631733CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seaford, R. (1994a) Reciprocity and Ritual: Homer and Tragedy in the Developing City-State (Oxford)Google Scholar
Seaford, R. (1994b) ‘Sophokles and the Mysteries’, Hermes 122, 275–88Google Scholar
Seaford, R. (2003) ‘Aeschylus and the unity of opposites’, JHS 123, 141–6310.2307/3246264CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seaford, R. (2004) Money and the Early Greek Mind: Homer, Philosophy, Tragedy (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511483080CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seaford, R. (2012) Cosmology and the Polis: The Social Construction of Space and Time in the Tragedies of Aeschylus (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511920790CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scapin, N. (2020) The Flower of Suffering: Theology, Justice, and the Cosmos in Aeschylus’ Oresteia and Presocratic Thought (Berlin)10.1515/9783110685633CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segal, C. (1964) ‘Sophocles’ praise of man and the conflicts of the Antigone ’, Arion 3, 4666 Google Scholar
Segal, C. (1981) Tragedy and Civilization: An Interpretation of Sophocles (Norman)Google Scholar
Smith, J.E.H. (2019) Irrationality: A History of the Dark Side of Reason (Princeton)Google Scholar
Snell, B. (1953) The Discovery of the Mind (tr. T. Rosenmeyer) (Oxford)Google Scholar
Sourvinou-Inwood, C. (1989) ‘Assumptions and the creation of meaning: reading Sophocles’ Antigone ’, JHS 109: 134–4810.2307/632037CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stuttard, D. (2017) ‘Introduction: Antigone, a play for today?’, in Stuttard, D. (ed.), Looking at Antigone (London) 110 Google Scholar
Tambiah, S.J. (1990) Magic, Science and Religion and the Scope of Rationality (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Tor, S. (2017) Mortal and Divine in Early Greek Epistemology: A Study of Hesiod, Xenophanes and Parmenides (Cambridge)10.1017/9781139235747CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trapp, M.B. (1996) ‘Tragedy and the fragility of moral reasoning: response to Foley’, in Silk, M.S. (ed.), Tragedy and the Tragic (Oxford) 7484 Google Scholar
Trépanier, S. (2010) ‘Early Greek theology: god as nature and natural gods, in Erskine, A. and Bremmer, J. (eds), The Gods of Ancient Greece: Identities and Transformations (Edinburgh) 273317 10.1515/9780748642892-019CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ustinova, Y. (2009) Caves and the Ancient Greek Mind: Descending Underground in the Search for Ultimate Truth (Oxford)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vernant, J.-P. and Vidal-Naquet, P. (1988) Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece (tr. J. Lloyd) (New York)Google Scholar
Versnel, H.S. (2011) Coping with the Gods (Leiden)10.1163/ej.9789004204904.i-594CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, G. (1947) ‘Equality and justice in early Greek cosmologies’, CPh 42, 156–78Google Scholar
West, M.L. (1983) The Orphic Poems (Oxford)Google Scholar
West, S. (1999) ‘Sophocles’ Antigone and Herodotus book three’, in Griffin, J. (ed.) Sophocles Revisited: Essays Presented to Sir Hugh Lloyd-Jones (Oxford) 109–36Google Scholar
Willi, A. (2008) Sikelismos: Sprache, Literatur und Gesellschaft im griechischen Sizilien (8.-5. Jh. v. Chr.) (Basel)Google Scholar
Winnington-Ingram, R.P. (1980) Sophocles: An Interpretation (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511586194CrossRefGoogle Scholar