Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-01T16:19:19.551Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part VI - Global Responses to COVID-19

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 October 2023

I. Glenn Cohen
Affiliation:
Harvard Law School, Massachusetts
Abbe R. Gluck
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Katherine Kraschel
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Carmel Shachar
Affiliation:
Harvard Law School, Massachusetts

Summary

Type
Chapter
Information
COVID-19 and the Law
Disruption, Impact and Legacy
, pp. 329 - 390
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

Introduction

Michelle M. Mello

Several themes unite the wide-ranging chapters in Part VI as the authors explore what lessons can be learned from the disparate ways in which governments around the globe responded to the COVID-19 pandemic. First, there is a complicated relationship between democratic institutions and a nation’s ability to respond to serious disease outbreaks. Reasonable people might hypothesize that democracy is a handicap during public health emergencies. Authoritarian governments can get even draconian things done quickly, quashing public resistance. Further, the more the law dilutes power in order to impose checks and balances and prevent abuse, the more it hobbles a swift response. But, on the other hand, democratic institutions make it harder for government to deny or downplay public health threats without detection, and federalism and other forms of power decentralization make it possible for some units of government to mount a vigorous pandemic response, even if others refuse.

In Chapter 22, “COVID-19 and National Public Health Regimes: Whither the Post-Washington Consensus in Public Health?,” Tess Wise, Gali Katznelson, Carmel Shachar, and Andrea Louise Campbell empirically investigate how effectively countries with different political, legal, social, cultural, economic, and organizational structures stemmed the early spread of COVID-19. The authors report the surprising finding that the countries whose systems appeared best prepared for a public health emergency enjoyed no clear advantage. Neither development nor democracy significantly predicted governmental effectiveness in fighting disease spread.

In Chapter 23, “A Functionalist Approach to Analyzing Legal Responses to COVID-19 Across Countries: Comparative Insights from Two Global Symposia,” Joelle Grogan and Alicia Ely Yamin also consider the connections between democratic institutions and governmental performance during health emergencies – specifically, a nation’s performance in protecting human rights. Drawing on findings from two multi-country symposia, they conclude that formal legal regimes (for example, whether a country uses emergency-powers laws or ordinary legal powers) may be less important to whether a country avoids abuses of power during a pandemic than the social and political environment in which these regimes function. Grogan and Yamin voice greater suspicion about undemocratic regimes than Wise and her coauthors, perhaps because their conception of an effective government response includes consideration of human rights concerns.

In Chapter 24, “A Tale of Two Crises: COVID-19, Climate Change, and Crisis Response,” Daniel Farber worries about democratic nations’ ability to solve global crises when their governments are fractured and polarized. He considers the connections between the two seminal global crises of our age: COVID-19 and climate change. Farber’s analysis finds that although the pandemic induced short-term reductions in carbon emissions, its longer-term impacts on how societies obtain and use energy are more uncertain. He notes opportunities to pursue a “green recovery,” using economic stimulus funds to invest in clean energy, but also the prospect of long-term damage to public transportation infrastructure. Farber trenchantly observes that while both crises have generated fervent hopes for technological rescues, making technology effective in combating the crises requires complex social investments.

In Chapter 25, “Vaccine Tourism, Federalism, Nationalism,” Glenn Cohen highlights the complexities that federalism layers on already thorny problems such as vaccine allocation. Democratic institutions, he underscores, can be both friend and foe during health emergencies. Cohen asks who, among several different groups of community outsiders, may have a morally legitimate claim to a community’s vaccine doses, and why. Fixing on communitarian principles as a lodestar, he offers a helpful definition of who belongs to a community for the purpose of vaccines.

A second theme connecting the chapters pertains to measurement. Answering questions about the optimal form of governance during pandemics begs the question: Optimal for what? Which outcomes are most relevant to assess? For instance, should we focus on COVID-19 cases and deaths, as Wise and colleagues do, or a more holistic assessment of how countries balance disease response with individual rights protections and equity considerations, per Cohen and Grogan and Yamin? Further, how can we rigorously conduct cross-national comparisons when countries differ in so many ways?

The ambitious empirical analysis undertaken by Wise and her coauthors illustrates the challenges. Countries have different levels of baseline vulnerability to infectious disease spread due to features unrelated to their legal, political, and social structures – for example, different levels of rurality and population mobility, and entry into the pandemic at different times, when different levels of knowledge had accumulated about how SARS-CoV-2 spreads. Figuring out how to rigorously isolate effects and control for confounding factors will occupy analysts of COVID-19 governance for some time.

For now, we can reach only tentative conclusions about how much political, legal, and public health systems matter to effective pandemic response. It is valuable to make the point, as Wise and her coauthors do, that prepositioning is not destiny when it comes to fighting novel pathogens. But some caution is warranted before concluding that redressing historical underinvestment in public health and health care systems will not help next time. On the contrary, Grogan and Yamin argue, it is reasonable to continue to operate on the assumption that having a well-functioning health care system and a public health system that assures equitable access to preventive and therapeutic measures will help avoid loss of life. Similarly, Cohen’s chapter gives rise to the inference that investing in advance planning for pandemic countermeasure allocation will yield dividends.

A final thread uniting the chapters is the notion of community. For many reasons and in many respects, COVID-19 led to the rapid drawing of lines around communities throughout the world. From the allocation of vaccine doses to the imposition of community mitigation orders, national, state, and local communities asserted themselves in defining their own individual pandemic responses. While this patchwork created interesting natural experiments to study, as the chapter by Wise and her coauthors shows, it likely undermined an effective global response to the virus. Whereas other global crises – most notably, World War II – cultivated social solidarity and a widening of the concepts of community and belonging, COVID-19 drove social fragmentation. Not only did this complicate disease response (for example, by prompting vaccine tourism and perpetuating inequities in COVID-19 outcomes among population subgroups), it may also have enervated the prospects for global cooperation to solve other problems, such as climate change. Our joint future may depend on redefining community. To the searching questions that Grogan and Yamin ask at their chapter’s end – “who should exercise power, of what sort, and over whom?” – might be added, “who should exercise care, of what sort, and for whom?”

Collectively, these chapters shed much light on the critical question of what constitutes good governance during a pandemic and how it can be secured for populations around the world.

22 COVID-19 and National Public Health Regimes Whither the Post-Washington Consensus in Public Health?Footnote 1

Tess Wise , Gali Katznelson , Carmel Shachar , and Andrea Louise Campbell
I Introduction

On June 2, 2016, the Center for Strategic and International Studies Global Health Policy Center in Washington, DC hosted a conversation with Jim Yong Kim, then president of the World Bank Group. Kim’s talk was entitled “Preventing the Next Pandemic.” Framed by the Ebola crisis that was just winding down in West Africa, pandemics in 2016 were presented as primarily a problem for developing countries. In his introductory remarks, the Center for Strategic and International Studies moderator, J. Stephen Morrison, even felt it necessary to remind the audience that understanding pandemics “mattered” for “US national interests.”Footnote 2 The primary pandemic-prevention mechanism proposed by the World Bank was emergency pandemic financing and insurance. In his remarks, however, Jim Yong Kim also argued that health was central to more than just national well-being: it was a key driver of economic growth and development. He cited findings from the Lancet Commission Report that, between 2000 and 2011, about 24 percent of income growth in developing countries resulted from improvements in health.Footnote 3

Kim’s position reflected what is sometimes called the “Post-Washington Consensus,” or the conclusion that development strategies should emphasize a broad array of social policies beyond what had been originally emphasized by the “Washington Consensus” of the 1980s and 1990s. The originator of the Washington Consensus, John Williamson, suggested that public expenditure priorities be redirected toward “neglected fields” such as “primary health and education, and infrastructure.”Footnote 4 Nevertheless, scholars generally agree that the Washington Consensus was characterized by a dominant orthodoxy that countries should “stabilize, privatize, and liberalize.”Footnote 5 When the Post-Washington Consensus was proposed in the mid-2000s, health again emerged as an area scholars saw as key for development,Footnote 6 though, as evidenced by Kim’s suggestions regarding pandemic insurance and financing, market-forward solutions are still seen as central, reflecting an international trend toward leveraging financial markets for development that some have dubbed the “Wall Street Consensus.”Footnote 7

Health will undoubtedly be central to any emerging global development consensus, but as the COVID-19 pandemic has made clear, a broader global consensus on public health, including the vision of society informing the concept of “the public,” is needed. In this chapter, we use data from the World Bank and other (Post-)Washington Consensus institutions to create a snapshot of global public health on the eve of the COVID-19 pandemic. We find that (Post-)Washington Consensus institutions saw the world as having varying levels of public-health-related development and social priorities. We then examine how countries from different clusters in this space fared in the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic (in other words, before vaccinations became available in at least a few countries). We find that the countries supposedly best prepared for a public health emergency had no systematic advantage and even lagged behind countries that were supposedly not as well prepared in the early stages of the pandemic. Similarly, other classifications of public health preparedness from the pre-COVID-19 period, such as the World Health Organization’s Joint External Evaluation Tool or the Global Health Security Index, which did not adequately predict detection time and mortality in the early months of the COVID-19 pandemic, also fell short.Footnote 8 From our data and case studies, we are concerned that a tradeoff between democracy and government effectiveness may be a lesson taken from experiences in the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic and suggest instead that a social democratic perspective on public health that links justice and efficacy is needed.

II Creating a Typology of Public Health Regimes

To create a typology of public health regimes that characterizes the variation in national public health on the eve of the COVID-19 pandemic from the perspective of institutions such as the World Bank, we group countries by similarity in “political, legal, social, cultural, economic, and organizational structures” related to public health.Footnote 9 While Asthana and Halliday emphasize that scholars can tailor public health regimes to study particular areas, such as nutritional inequalities or anti-smoking campaigns, we look broadly to see whether grouping countries by general indicators of public health can help us understand performance in response to the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic. Our indicators of public health-related factors come primarily from World Bank and United Nations data, with two additional indicators of democracy, using the 2018 POLITY5 scores,Footnote 10 and ethnic and linguistic fractionalization, from measures developed by Alesina et al. in 2003.Footnote 11 Table 22.1 below shows the full set of indicators.

Table 22.1 Global indicators of public health

All from World Bank (except where indicated)
PoliticalLegalSocial and CulturalEconomicOrganizational Structures
Corruption control; regulatory quality; government effectiveness (average percentile rank last ten years); legislative and executive indices of political competitiveness; and Polity scores assessing autocracy vs. democracy (from Center for Systemic Peace)Rule of law, and voice and accountability (average percentile rank last ten years)Status of women (female labor force participation, percentage of women in legislature, gender discrimination law in employment); heterogeneity (ethnic, religious, and linguistic fractionalization measures from Alesina et al. 2003); and demographics (total population; life expectancy; percent aged sixty-five+; fertility rate; population growth rate; percent rural)Spending capacity and priorities (gross national income per capita; and health spending and military spending as percentage of GDP); and inequality (Gini index)Capacity (hospital beds and physicians per 1,000 population); cost (out-of-pocket spending per capita); conditions (percent of population using at least basic sanitation services; percent overweight); and presence of autonomous regions

When conducting a global analysis, choices of indicators are limited to what is widely available and reliably measured. This limits what we can choose to explore and has theoretical implications because existing data do not come into existence by chance. Our analysis relies primarily on World Bank data, which, we argue, are indicators of a weak “Post-Washington Consensus” in public health.

These indicators arise from a contested paradigm. The Washington Consensus of the 1980s and 1990s on effective development strategies was associated with Washington-based policy institutions with strong international influence – such as the International Monetary Fund, the World Bank, and the US Treasury – which were proponents of neoliberal development policy.Footnote 12 Before the mid-2000s, when a spate of studies called its effectiveness into question, the Washington Consensus represented the dominant ideology in the area of development.Footnote 13 Though there have been numerous efforts to move beyond the Washington Consensus, such as the Post-Washington Consensus, no new dominant ideology has taken hold.Footnote 14 As Joseph E. Stiglitz put it in 2008, “If there is a consensus today about what strategies are most likely to promote the development of the poorest countries in the world, it is this: there is no consensus except that the Washington Consensus did not provide the answer.”Footnote 15 Despite being a contested consensus, the (Post-)Washington Consensus still looms large in contemporary indicators such as those we draw upon in this chapter, understandings of concepts such as “governance,” and global targets such as the Sustainable Development Goals.Footnote 16

A Principal Component Analysis

Principal Component Analysis (PCA) is a statistical method used to project high-dimensional data into a lower-dimensional space while preserving as much variation as possible. The “principal components” uncovered by PCA are linear combinations of the indicators that define orthogonal axes of variation. Running PCA on our 116-country dataset reveals two main components (see the Methodological Appendix in this chapter for the methodological details). Figure 22.1 shows how countries map onto them.

Figure 22.1 PCA results

1 A Primary Component of “Development”

Countries’ scores on the primary component, accounting for 40.9 percent of the overall variance, are graphed along the x-axis in Figure 22.1. We interpret these scores as broad indicators of public health-related development in the context of a weak Post-Washington Consensus.

The primary component distinguishes between, on the one hand, nations with good governance, high levels of health infrastructure, a more elderly and urban population, higher income levels, and longer life expectancy, and, on the other hand, nations with lower indicators of good governance, lower levels of health infrastructure, a younger and more rural population, lower income levels, and shorter life expectancy. We describe this component in more detail in the Methodological Appendix.

2 A Secondary Component of “Social Priorities”

The second component, explaining 10.4 percent of the variation in the data, is characterized by political distinctions that, in linear combination, explain variation orthogonal to (independent of) the first component. Countries’ scores on the second component are graphed on the y-axis of Figure 22.1. We describe the secondary component as a measure of “social priorities” related to public health. The social priorities component is characterized by women’s position in society, military spending, and democracy. Countries that score low on social priorities, and cluster at the center bottom of Figure 22.1, have lower levels of women in the workforce, higher military spending, and lower levels of democracy compared to countries with higher scores. Again, we describe this component in more detail in the Methodological Appendix.

B K-Means Clustering to Identify Public Health Regimes

We apply a second statistical method, k-means clustering, to group the countries based on their similarities within our statistical space to define groups that we call public health regimes.

Theoretical motivation, certain statistical indicators, and face validity suggest that five clusters are optimal (see the Methodological Appendix). Figure 22.2 shows our clusters graphed over the first two components from the PCA. Table 22.2 summarizes the public health regimes that we find using five-cluster k-means.

Table 22.2 Public health regimes and key characteristics

Cluster12345
Public Health RegimeMedium-High Development DemocraciesHigh-Development DemocraciesMedium-Development DemocraciesLow-Development Semi-DemocraciesMedium-Low Development Semi-Autocracies
CountriesAlbania, Armenia, Belarus, Bulgaria, Chile, Croatia, Cyprus, Czech Republic, Estonia, Georgia, Greece, Hungary, Israel, South Korea, Latvia, Lithuania, Mauritius, Moldova, Poland, Russian Federation, Slovak Republic, Ukraine, UruguayAustralia, Austria, Belgium, Canada, Denmark, Finland, France, Germany, Ireland, Italy, Japan, Luxembourg, Netherlands, New Zealand, Norway, Portugal, Slovenia, Spain, Sweden, Switzerland, United Kingdom, United StatesArgentina, Bolivia, Botswana, Brazil, Cabo Verde, Colombia, Costa Rica, Dominican Republic, Ecuador, El Salvador, Guatemala, Honduras, Indonesia, Jamaica, Kyrgyz Republic, Malaysia, Mexico, Mongolia, Nicaragua, Panama, Paraguay, Peru, Philippines, South Africa, Sri Lanka, Thailand, Tunisia, TurkeyBenin, Burkina Faso, Burundi, Cameroon, Central African Republic, Ethiopia, Gabon, The Gambia, Ghana, Haiti, Kenya, Lao People’s Democratic Republic, Liberia, Madagascar, Malawi, Mali, Mozambique, Nepal, Niger, Tanzania, Togo, Uganda, Zambia, ZimbabweAlgeria, Azerbaijan, Bangladesh, China, Egypt, Arab Republic, Fiji, India, Iran, Islamic Republic, Iraq, Jordan, Kazakhstan, Lebanon, Morocco, Pakistan, Tajikistan, United Arab Emirates, Uzbekistan, Vietnam, Yemen
“Development Component” Variables (top six variables)
Percent Sixty-Five+ (Cluster Avg.)15.017.96.63.05.1
Government Effectiveness (Percentile Rank, Cluster Avg.)66.991.449.022.839.0
Regulatory Quality (Percentile Rank, Cluster Avg.)70.190.650.927.532.0
Rule of Law (Percentile Rank, Cluster Avg.)63.091.840.927.632.0
Life Expectancy (Years, Cluster Avg.)76.181.573.360.872.1
Gross National Income (Per Capita, International $, PPP, Cluster Avg.)$23,050$47,324$12,144$2,735$12,741
“Social Priorities Component” Variables (top six variables)
Female Labor Force Participation (Rate, Ages Fifteen+, Cluster Avg.)45.746.240.047.628.2
Military Spending (% GDP, Cluster Avg.)2.01.41.31.23.1
Polity Score (−10 to +10, Cluster Avg.)7.99.77.23.7−2.1
Exec. Index of Electoral Competition (1 to 7, Cluster Avg.)7776.34.8
Basic Sanitation (% pop. using, Cluster Avg.)94.998.981.328.182.5
Religious Fractionaliz’n (0–1 index, Cluster Avg.)0.480.440.310.570.33

Figure 22.2 Five clusters – our selected grouping

III How Have Different Public Health Regimes Fared in the Context of COVID-19

We now examine how different public health regimes fared in the COVID-19 pandemic. We draw on data from the University of Oxford’s COVID-19 Government Response Tracker (OxCGRT),Footnote 17 for government response outcomes, and from Johns Hopkins University, for cases and deaths.Footnote 18 These datasets, while the most comprehensive data available at the time of writing, are not infallible. For example, in low- and middle-income countries, even during non-pandemic times, most deaths occur outside of the hospital system and are unlikely to have a cause-of-death certified by a physician.Footnote 19 Noh and Danuser find that in half of the fifty countries they explored, actual cumulative COVID-19 cases were estimated to be five to twenty times greater than the confirmed cases.Footnote 20

The first set of outcomes we examine is how fast COVID-19 spread and how comprehensive the government response was. We might expect a comprehensive response to slow the spread and variation in response and speed to vary across public health regimes we established in the previous section. Interestingly, neither pattern is borne out in the data.

In Figure 22.3, the x-axis indicates the number of days between the first and the 10,000th reported case in each country. The y-axis displays the maximum government containment score (0 to 100) over the period from January 1, 2020, and April 10, 2021, the maximum data window allowed at the time of analysis.Footnote 21 Maximum government containment comes from OxCGRT and includes the sum of fourteen indices from the areas of containment and closure policies (e.g., closing schools) and health system policies (e.g., public information campaigns) scaled to vary between 0 and 100. Taking a government’s maximum score on this metric produces a somewhat blunt measure of the initial COVID-19 response, but one that reflects the broad contours of important variation in government responses. In the Methodological Appendix, we show an alternative measure using the average government containment, which does not change the substantive results. The shape of the marker indicates the country’s cluster (public health regime).

Figure 22.3 Max government containment vs. speed of spread

Figure 22.3 and Table 22.3 indicate that none of the public health regimes we identified had a distinct advantage against COVID-19 in slowing the spread during the early phases of the pandemic. The High-Development Democracies (Cluster 2), which we would expect to be the best prepared, actually had the fastest spread, with only 95 days on average to reach 10,000 cases and 77 days on average to reach 1,000 deaths. While we might attribute the seemingly outstanding performance of the Low-Development Semi-Democracies (Cluster 4) to poor data quality, the fact that the High-Development Democracies did worse than Medium- and Medium-High-Development Democracies (Clusters 1 and 3), and even worse than Medium-Low-Development Semi-Autocracies (Cluster 5), is harder to attribute to data quality issues. This pattern persists even after accounting for population and examining the number of days to reach 100, then 500, deaths per million. Levels of containment were similar across all public health regimes, except for Low-Development Semi-Democracies (Cluster 4), which had somewhat lower average and maximum containment than other public health regimes.

Table 22.3 Public health regimes, speed of spread, government response

Cluster12345
Public Health RegimeMedium-High Development DemocraciesHigh- Development DemocraciesMedium- Development DemocraciesLow- Development Semi-DemocraciesMedium-Low Development Semi-Autocracies
Days to 10k cases (Cluster Avg.)1589514622099
Days to 1k deaths (Cluster Avg.)21677118250151
Days to 100 deaths per million (Cluster Avg.)18878138244196
Days to 500 deaths per million (Cluster Avg.)216194201Not reached269
Avg. Containment (Jan 2020–Apr 2021, Cluster Avg., 0 –100)49.351.053.140.251.4
Max Containment (Jan 2020–Apr 2021, Cluster Avg., 0 –100)76.074.274.765.575.3

In sum, the High-Development Democracies of Cluster 2, those we expect would be best prepared, were likely to see a faster spread than countries with any other public health regime.

We might attribute some of this rapid spread to location, data quality, and demographics. However, examples from across the world highlight that these factors alone were not enough to determine a country’s destiny. For example, in Figure 22.3, Thailand stands out as a country that managed to slow the spread significantly despite geographical proximity to, and a close trade relationship with, China.

Figure 22.4 examines another factor that may have increased the challenge of containing COVID-19: the percentage of a country’s population aged sixty-five and older. For this analysis, we examine the number of days it took to reach the threshold of ten deaths per million. We see a negative relationship – countries with younger populations took somewhat longer to reach ten deaths per million – but there are some notable outliers, particularly South Korea, which has an older population, but was one of the slowest to reach the ten deaths per million threshold (260 days).

Figure 22.4 Percent sixty-five plus vs. days to reach 10 COVID-19 deaths per million population

In general, there is no strong correlation between what we identify as a country’s prior public health regime and its performance in the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic. If anything, countries we might have expected to perform the best, those with the most consolidated democracies and higher levels of governance, income, and state capacity (the high-development democracies of Cluster 2), did worse in slowing the spread and lowering the death rate than countries in other clusters. In the face of the COVID-19 pandemic, the weak (Post-)Washington Consensus in public health is not indicative of less devastation even among its best students, just as the (Post-)Washington Consensus did little to stop the Great Recession of 2007–2009 from affecting wealthy countries around the globe.Footnote 22 Explaining this underperformance will take further analysis, but contributing factors may be demographics (as Cluster 2 countries tend to be older) and difficulty implementing non-pharmaceutical social interventions. We now conduct brief case studies to produce suggestions for key factors that we should be incorporating into our understanding of good public health.

IV Case Studies

We chose to investigate China, Thailand, and Israel through brief case studies. China is unique on a global scale because of its large population and experience of coping with an emerging virus first. China is a Cluster 5 country (medium-low development semi-autocracy). Thailand is a Cluster 3 country (medium-development democracy), though it bucks the dominant trend of its group by being an autocracy with a Polity score of -3. Finally, Israel is a Cluster 1 country (medium-high-development democracy).Footnote 23 Table 22.4 shows comparative pandemic outcomes and selected background characteristics for each country relative to its cluster. The performances of these countries stand out in comparison to the poor performance of the United States and the other high-development countries of Cluster 2.

Table 22.4 China, Thailand, Israel, and United States pandemic outcomes

China (Cluster 5)Cluster 5 AverageThailand (Cluster 3)Cluster 3 AverageIsrael (Cluster 1)Cluster 1 AverageUnited States (Cluster 2)Cluster 2 AverageGlobal Average
Days to Reach 10k Cases1099370146491585795134
Days to Reach Ten Deaths per Million PeopleNot reached61Not reached63145192161
Max Government Response (0–100)787569758876707473
Percent Pop. Sixty-five+ (%)9.45.110.56.611.21514.517.99.4
Percent Pop. Overweight (%)304829.649.863.355.266.456.747.1
Hospital Beds per 1,0003.42.32.12.03.15.72.94.53.1
Basic Sanitation (%)7982.597.381.310094.910098.976.5
Polity (−10 to +10)−7−2.1−37.267.989.75.6
Government Effectiveness (Percentile Rank 1–100)643964498767919154
A China

China, where the novel coronavirus originated, experienced rapid spread to 10,000 cases, but quickly controlled the disease, ultimately performing better than the rich democracies of Cluster 2. The effective Chinese response was facilitated by public health and industrial capacity, and by governmental and cultural factors.

After the first cases were reported in Wuhan in December 2019, lockdowns, school closures, and transport suspensions quickly followed. Coordination among government offices, extensive testing, and a national system of contact tracing facilitated the response, as did the early use of Fangcang hospitals to isolate mild-to-moderate cases from both homes and conventional hospitals. Although China has a large elderly population, only 3 percent live in nursing homes, minimizing one major source of infection experienced in some Western countries. Testing and quarantine measures for travelers aimed at preventing imported cases. China’s status as the world’s largest manufacturer of personal protective equipment also facilitated its reaction.Footnote 24

Among the public, “fresh memories” of the SARS-CoV outbreak hastened the response, as did ready compliance with mask wearing.Footnote 25 In general, the pandemic countermeasures were less fettered by concerns with civil liberties. “In China, you have a population that takes respiratory infections seriously and is willing to adopt non-pharmaceutical interventions, with a government that can put bigger constraints on individual freedoms than would be considered acceptable in most Western countries,” noted Gregory Poland, director of the Vaccine Research Group at the Mayo Clinic, adding that the response in the United States has been hampered by “hyper-individualism” and a “raucous anti-vaccine, anti-science movement that is trying to derail the fight against COVID-19.”Footnote 26 At the same time, the pace of vaccination was relatively slow because the country’s inactive-virus-based vaccine candidates took longer to manufacture, because millions of doses were donated to other nations to bolster foreign relations, and because, ironically, the effective response undercut urgency among the population, in contrast to the United States and United Kingdom, where raging infection rates spurred desperation over getting vaccinated.Footnote 27

B Thailand

Thailand illustrates the phenomenon of good governance without democracy, and its success in containing the pandemic is likely to reinforce calls for an emphasis on governance over democracy in the emerging public health consensus.Footnote 28

In March 2019, Thailand held elections for the first time since 2014, when a military coup overthrew its democratically elected government. Unfortunately, the 2019 election was widely considered to have been designed to prolong and legitimize the military’s dominant role in Thailand’s governance.Footnote 29 Between 1996 and 2018, Thailand’s ranking on the World Bank’s Worldwide Governance Indicators fell. Between 2002 and 2018, Thailand’s global rank decreased from the 65th percentile to below the 20th percentile for political stability, and from the 60th percentile to the 20th percentile for voice and accountability. However, government effectiveness remained relatively stable (around the 65th percentile). Kantamaturapoj et al. report that public services remain functioning with adequate quality, “reflecting a degree of independence from political pressure and a capacity to formulate and implement policies among bureaucrats.”Footnote 30

Since 2002, Thailand has provided comprehensive health benefits to its entire population through a universal coverage scheme with a high level of financial risk protection, as well as voice and accountability provided through legislative provisions and a deliberative process.Footnote 31 This health system was put to the test when, on January 13, 2020, Thailand was the first country to detect a case of COVID-19 outside of China.Footnote 32 After an initial spike in cases, Thailand went 102 days between May and September without any reported local transmission of COVID-19.Footnote 33

Thailand’s public health response to COVID-19 was swift and comprehensive. The Thai government quickly recommended the use of face masks and this was met with 95 percent compliance from the Thai population.Footnote 34 Tracing and quarantining were set up by rapid response teams, who isolated cases in facilities rather than in homes. When demand for N95 face masks spiked amid a global shortage, a new factory was constructed in a month, supplying free N95 masks to health facilities.Footnote 35 By the end of July 2020, a laboratory network for diagnosing COVID-19 using PCR (polymerase chain reaction) tests was active in 78 percent of Thailand’s seventy-seven provinces.Footnote 36

Although Thailand was successful in the initial stages of its response to the COVID-19 pandemic, Marome and Shaw raise concerns over the Thai government’s handling of the social and economic fallout from declining tourism revenue.Footnote 37

C Israel

Israel is one of the medium-high-development democracies that showed moderate success at COVID-19 containment during the initial months of the pandemic by utilizing centralized leadership. Inspired in part by a shortage of surge intensive care unit capacity, the Israeli Ministry of Health took control of hospital referrals and admissions and pioneered a containment strategy that included significant early travel restrictions and quarantine of travelers.Footnote 38 The Ministry of Health also took advantage of Israel’s strong digital health and surveillance capabilities to implement digital tracking, although this initiative was eventually struck down by the Israeli High Court of Justice as requiring legislative authorization rather than executive action.Footnote 39

There were also favorable demographic factors at play. Israel tends to be younger than other industrialized countries, such as those in Cluster 2, due to relatively high fertility rates.Footnote 40 Ethnic segregation may have also served as a protective factor for some communities, such as the Israeli Arab population, in the first wave of infection.Footnote 41

Interestingly, Israel’s strong centralized response to the pandemic and its emphasis on technology, including digital health, may ultimately allow it to be a COVID-19 “success story.” Then-Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu was able to secure a significant number of COVID-19 vaccine doses by, in part, promising a significant amount of data to manufacturers.Footnote 42 This promise was feasible because Israel had already created a national database that included the health information of 98 percent of its citizens. As a result, Israel may be the first country to immunize virtually all of its citizens over the age of sixteen and, therefore, potentially the first to control the pandemic via vaccination. Therefore, Israel may serve as a good reminder that this analysis considers the initial response and first wave of the pandemic, rather than the full life cycle of COVID-19.

V Discussion

The relative failure of the United States to slow the spread of COVID-19, along with the mediocre performance of high-development democracies in general, is continued evidence of the failure of the (Post-)Washington consensus in public health. As we look forward toward a still-hazy emerging public health paradigm, countries such as Thailand, South Korea, and Israel will likely become models that others will hope to emulate. For Israel and other similar success stories, we see a noteworthy pattern of above-average government effectiveness combined with below-average levels of democracy relative to their cluster peers.

The assumption that development and democracy are the sole predictors of pandemic preparedness and responsiveness has been challenged as agreement is emerging that Western countries have fared poorly. In an essay in the Intelligencer, “How the West Lost COVID-19,” David Wallace-Wells identifies slowness of response in the early stages of the pandemic amidst fear of how citizens might perceive rapid shutdowns as one major factor.Footnote 43 In the United States, for example, the first instinct of governments was to downplay the severity of the virus, while in East Asia, countries acted quickly and decisively despite incomplete information about the nature of the virus. This may in part be due to an arrogance that Western countries’ perceived development would shield them from the consequences of a pandemic. However, identifying precisely “how the West lost COVID-19” has been difficult. Multiple factors, including chance, contact with Italy, climate, and air conditioners, may all be at play. This is consistent with our analysis – no one set of indicators emerged as a reliable explanation for successes or failures in the early stages of the pandemic.

In noticing a tension between government effectiveness and democracy, we see a need for the future global consensus in public health to transition from a neoliberal vision of society to a social democratic one, in which the risks and costs associated with sickness are shared by the whole society, not only sick individuals, emphasizing that justice and efficiency must be linked together.Footnote 44 This linkage is desirable to avoid a world in which government effectiveness and democracy appear as tradeoffs, as they seem to be in our data, which arise from the neoliberal tradition embodied in the (Post-)Washington Consensus. In imagining the evolution of the Post-Washington Consensus in public health following COVID-19, we should cast off the centering on Washington and the neoliberal tradition that, in our analysis, fails to predict success in early pandemic responses. Instead, to prepare for the next global pandemic, we should focus more strongly on the connection between public health and democratic institutions, rather than government effectiveness in the abstract.

23 Mapping COVID-19 Legal Responses: A Functionalist Analysis

Joelle Grogan and Alicia Ely Yamin
I Introduction

The global COVID-19 pandemic caused by the novel coronavirus SARS-CoV-2 has focused the world’s attention on the central importance of population health to the economic and social well-being of societies and to the multilateral order that depends upon a globalized, interconnected world. It has also highlighted the challenges to the democratic rule of law posed by the widely varying actions adopted by governments in response. The notion that health and democratic rights are intimately connected is not new. For example, Robin West asserts that the sovereign is given a monopoly on coercion in exchange for security against a life that is “nasty, brutish and short” and that the baseline condition of the sovereign’s legitimacy lies in the protection of human health and well-being.Footnote 1 Therefore, according to West, health protection is foundational, not peripheral, to the liberal philosophical tradition.Footnote 2 Similarly, public health and health promotion is a precondition to substantive democracy – as those hobbled by infirmity will be unable to meaningfully engage in democratic self-governance. Historically, movements for universal health care, including the adoption of the National Health Service in the United Kingdom,Footnote 3 were democratic struggles to enlarge democratic inclusion.Footnote 4 Further, as laid bare during the pandemic, health systems have a role to play in sustaining and reproducing core democratic commitments to formal and substantive equality.

Drawing both on our respective scholarship in these fields as well as on insights from two global symposia on governmental responses held during the early phase of the pandemic, this chapter links analyses of democratic institutions and their capacity to maintain fundamental rights protections with the functioning of health systems and protections for the health rights of diverse people in practice. From April 6 to May 26, 2020, the “COVID-19 and States of Emergency” symposium, co-hosted by the Verfassungsblog and Democracy Reporting International, published eighty-two reports and commentaries on states of emergency and the use of power in response to the pandemic.Footnote 5 From May 12 to June 12, 2020, the “Global Responses to COVID-19: Rights, Democracy and the Law” symposium, hosted by the Petrie-Flom Center, produced thirty Bill of Health entries, each of which responded to three questions regarding: (1) the legal vehicles used in response to the pandemic; (2) the effects of these on marginalized populations; and (3) the roles of legislative and judicial oversight.Footnote 6 The analytical reports on the early months of the pandemic were authored by over 120 contributors worldwide, including academics drawn from the fields of international and constitutional law and health and social policy, as well as judges and lawyers specializing in public, administrative, and international law. These comparative approaches contrasted with efforts in those early days to produce repositories of laws and policies enacted with no contextualization.Footnote 7 As both symposia sought a diversity of perspectives about the preexisting legal architectures, as well as complex social and political impacts of governmental responses, they are not susceptible to a simplistic tabulation. Thus, the conclusions presented in this chapter should be read as reflecting the authors’ joint interpretations of reported findings across the separate symposia.

This chapter proceeds as follows. First, it considers whether the use of emergency powers (e.g., the declaration of a constitutional state of exception or the use of legislative emergency frameworks which allow for the exceptional use of executive power outside normal constraints) is preferable to using ordinary legislation in managing the impacts on civil liberties of a health and social crisis. This chapter argues that whether countries are successful in limiting the potential for abuse of power in emergencies is dependent on the social and political environment in which the legal rules operate, as much as whether formal limitations and checks on the use of power are present. Second, the pandemic raises questions regarding the role of health policymaking and health systems as democratic institutions, which have been inexorably affected by decades of privatization and reduced social spending on health. This chapter suggests that the background rules that structure health systems (public health and care) and decision-making regarding priorities are as critical to understanding governmental responses as the legal recognition of health-related rights.

II States of Exception and Emergency

States of exception or emergency enable the exceptional use of powers, typically by the executive outside ordinary legislative processes or scrutiny, justified on the basis of the necessity of an urgent response to an emergency. By their nature and the strength of justifying urgency which calls for their use, emergency powers are at heightened risk of misuse or abuse where significant action can be taken with limited capacity for oversight, and where subsequent judicial review of executive discretion can be “so light a touch as to be non-existent.”Footnote 8 The extended duration of the COVID-19 pandemic, in addition to concerns that the virus will become endemic, have extended the duration of executive dominance of decision-making,Footnote 9 leading to concerns that this will further global trends towards the autocratization and “decay” of democracies which were in motion prior to the pandemic.Footnote 10 Even as some countries have lifted many of the most restrictive measures on liberties at the time of writing, most provisions enacted have remained in place on statute books or in practice, leading to concerns that the modes of governance employed during the pandemic have normalized the exceptional in relation to public health emergencies.

Emergencies should not function as opportunities to permanently shift the balance of power toward the executive, resulting in decision-making that is all but unaccountable. Both symposia also underlined the importance of ensuring not only the limited nature of states of exception but, critically, the necessary limitations on the use of power during the emergency. For this, international human rights instruments, including the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, the American Convention on Human Rights, and the European Convention on Human Rights, have provided guidelines for safeguards on the use of exceptional power, which are typically premised on: (1) identifying certain non-derogable rights (e.g., the prohibition on torture and the right to a fair trial); and (2) requiring the use of emergency powers to be proportionate, necessary, non-discriminatory, and temporary in nature.Footnote 11 Health emergencies, including the current pandemic,Footnote 12 have been interpreted to come within these provisions.Footnote 13

A majority of countries in the symposia declared a “state of emergency” (or the domestic equivalent: e.g., a “state of exception” or “state of catastrophe”) or relied upon some form of emergency powers in response to the pandemic. The symposia demonstrated a broad range and form of domestic design of both states of emergency regimes and on constitutional and legal safeguards on their use. Examples of constitutional states of exception ranged from highly prescriptive, tiered, and differential states of exception requiring legislative approval depending on the perceived severity of the emergency (e.g., Estonia and Peru) to open-ended and discretionary provisions providing for an exclusively executive decision on what constituted a “threat” (e.g., Cameroon, Malaysia, and Thailand). A number of states alternatively introduced new legislative (rather than constitutional) states of emergency (e.g., France and Bulgaria) or introduced new powers which were designated as “emergency.” The latter legislative forms of emergency powers would have been expected to be subject to ordinary democratic checks and balances, including parliamentary scrutiny and judicial review, though often were not, either by legislative design or the degree of deference displayed by parliaments and courts.Footnote 14

In the use of emergency power, a central question is the safeguarding of civil liberties through the permissible degree to which rights can be limited or states may derogate from rights protections. The “limitation” of rights, often as part of a domestic balancing exercise between competing rights or overriding public interest (e.g., the requirement to wear masks in public), is distinguishable from derogation, which is envisioned as a temporary suspension of certain (not all) rights during an emergency subject to a range of justificatory conditions (e.g., proportionality and temporariness) and the oversight of external human rights bodies, in the case of international instruments, or domestic courts, in the case of protections on constitutional rights. What is notable is that while nearly all states acted to place highly restrictive limitations on the exercise of rights, including movement, assembly, and worship, only a minority of these states in the initial phase of the pandemic made official notifications of derogations from international human rights instruments.Footnote 15

There is no common reason why some states did, or did not, declare a state of emergency and it should not be assumed that it was to avoid ostensibly higher levels of scrutiny which may be expected under ordinary legislative processes. For example, a number of populous states, including Brazil, Bangladesh, Indonesia, and India, eschewed a declaration, likely for political reasons to either avoid negative historical associations of abuse of emergency powers or in the underestimation or downplaying of the severity of the pandemic threat. States which did not rely on emergency provisions instead relied on ordinary health legislation. Restricting power within ordinary democratic and legal constraints is in line with what Martin Scheinin advocates as the principle of normalcy: addressing the health emergency through “normally applicable powers and procedures and insist[ing] on full compliance with human rights, even if introducing new necessary and proportionate restrictions upon human rights on the basis of a pressing social need created by the pandemic.”Footnote 16 However, in some more concerning cases, any form of parliamentary legislative procedure was abandoned in favor of executive decrees and presidential or ministerial circulars (e.g., Cameroon, India, Turkey, and Vietnam). These measures were emergency powers in effect, though were not considered so in form. The effect in practice of reliance on ersatz “ordinary” powers was the avoidance of safeguards which otherwise were designed to control power under emergency. The commonality exposed is that without a requisite degree of democratic oversight and input, the negative consequences which can arise both under a state of emergency and upon reliance on ordinary legislation are indistinguishable.

Evident from analysis of both symposia is that whether a state has declared a state of emergency is not a reliable indicator of potentially abusive executive practices. Such practices include the targeting of populations in vulnerable circumstances: for example, the Romani in Slovakia (state of emergency), prisoners in Peru (state of emergency), and religious minorities in India (no state of emergency) and Bangladesh (no state of emergency). The wider sociopolitical context is a stronger factor in gauging the likelihood of abusive practices. The autocratizing states of Hungary (declared a state of emergency) and Poland (no declared state of emergency) have both taken advantage of the pandemic to further consolidate executive power, to the detriment of the separation of powers and democratic checks and balances, with the former taking the opportunity to adopt emergency legislation empowering the executive to amend any law of any value in a way which is all but immune from any legislative scrutiny,Footnote 17 and the latter adopting questionable restrictions on human rights via executive decrees rather than through parliamentary statute, as required by the constitution for such a limitation of fundamental rights.Footnote 18 Paired with the temporary closure of courts, or the restriction of access to only a limited type of cases, and compounded by a pre-pandemic trend toward the demolition of judicial independence in both states, any effective judicial remedy is all but moot.Footnote 19

The essential focus, therefore, should be the use and not the form of power, and whether safeguards in the form of legislative oversight and/or judicial review have been effectively utilized – not whether they exist at all. However, this appears all the more challenging in times of crisis if both legislatures and the courts tend to be deferential to the actions of the executive and unwilling to exercise robust forms of oversight or review.Footnote 20 Such experience also lends support to the argument of Mexican Supreme Court Justice Alfredo Gutiérrez Ortiz Mena that while courts should be more deferential in cases where formally declared exceptions have been declared, they should exercise heightened review (“strict scrutiny”) of the arrogation of ordinary powers by the executive even in times of crisis.Footnote 21

However, there is also emerging evidence of good practices which are not dependent on an emergency/ordinary powers dichotomy, and instead reveals good governance practices inculcated within the wider sociopolitical ecosystem. Those states which aligned law and policy with principles of legality and legal certainty, as well as clarity in public communication, scrutiny, transparency in decision-making, and publication of underlying rationale for (in)action, and engagement with external expertise, civil society, and criticism to reform law and policy have, more often, correlated with higher levels of both public trust and compliance.Footnote 22 These practices are essential to effective strategies to combat the virus and the preservation of democratic legitimacy. By correlating infection and mortality rates with levels of restriction adopted, and the impact on ordinary life and governance, we can highlight countries from among the symposia which have epitomized this approach. For example, New Zealand’s strategy of early response and engaging a combination of ordinary powers aided by some emergency provisions, and framed by recommendations and social nudges, along with robust parliamentary oversight and government accountability, have correlated not only with lower infection rates but also high levels of public trust. Such practices are evident among the responses of the “best responders” to COVID-19:Footnote 23 Finland, Iceland, Singapore, South Korea, and Taiwan. However, such “political trust needs to be continually earned, and traditions of transparency are deeply ingrained; they do not begin during pandemics.”Footnote 24

In sum, the symposia have revealed that the use of power within the wider sociopolitical context, not the form of legal authority, should be the starting point for reimagining democratic controls to contain abuses of civil liberties. First, conditionality within either constitutional provisions or domestic legal frameworks, or even under obligations to international standards on the use of emergency powers, cannot alone limit abuse. Second, neither the declaration of a state of exception nor the exclusive reliance on ordinary legislative powers is a reliable indicator of the likelihood of abuse of power during the pandemic. A stronger indicator, albeit one often more difficult to identify than legal text, is the sociopolitical ecosystem in which legal measures are operating: autocratizing states have capitalized on the emergency to further consolidate power, despite formal legal or constitutional safeguards, while states inculcating democratic values of trust and accountability prior to the pandemic, by contrast, have embodied these values in response. Thus, efforts to reform in order to mitigate the dangers of excessive restriction, arbitrary discrimination, and hypertrophied executive action through formal legal rules alone are largely ineffective, and must instead focus on building a robust democratic system of an independent judiciary and on encouraging active government engagement with parliamentary processes, including debate, review, and scrutiny.

III Health, Health Systems, and Democratic Decision-Making

The pandemic has brought far greater attention to connections between population health and health systems, on the one hand, and democratic legitimacy of government actions, on the other. The pandemic revealed clearly that inequalities in access to care, as well as in outcomes, reflect larger patterns of discrimination and marginalization within societies, and that normative commitments to the equal dignity of diverse members of the society is encoded in health systems, just as it is in justice systems, for example.Footnote 25 Reflections on these symposia suggest that it is insufficient to examine whether health-related rights (including the right to life with dignity when interpreted to include aspects of health care, e.g., India) are enshrined directly in constitutional norms or incorporated from international human rights law through constitutional blocs. It is just as critical to understand the structural conditions that enable health-related rights to be exercised in practice, including the formal and informal practices of subjecting health policies to democratic justification.

COVID-19 struck a world already reeling from multiple waves of austerity. Even in countries where universal health care is guaranteed under law (e.g., the Netherlands and the United Kingdom), the symposia underscored that governments’ role in financing and provision of public health and care has shrunk dramatically over the last few decades. Indeed, just as socioeconomic rights, such as health, were being formulated and incorporated into constitutions across much of the world, including in most states represented in the symposia, neoliberal economic governance has driven reductions in budgets for public health and increased privatization of health care sectors. International financial institutions have played no small part in driving these trends in the Global South. From the late 1980s to today, loan conditions attached to structural adjustment, fiscal consolidation, and the like have prompted steep cuts in public health spending, the flexibilization of labor in health sectors, increasingly stringent intellectual property restrictions on access to medicines imposed through trade agreements, and the privatization of services and supply chains, together with sweeping disruptions in social determinants of health.Footnote 26 At the same time, the political capacity to resolve social demands for health has been constrained by loan agreements that convert these fiscal issues or trade-related aspects of intellectual property into questions for technocratic expert panels to resolve.Footnote 27

Therefore, it is unsurprising that despite health rights being enshrined in constitutional law in each case, contributions to the symposia suggest that countries with well-functioning health care systems, particularly those considered “sacrosanct” in the political culture (e.g., Canada), are inevitably better placed to tackle a major health crisis than those with weak or dysfunctional health systems (e.g., South Africa, Argentina, and Colombia) or those whose systems were already in a state of total collapse prior to the crisis (e.g., Ecuador). Nor is it surprising that chronic shortages are often further compounded by widescale corruption when a sudden influx of emergency funds incentivizes opportunism (e.g., Nepal). However, this insight points to the need for international and comparative legal analysis to pay closer attention not just to the grafting or importing of human rights into domestic law,Footnote 28 but also to the structural changes needed, to ensure the infrastructure for fair provision, locally and globally, that legal frameworks based on neoliberal imperatives have made impossible.

The symposia further highlight the importance of decision-making processes in relation to health to the meaningfulness of health rights in practice, as well as the preservation of democratic legitimacy. At one level, at least since Rudolf Virchow’s work on the social origins of disease and the need to address epidemics through political, not merely medical, means, there has there been an awareness of public health policies and health systems as sites of democratic contestation.Footnote 29 As already noted, movements for universal health coverage were often struggles for democratic inclusion. The more recent technocratic conceptualization of health is a contingent historical response to increasingly neoliberal socioeconomic transformations, coupled with technological innovations based on accelerating medicalization after World War II, and biomedicalization in the twenty-first century.Footnote 30

Nonetheless, by the time COVID-19 emerged, decision-making processes regarding health, within health systems and beyond, had largely been exiled from democratic deliberation to insulated islands of professional expertise. As a result, during the pandemic, we have witnessed the widespread adoption of an overly simplistic dichotomy of “objective scientific truth versus political power,” coupled with considerable partisan politicization across a number of the countries included in one or both of the symposia (e.g., Brazil under President Bolsonaro and the United States under President Trump). In both symposia, this dichotomy has become encapsulated in the tension of who is (and should be) the decisionmaker, marking often a radical reformulation of roles – for example, “doctor as politician” in Croatia,Footnote 31 and “public opinion as epidemiologists” in the Netherlands.Footnote 32 Devi Sridhar, a leading public health academic, deploys an analogy to express the need for deference to infectious disease experts in setting policy: “It’s like being on a plane and the engine does not work. Everyone gives their opinion on what should happen instead of trusting the people who have engineering experience and have done that for years.”Footnote 33

However, there is a difference between politicized dismissal or cherry-picking of empirical scientific evidence and accepting that the forms of knowledge needed to respond to COVID-19 in a democracy have inherently political dimensions that go beyond the expertise of infectious disease specialists and epidemiologists. As Sheila Jasanoff wrote before the pandemic, in relation to science more broadly than health, “risk”:

is not a matter of simple probabilities, to be rationally calculated by experts and avoided in accordance with the cold arithmetic of cost-benefit analysis …. Critically important questions of risk management cannot be addressed by technical experts with conventional tools of prediction. Such questions determine not only whether we will get sick or die, and under what conditions, but also who will be affected and how we should live with uncertainty and ignorance.Footnote 34

In the reflections from both symposia, and throughout this pandemic, measures implemented to prevent or slow the spread of the virus have had a disproportionately negative impact on vulnerable populations, including the elderly, prisoners, persons with physical or mental disabilities, migrants, racial and ethnic minorities, and refugees and migrant workers. Analyses across countries of different income levels (e.g., Spain, Ireland, Chile, Colombia, Kenya) noted that the sudden onset of mass unemployment among part-time and informal workers, the shutdown of childcare and schools, and stay-at-home orders that led to spikes in domestic violence, had devastating impacts on women. For the millions living with poverty, malnutrition, or with high rates of potential comorbidities, including tuberculosis and HIV, in cramped conditions and with limited access to water (e.g., Argentina, Guatemala, Nepal, Nigeria, and South Africa), the most prevalent political and medical messaging of “stay home and wash your hands” ignored endemic socioeconomic disparity and the underlying structural inequalities which have enabled and embedded it.

There is no reason to believe that public health expertise offers a privileged domain of knowledge in weighing containment of transmission against losing access to other socioeconomic rights and basic needs, such as food, housing, and education. Indeed, Dr. Jonathan Mann, a founder of the “health and human rights movement,” argued based on his experience with HIV/AIDS that all “health policies and programs should be considered discriminatory and burdensome on human rights until proven otherwise.”Footnote 35 In the different dynamics of the COVID-19 pandemic, policies dictated by utilitarian calculations of public health experts have shown themselves to be particularly apt to be rife with blind spots. Cloaked in an aura of objective, apolitical “scientificity,” and justified under the idea of safeguarding an unchallengeable good, which is made to appear of heightened necessity when coupled with a generalized fear, these prescriptions are insulated from normal democratic deliberation.

Further, the fallaciously denominated “health versus wealth” tradeoff – public health restrictions versus opening the economy – has in many countries involved dueling fields of expertise and cost-benefit calculations between economists and public health experts, as opposed to enlarging our imagination of how decisions regarding health can be brought into the realm of public reason. As Jasanoff and Hilgartner assert, as both national and international authorities consider the lessons of COVID-19:

they should revisit their established institutional processes for integrating scientific and political consensus-building. If free citizens are unable to see how expertise is serving the collective good, at all levels of governance, they will sooner rebel against expert authority than give up their independence. Just as a sound mind is said to require a sound body, so COVID-19 has shown that the credibility and legitimacy of public health expertise depends on the health of the entire body politic.Footnote 36

As reflected in the symposia, the pandemic has only heightened the urgency of grappling with the lack of public accountability and democracy in current health governance across most of the world, and imagining new institutions, processes, and methods for restoring normative questions to addressing health policy in pandemic and “normal” times. The critical role of reasoned justification for how health systems function has often been evidenced by its absence during COVID-19. For example, decisions regarding what services are deemed “essential” have often disproportionately affected sexual and reproductive health and rights.

Insights provided by both symposia indicate that decisions on whom to prioritize and where to allocate testing and treatment have also been questioned (e.g., Croatia, Slovakia, Nepal, and the Netherlands). Across societies, evidence suggests that the social legitimacy of health decisions, just as in others, is based on both sociohistorical context and in the case of local health systems the slow building of trust, which does not happen overnight when a pandemic breaks out. The reflections in these symposia confirm lessons from previous epidemics (e.g., HIV/AIDS and Ebola) in that the best way to implement public health policies, as well as preserve the legitimacy of the health system and government more broadly, is to engage a wider number of constituencies in a meaningful and equitable manner on an ongoing basis, as opposed to undertaking ad hoc consultations during times of crisis.

Whether allocating vaccines or scarce equipment, supplies, and treatments, which follow different logics, there is growing agreement among health ethicists that decision-making processes regarding health require the same principles suggested earlier for the promulgation of COVID-19 measures more broadly – as well as for expectations of democratic decision-making in general. These include: (1) explicit justification and transparency of rationales; (2) transparency about empirical and normative uncertainty; (3) openness to address and include diverse perspectives on competing criteria for decisions, ranking of criteria, and why they matter; (4) inclusion of the perspectives of marginalized and disadvantaged populations as to the formulation of choice criteria, as well as disparate impacts; (5) willingness to revise policy decisions in light of populations’ negative experiences with implemented decisions and critical feedback on the rationales for the decisions; and (6) regulation and enforcement of (1) to (5).Footnote 37 In addition to including distinct constituencies in specific allocation decisions or the tradeoffs between containment and other health concerns, such as mental health, reflections on the first phase of pandemic response in the symposia, together with other studies,Footnote 38 suggest that democratizing health policy requires making visible how the issues are framed in legal and policy analysis, including structural forms of subordination and exclusion that invariably affect distributions of health and ill-health.

In sum, the effectiveness, as well as legitimacy, of governmental responses to COVID-19 call for thinking more deeply about the role of health systems as democratic social institutions and the ways in which they formally and informally enshrine normative values from macro to micro levels in both pandemics and normal times. As Scott Burris argues, health law is not a matter of “just the formal rules, but how these rules are enacted every day” by the health care program implementers and providers, as well as users of the system.Footnote 39 The meaning of health rights, and health laws more broadly, invariably depends upon how multiple actors understand how they relate to other sets of rules and norms beyond the health system. Neither constitutionalization nor legislation enshrining health rights in formal law is an adequate indicator of the normative and social legitimacy of specific health policymaking and priority-setting in practice. Structural conditions underpinning meaningful access, together with the nature of processes for making health-related decisions and setting priorities, are equally critical.

Bringing health policy under the purview of public reason, as is taken for granted with respect to other rights, will likely call for a paradigm shift that enables diverse persons to see public health and access to care in normal times, as well as pandemics, not as the domain of technocratic experts alone, but as assets of (social) citizenship.

IV Conclusion

The global but differentiated impacts of the sweeping COVID-19 pandemic present an opportunity, and an imperative, for reflection on the legal, social, and institutional changes required for advancing public health, as well as for strengthening the rule of law moving forward. Joint reflections on the contributions to the symposia, together with other scholarship, suggest at least three insights for building stronger democratic institutional structures to withstand the pressures both of pandemic and autocratizing forces. First, the use of power within the wider sociopolitical context, not the form of legal authority, should be the starting point for reimagining democratic controls to contain abuses of civil liberties. Second, the institutional arrangements and structural conditions necessary to ensure access to public health, as well as to medical care, are as important as formal legislative regimes enshrining health-related rights. Third, democratic decision-making processes that include participation by a wide array of experts, as well as by constituencies affected, afford space to critique government (in)action, and are linked to responsive reforms are more effective both in producing equitable health outcomes and in preserving confidence in the rule of law. In short, the COVID-19 pandemic has illustrated starkly that health, perhaps more dramatically than any other area of law and policy, involves what Britton-Purdy et al. refer to as “the need for political judgments about the gravest questions: who should exercise power, of what sort, and over whom? What should count as a human need, and what claims should politically recognized needs give us against the state and thus against one another? Whose dreams come true, and who is enlisted in the realization of others’ schemes?”Footnote 40

24 A Tale of Two Crises COVID-19, Climate Change, and Crisis Response

Daniel Farber
I Introduction

A viral pandemic and a change in global climate are utterly dissimilar in a physical sense. The pandemic is an abrupt emergency, while climate change is a long-term problem, though one requiring an urgent response. In a sense, both can be considered crises. Despite their differences, the pandemic and the climate crisis have many linkages. The response to the pandemic can impact the carbon emissions that drive climate change, while the pandemic’s economic effect may prompt government responses which impact such emissions. In the meantime, efforts to respond to this public health crisis and to the climate crisis must both contend with the frailties of human nature and of existing political institutions.

Section I of this chapter investigates the effect of COVID-19 on carbon emissions. There was a sharp initial reduction in emissions, with the question being how much of this reduction, if any, will persist. Section II turns to the possible impact of economic recovery measures on climate change. Some jurisdictions planned green recoveries, which may succeed in accelerating the transition to a low-carbon economy. Part III discusses the governance issues that have arisen regarding climate change and the pandemic; these governance issues have proved remarkably similar. Part IV then offers some concluding thoughts about the relationship between these two global crises.

II The Impact of the Pandemic on Carbon Emissions

The linkages between COVID-19 and climate change are complex. One connection involves fossil fuel consumption, which declined during lockdowns. Fossil fuel use is the primary cause of climate change, but may also indirectly increase susceptibility to COVID-19. Fossil fuels are also prime sources for ultra-fine particulates (known technically as PM2.5) due to emissions by power plants and vehicles. Several studies connect past air pollution levels with COVID-19 mortality rates, which is not surprising given the general association between air pollution and susceptibility to respiratory diseases. A 2019 study linked PM2.5 to 200,000 US deaths per year, mostly due to respiratory and cardiovascular issues.Footnote 1 A Harvard study found that an increase of one microgram per cubic meter in PM2.5 causes an 8 percent increase in the COVID-19 death rate.Footnote 2 Thus, jurisdictions that had taken steps to reduce carbon emissions may also have indirectly helped themselves in terms of the pandemic by reducing vulnerability due to PM2.5.

Another indirect connection between COVID-19 and climate change relates to extreme weather events, which climate change has amplified. Certain disaster response efforts, including evacuations and mass sheltering, provide opportunities for viral contagion, helping exacerbate the pandemic.Footnote 3

The most direct linkage, however, ties COVID-19 to economic dislocation and then to carbon emissions. It was initially expected that the economic shutdown associated with the virus would at least have the beneficial side effect of reducing carbon emissions. That direct effect on emissions seems to have been transitory. As we will see, however, some of the economic changes caused by the pandemic may have longer-lasting impacts on emissions.

Initially in China and then across the globe, the pandemic slashed economic activity and shut down transportation. By April 2020, emissions had fallen by about 17 percent globally and 25 percent in the United States.Footnote 4 But by mid-June, global emissions had begun to recover, leading to a roughly 9 percent decline below 2019 levels in the first half of 2020. In the United States, the Energy Information Agency estimated a 10 percent drop in carbon emissions for 2020 as a whole, with a 6 percent rebound in 2021 as the economy recovered.Footnote 5 Even if the 2020 emission cuts had been permanent, they would have been far less than what is required to meet global emissions targets.Footnote 6

In China, the world’s largest carbon emitter, emissions dropped 20 percent in early 2020, but then rebounded by April 2020 to 2019 levels, or slightly above.Footnote 7 The planning, permitting, and construction of new coal-fired power plants leaped in the first half of 2020.Footnote 8 Yet the central government also announced efforts to prioritize clean energy, cross-province transmission, and flexibility measures.Footnote 9 Thus, it is not clear how the pandemic will impact longer-term emissions growth.

The impact of the pandemic on the global oil industry was especially severe. Because of COVID-19-related restrictions on travel and the general economic downturn, oil prices crashed by almost 50 percent between December 2019 and March 2020.Footnote 10 In some cases, prices went negative, with well owners having to pay to have oil taken off their hands.Footnote 11 At one point, some oil futures dropped momentarily to a price of negative $37 as producers anticipated having to pay firms to take charge of their oil.Footnote 12 The price collapse seems to have accelerated trends in the industry due to the long-term prospects for oil usage. By June 2020, major oil companies such as Shell and BP were writing down the values of their oil and gas assets by tens of billions of dollars.Footnote 13 In September 2020, BP announced a radical shift in its strategic planning, away from petroleum and toward renewable energy.Footnote 14 The decline of the industry is mixed news in terms of emissions. The direct effect of a shift away from oil would clearly be beneficial. Yet there is also a risk connected with the economic decline of the industry. As demand declines, wells go out of use, and less solvent or responsible operators may simply abandon marginal wells without properly capping them. Those abandoned wells may result in significant environmental problems, including leakage of methane, a potent greenhouse gas.Footnote 15 Further uncertainties and additional strategic shifts took place in the aftermath of the Russian invasion of Ukraine, which abruptly raised global oil and gas prices.

The longer-term impacts of the pandemic on transportation remain uncertain. Telecommuting increased dramatically in some countries in the early days of the pandemic, with nearly all workers who were allowed to do so engaging in the practice.Footnote 16 By September 2020, about 12 percent of those workers had returned to the workplace in the United States, although trends were quite different in various occupations. To the extent that telecommuting remains common after the pandemic, the result should be a decline in the carbon emissions associated with commuting. It also remains to be seen how much business and educational travel may be replaced by the use of electronic media even after the pandemic ends.

A more ominous possibility is a permanent decline in public transportation. During the pandemic, use of public transit declined precipitously, leaving public transportation systems in a perilous financial condition. Experts warn of the possibility that service cuts could send public transportation into a “death spiral” in which financial woes lead to service cuts, which decrease ridership and thereby lead to deeper financial distress.Footnote 17 The end result could be to throw more riders back into cars, resulting in far greater emissions.

Forecasting the long-term impacts of COVID-19 on the economy or society more generally is difficult. It could result in permanent shifts in some economic sectors or in broader societal trends, such as increasing appreciation of the governmental role in controlling risk, the need for investment in public health, and deference to experts. Alternatively, it could turn out to be merely a blip in terms of longer-term trends, with little or no long-term impact. We have little precedent to draw upon in making predictions. The last pandemic of similar severity took place under very different circumstances over a century ago in the form of the 1918 influenza. As Robert Schiller, a Nobel-Prize winning economist, has pointed out: “Big events like a pandemic have the potential to leave behind a trail of disruption. They can create social discord, reduce people’s willingness to spend and take risks, destroy business momentum and shake confidence in the value of investments.”Footnote 18 Prediction is fraught even for experts. As Schiller explains, “[e]pisodes as far-reaching as this one are scarce, widely spaced in time, and so different in circumstances that statisticians cannot easily compare them systematically.”Footnote 19

III A Path Forward

It is possible that the most important long-term climate effect of the pandemic, at least in some jurisdictions, will involve the economic recovery rather than the pandemic itself. Economic stimulus proved necessary to deal with the economic downturn. The biggest question was whether the economic recovery could be used to promote sustainability. Economic stimulus measures offer the opportunity for major investments in low-carbon technologies, which could accelerate the energy transition. Experience has shown permanent beneficial effects from stimulus spending on green infrastructure and energy-related research and development.

International institutions strongly advocated using the recovery to accelerate the energy transition away from fossil fuels. In a speech making the case for a green recovery, the deputy managing director of the International Monetary Fund said: “Let me end by emphasizing that the time to act, especially with lower oil prices, is now. The decisions we take now will shape economies and the global system for decades. Europe must, and is, setting a high bar that should galvanize action elsewhere.”Footnote 20 Along the same lines, the International Energy Agency produced an ambitious green recovery plan requiring investment of $3 trillion over three years.Footnote 21 The agency estimated that its plan would increase global gross domestic product by 1.1 percent every year it was in effect, create nine million jobs per year, and result in a $4.5 billion ton decrease in annual emissions by 2023.Footnote 22

One ambitious green stimulus to date has been adopted by the European Union.Footnote 23 Out of €1.8 trillion euro ($2 trillion) in funding, almost a third of the spending targets climate action. The stimulus targets €91 billion euros per year for EU grants and loan guarantees for building improvements, such as rooftop solar panels and insulation, at least €20 billion for developing hydrogen as an energy source, another €20 billion for adding 15 gigawatts of renewable generation, €20 billion more for zero-emissions vehicles, and €40–60 billion for zero-emission trains.Footnote 24 The spending deal was greeted enthusiastically by the German environmental minister. She commented that: “[n]ever before, has so much of an EU budget been allocated to combating climate change. The commitments to climate action and environmental protection are important and necessary, but the distribution of funds must reflect that.”Footnote 25

Some individual European countries also invested heavily in a green recovery. About a third of Germany’s $145 billion stimulus plan was directed to public transportation, electric vehicles, and renewable energy.Footnote 26 Meanwhile, France invested $8.8 billion in a plan to become the main producer of electric vehicles in Europe.Footnote 27 In November 2020, the United Kingdom announced a plan for a “green industrial revolution,” with an investment of £12 billion, building on £5 billion committed to a green recovery.Footnote 28 Some countries have also imposed conditions on funding. Sweden required Scandinavian Airlines to accelerate its goal of a 25 percent reduction in emissions by five years, whereas the French required a 50 percent emission cut for Air France as a funding condition.Footnote 29

East Asia has seen significant green recovery efforts.Footnote 30 China is investing $1.4 billion in charging infrastructure,Footnote 31 and possibly much more in other green stimulus funding.Footnote 32 Like China, Korea and Singapore are also emphasizing spending on electric vehicles.Footnote 33 Climate action also figured in recovery plans elsewhere. Nigeria’s stimulus included $620 million for rooftop solar, while Colombia’s plan includes $4 billion for zero-carbon energy and transmission.Footnote 34 It is possible, however, that the after-effects of the economic recession due to COVID-19, along with the economic dislocations caused by the Ukraine invasion, might impair the financial ability of some countries to address climate change going forward.

In terms of COVID-related spending, $26 billion of the massive US COVID-19 spending program has been devoted to rail transit and mass transit, the only “green” components of the spending plan.Footnote 35 Subsequently, Congress passed major legislation with massive spending for infrastructure and climate-related incentives.Footnote 36 It is unclear how closely related these projects are to the COVID pandemic, since they are not framed in terms of pandemic response. The precedent of large scale spending set during the pandemic may, however, eased the way politically for this additional legislation.

Even if the direct effects of COVID-19 on emissions turn out to be transitory, a green stimulus may be more durable. Experience from the Great Recession provides at least suggestive evidence of long-term impacts from stimulus funding. On the heels of the 2008 financial crisis, the US Congress enacted a stimulus plan providing $90 billion for renewable energy and energy efficiency.Footnote 37 By many accounts, that 10 percent chunk of the stimulus bill changed the trajectory of renewables in America. By 2011, the United States had reached the Energy Information Agency’s forecast of US renewable capacity for 2030.Footnote 38 Due to the stimulus and other policy initiatives, “U.S. solar electricity generation increased over 30 times from 2008 to 2015, and wind generation has increased over three times.”Footnote 39 Moreover, the “share of wind turbine equipment manufactured domestically rose from 25 percent in 2006–07 to 72 percent in 2012.”Footnote 40

Globally, there is also reason to believe that the green stimulus programs of the Great Recession strengthened national efforts significantly. According to researchers at the World Resource Institute, “[t]he United States, China, and Germany became renewable energy leaders in part because of programs coming out of the Great Recession.”Footnote 41 Meanwhile, “China’s solar PV [photovoltaic] manufacturing capacity increased by a factor of 20 between 2007 and 2011.”Footnote 42 Proof of causation is difficult given the difficulty of establishing the pathway that these countries would have taken absent the Great Recession. Nevertheless, the evidence is certainly suggestive of a causal link.

The EU and countries such as Korea are leveraging their pandemic recovery efforts to reduce their emissions and strengthen sectors of their economy relating to clean energy. Other countries may have allowed the opportunity to slip by. Still others lacked the resources to undertake green recovery efforts of their own. These heterogeneous responses may widen the gap between the laggards and the leaders in clean technologies and climate action.

Like public health responses to the pandemic, economic recovery efforts implicate national governance systems, as does climate policy. The next section discusses the lessons of the pandemic response for future efforts to control emissions. As it turns out, despite their very different natures, there are strong resemblances between the governance issues exposed by the pandemic and the governance challenges facing climate action.

IV The Pandemic Response and Climate Governance

What can we learn from COVID-19 about what works and does not work in governance?

How will COVID-19 impact future international cooperation?

While the COVID-19 crisis could end up advancing climate action, it has mixed lessons for climate governance. Like the response to climate change, the response to COVID-19 has been loosely coordinated at the international level and often featured bottom-up action by local jurisdictions. As the public health response to COVID-19 demonstrates, policies that require costly behavioral changes are difficult to implement, particularly over longer time periods.

Moreover, populist movements and leaders pose a challenge to global (and sometimes even national) cooperation. To be successful, climate governance will have to learn from the successes and failures of the coronavirus responses.

Globally, the direct response to the pandemic has largely taken place at the national or regional level, with international institutions largely playing a supportive role.Footnote 43 Some nations responded vigorously to the crisis. In the United States, the Trump Administration did not press for aggressive public health measures in order to avoid burdening the US economy through public health measures.Footnote 44 President Trump also withdrew the United States from the World Health Organization (WHO).Footnote 45 State governments, to varying extents, implemented their own public health measures.Footnote 46 As with climate change, partisan and ideological affiliations are the main determinants of public attitudes toward public health responses to the pandemic.Footnote 47

The picture for climate policy is quite similar. Just as he withdrew the United States from the WHO, President Trump withdrew the country from the Paris Agreement.Footnote 48 As in the case of COVID-19, the Trump Administration prioritized the economy over addressing environmental problems.Footnote 49 The Trump Administration has also systematically eliminated prior federal efforts to reduce carbon emissions.Footnote 50 The lack of any sustained federal effort to address climate change created a policy vacuum.

As with the pandemic response, climate action in the United States was largely bottom up, with the initiative coming from state and local governments.Footnote 51 Unlike public health, where states have historically taken the lead (partly for constitutional reasons), environmental protection has generally been dominated by federal regulation. In a deviation from that pattern, states have addressed climate change on many fronts.Footnote 52 They have also been active in promoting renewable energy, sometimes under the climate umbrella and sometimes independently. Many states have adopted renewable portfolio standards mandating that utilities obtain a certain percentage of electricity of the electricity they sell in the state from renewable sources. By forcing utilities to buy renewable energy, these mandates promote the development of more solar and wind energy.Footnote 53 There are significant variations in these standards from state to state.Footnote 54

Some states have gone further to reduce the use of fossil fuels by adopting cap and trade schemes. In 2006, Governor Arnold Schwarzenegger signed the California Global Warming Solutions Act, usually referred to as AB 32,Footnote 55 which required California to reduce emissions to the 1990 level by 2020. As another important example of state-level action to address climate change, nine eastern states combined to form the Regional Greenhouse Gas Initiative (RGGI, pronounced “Reggie”).Footnote 56 RGGI created a multistate emissions trading system for power plant emissions with the goal of cutting emissions. This “polycentric” response has been characteristic of climate policy.Footnote 57

Both the efforts to combat climate change and the response to the pandemic have been hindered by the resurgence of populism in many parts of the world. Populist nationalism undermines international cooperation, which is essential for dealing with global threats such as pandemics and climate change. Populism also undermines faith in experts, leading to a willingness to disregard expert views in favor of misinformation. President Trump embodied both aspects of populism, but he was not alone. In Brazil, President Jair Bolsonaro followed a similar path for the coronavirus,Footnote 58 as well for climate change.Footnote 59 Though neither remain in office, the risks posed by populism continue.

Underlying the shared governance issues for climate change and the pandemic are psychological and sociopolitical commonalities. Humans can be taken unaware in situations where change is not linear but instead shows dramatic or exponential growth.Footnote 60 They can also do poorly with respect to anticipating that their own actions can unintentionally cause great harm.Footnote 61 These psychological issues have been amplified by political divisions. Just as they are often more skeptical of vigorous political action to address climate change, those on the political right tended toward delayed responses to the disease, resisted stringent control measures, and were receptive to early termination of control measures.Footnote 62 Conservative media have played a significant role in fostering these attitudes, even controlling for the ideology of the audience members.Footnote 63 This political divide has been most obvious in the United States, but is echoed elsewhere in the world.Footnote 64 Political preferences plus psychological barriers have combined to provide fertile ground for conspiracy theories stoked by Internet misinformation efforts.Footnote 65

Both crises also share a common hope that technological advances may be crucial to long-term solutions, meaning vaccines in the case of COVID-19 and advanced energy technologies in the case of climate change. But technology is not a deus ex machina that will save the day on its own. People must be educated about the value of vaccines, and hundreds of millions (ultimately billions) of doses must be distributed and administered. The emergence of variants may require continued advances in vaccine design and renewed efforts by governments to ensure the manufacture and broad distribution of subsequent booster shots. With regards to climate change, coordinated changes must be made in electricity systems along with incentives to abandon existing assets in favor of massive new investments. Thus, government policy will retain a critical role in both crises.

V Conclusion

The COVID-19 outbreak has several links with the issue of climate change. The restrictions adopted in many places in response to the coronavirus caused an immediate decline in carbon emissions, although the impact on emissions faded over time. The effect on the transportation system may prove longer lasting, perhaps for good (in substituting virtual meetings for physical ones) and for bad (in undermining public transit). In some places, green recovery programs may provide a route to accelerating the energy transition, with long-term economic and environmental effects. Thus, the longer-term effects of the pandemic on emissions remain uncertain but are likely to be mixed on balance.

Despite their obvious differences, the pandemic and the climate crisis have encountered similar governance institutions and political trends, and with similar effects. Bottom-up governance has featured heavily in both responses, with nations and subnational jurisdictions playing the leading roles. Efforts to respond to both crises have run into headwinds due to the global upsurges in nationalism and populism, which have frustrated efforts at global cooperation and undermined support for the measures recommended by experts. Unfortunately, there is no solution in sight to the weaknesses in governance systems, which will continue to be a source of frustration. At the same time, we can take some satisfaction from the partial successes which we have been able to achieve, despite the frailties of human nature and the flaws in human governance.

25 Vaccine Tourism, Federalism, Nationalism

I. Glenn Cohen Footnote *
I Introduction

In early January 2021, the news stories started rolling out focused on so-called “vaccine tourism” to the sunny state of Florida. Non-Floridians were getting the coveted Pfizer and Moderna vaccines that were severely limited in supply. There were reports of a “celebrity lawyer from Argentina [who] got the vaccine while she was visiting Florida,” and an Argentine television personality whose mother was vaccinated in Miami.Footnote 1 Two “India travel agencies … reportedly market[ed] vaccine travel packages,” including roundtrip airfare and “a shot upon arrival” for two thousand dollars.Footnote 2 And, closer to home, a travel insurance broker in Canada reported that many of his clients who typically flew south for the winter but had decided to stay put were changing their minds once friends told them they could travel to Miami and get vaccinated, rather than waiting months or longer in Canada.Footnote 3

Government officials in Florida were none too pleased. The mayor of Miami chafed, “[i]t’s sort of a slap in the face to this community that is desperately trying to get vaccinated.”Footnote 4 Florida’s governor initially tried to distinguish different kinds of non-Floridians seeking vaccines:

[I]t is difficult to block non-residents from getting vaccinated because Florida attracts so many snowbirds.

“We’re a transient state,” DeSantis said Monday during a news conference in Miami. “You’ll have people that will be here and it’s not like they’re just on vacation for two weeks.”

Still, while it would be difficult to turn away snowbirds, tourists who are “flying by night” are a different matter, DeSantis said. “We’re discouraging people who come to Florida just to get a vaccine,” he said.Footnote 5

By late January, the state sought to do more than “discourag[e]” those from out of state or out of country from vaccination in Florida; amidst some confusion, the state sought to restrict vaccine access to “those who can prove state residency using a state driver’s license or other official documents, such as a deed, rental agreement or utility bill.”Footnote 6

Was it right to do so? This chapter analyses the phenomenon of vaccine tourism and seeks to answer that question. Section I situates vaccine tourism in the larger phenomenon of medical tourism and describes what is undesirable about it. Section II seeks to answer the question of when a state should try to prevent international vaccine tourism head-on, arguing that states should adopt a communitarian conception of who qualifies that is tied to the purpose of the good in question. For vaccines, such a conception makes it appropriate for states to prohibit “tourists” from coming to a state such as Florida from abroad for the purpose of getting vaccinated. At the same time, this rationale does not justify excluding undocumented persons or even those who are not permanent residents but who have substantial ties to the community, such as part-time residents. Section III considers objections to the argument and briefly highlights some adjacent issues, such as whether interstate vaccine tourism is different from international vaccine tourism in the ethical analysis. Throughout this chapter, I use the state of Florida in the United States as my “home state” and the United States as my “home country” for ease of exposition, but I mean the arguments I offer to be more generally applicable. One editorial note as I review the proofs in April 2023: this chapter was written during the height of the COVID-19 pandemic. It reflects the facts on the ground as they then stood and captures my thinking while being “in the thick of it.” I have resisted the impulse to “Monday morning quarterback,” that is, to go back and change parts of it to reflect what actually transpired after I wrote it.

II What Is Worrisome About Vaccine Tourism?

“Vaccine tourism” might be thought of as a subspecies of “medical tourism” or “medical travel.” As defined in my prior work, it involves patients traveling from one country (the home country) to another country (the destination country) for treatment.Footnote 7 Vaccine tourism resembles most forms of medical tourism that involve “queue jumping,” such as a Canadian patient in need of a hip replacement traveling to a US state and paying for it out of pocket, rather than waiting for her turn on her home province’s wait list.Footnote 8

Vaccine tourism shares three ethically worrisome aspects with that queue jumping example. First, there is a concern that only those who are sophisticated, able-bodied, and wealthy enough to travel can take advantage of this opportunity. In the case of COVID-19, there is no reason to think that the “vaccine tourism eligible” population matches the populations that we might be most inclined to prioritize for vaccination – those who are at higher risk by virtue of health status, community spread, or workplace exposure. There is an additional wrinkle in that there is considerable moral luck in the question of what the ordinary visa regime means for the ability of an individual of a particular country to travel to the United States or another country.

This complication is further highlighted in the early period of the COVID-19 pandemic given the additional extraordinary restrictions on travel between certain countries.

Second, depending on the availability of the COVID-19 vaccine in the destination country, non-citizens and non-residents who queue jump may displace (and thus delay) access for citizens and residents. Importantly, even when COVID-19 vaccine access at some point becomes plentiful in a country such as the United States, vaccine tourism may still foster a problematic displacement of priority: in this case, the doses that are taken by vaccine tourists are ones that might otherwise be donated to the hardest-hit countries, either directly or through programs such as the COVID-19 Vaccines Global Access Facility.Footnote 9

Finally, as with other forms of medical tourism, there is a risk to the patient of being infected with COVID-19 as part of the travel process and a corresponding worry that that patient will infect others. The documented cases of multi-drug resistant bacterial infection spreading via medical travel serve as a precursor to some of what we face in COVID-19 air travel.Footnote 10

All that said, in policy design one always wants to make sure that the cure is not worse than the disease. In thinking about how to discourage or prohibit vaccine tourism for any of the categories discussed in the following section, we want to make sure that the techniques employed do not end up shutting out vulnerable communities. In particular, one might be concerned that overly rigorous requirements for residency documentation might intimidate undocumented persons or those who already feel profiled by the state, preventing them from seeking out vaccination. This is a hard thing to measure, especially ex ante, but one should treat this as a background consideration in policy design related to administrability above and beyond questions of entitlement, to which I turn next.

III Who Is Entitled to a Home Country’s Vaccine Doses?

Given all this, is a state such as Florida (or a country as a whole) justified in adopting legal means to deny vaccine access to vaccine tourists?

My answer is a qualified yes. It is qualified because we need to be careful to distinguish a spectrum of potential vaccine tourists. As to international vaccine tourism, one might conceptualize a spectrum that includes:

Non-citizen/non-resident on a temporary stay: This would include, for example, an Argentine citizen/resident who travels to Florida for the purpose of getting vaccinated and leaves shortly thereafter.

Non-citizen/part-time resident: This would include, for example, the Canadian “snowbird” who travels to Florida under established immigration channels every year for part of the year and resides in that community.

Non-citizen/full-time resident: This category itself contains a spectrum of kinds of relationships with the United States. At one end are permanent aliens who have not (or not yet) applied for US citizenship: for example, a Brazilian citizen with a US green card residing in Florida. Somewhere in the middle of the spectrum is someone with an immigration status which allows them to live in the United States but explicitly does not permit them to transition to citizenship, a temporary status such as a Canadian citizen working in the United States on a TN visa. Then there are individuals who are undocumented workers, non-citizens who as a legal matter have no entitlement to work or live in the country but may have built long-standing ties (indeed, familial connections in some cases) in the country: for example, a Haitian worker in Florida without lawful citizenship or residency in the United States who works and lives with her family in the state.

Citizen/non-resident: This would include, for example, a US citizen who has lived in Bolivia for the last ten years and flies to Florida for a vaccination.

Citizen/resident: This would include, for example, a US citizen who resides in Florida.

Who in this spectrum has an entitlement to be vaccinated in the United States?

When laid out in this way, one can see three possible principles as to who should be entitled to vaccines distributed by a home country government (in this instance, I will continue to use the United States as my example).Footnote 11 First, territoriality: anyone who finds themselves in the United States territory, as a geographical matter, is entitled to a vaccine. Second, citizenship: anyone who is a citizen of the United States is entitled to a vaccine. Third, communitarian: anyone who is a member of the community in the relevant sense is entitled to a vaccine.

These principles could be individually sufficient (e.g., if citizenship is individually sufficient then both the citizen/resident and the citizen/non-resident are entitled to vaccination), or individually necessary (e.g., if citizenship is a necessary condition then all non-citizens must be excluded, even those who reside in the country). Multiple conditions could also be jointly sufficient or jointly necessary. To make things more complicated, while I have framed it as a matter of “entitlement” – an on/off switch – one could have a more nuanced account of priority setting where one who, for example, satisfies all three conditions has priority over someone who satisfies only a particular two, and so on.

All this shows how complex the picture of moral claims to vaccination is. I do not aim to offer a full theory in these few pages, but I do want to use this theorizing to explain why I think citizen/residents, non-citizen/full-time residents, and most (if not all) non-citizen/part-time residents, but not non-citizen/non-residents on a temporary stay, are entitled to vaccines supplied by the US government.

One way of putting this in terms of the theories developed so far is that I would reject a strong version of the territoriality principle in favor of a communitarian principle. Although it is not my focus, I also think there is a strong argument in favor of the citizenship principle, which would also justify vaccine access to US citizens living abroad, in addition to whomever the communitarian principle picks out as entitled to vaccine doses from the United States.

Before I delve into the communitarian approach, I want to raise one assumption of the argument I offer – that the United States is entitled to the doses it has purchased through advance purchase agreements, that these “belong” to the United States to distribute in a way that achieves its goals. While I think most people have assumed that this premise is true, it is not self-evidently true. One could, for example, think that all vaccine doses should be viewed as common global property and allocated by need or some other framework of distribution. For the purposes of this chapter, I am going to just assume that the United States has a claim over the doses it has purchased, if only because I think any other arrangement would be politically impossible to imagine in our current moment. Readers who think this arrangement is unjust can take what follows as an argument operating in the sphere of “non-ideal justice,” or a second (or fifteenth!) best solution.Footnote 12

A Developing the Communitarian Approach Based on the Nature of the Good

The communitarian principle is that anyone who is a member of the community in the relevant sense is entitled to a vaccine. Now we have to unpack what it means to be a member of the community “in the relevant sense” for generating a claim to a US vaccine. Here it might be useful to start with an argument I offered in a 2014 article in which I analyzed a question somewhat similar to vaccine entitlement: Should non-resident/non-citizens (i.e., a French citizen who lives in Paris) be morally entitled to be waitlisted for US organs?Footnote 13 One of the difficult parts of that argument required justifying why a non-citizen/non-resident was not entitled to be waitlisted but an undocumented person living in the United States did have such an entitlement. I justified that on a particular communitarian conception relating to reciprocity:

[T]he key reciprocity is not between organ donation and receiving … but instead is between investment in the infrastructure of organ procurement and allocation and shared decision-making as organs vel non. It is this reciprocity that US citizen-residents share but that foreigners ordinarily lack, and thus this form of reciprocity justifies US citizen-residents’ priority, at least in the case of equally matched foreigners and US citizen-residents.

One interesting implication of this approach is that the strength of the argument varies with the amount that the home country’s citizen-residents (as against foreigners) have invested in or contributed to their country’s organ procurement and allocation system. Undocumented immigrants frequently pay into the US system through social security and other tax resources from which they do not draw, such that we can say that they in fact meet the investment prerequisites. Further, the OPTN [the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, the main organization setting policy for organ procurement and distribution in the U.S.] suggests that they frequently “pay in” more directly through organ donation. Second, the continued presence of undocumented aliens as residents in the United States, both with families and as part of communities, complicates our moral relation to them in a way that is not true in the case of true foreigner.Footnote 14

But, as with most approaches to just distribution, our analysis of what is just must be closely tailored to the good in question. Human organs eligible for transplant, say a kidney, are not collectively owned – most people do not think you have a rights claim to my kidney by virtue of being a fellow citizen or fellow resident of the same country.Footnote 15 The kidney belongs to me, not the United States. That is the reason why the argument for a preference for US residents for organs procured in the United States requires a more roundabout argument about common investment in the system of procurement and distribution by members of the community.

In the case of vaccine doses that are in the possession of the US government, by contrast, these doses really do, in some sense, belong to the United States qua national government. They were purchased by the US government,Footnote 16 purchases that were funded by US taxpayers. Those taxpayers include citizen/residents and many non-citizen/full-time residents. They do not include non-citizen/non-residents.Footnote 17 Whether or not part-time residents qualify as taxpayers may depend on their immigration status, tax treaties between the United States and their country of citizenship, and the amount of time they spend in the United States.

There is a second communitarian pathway worth exploring. This goes more directly to the nature of the good and is, if anything, more straightforward. Why is vaccination sought? To protect oneself and to protect the community in one which lives – be it very small (one’s family), larger (one’s workplace), or larger still (everyone one encounters within a few feet indoors). If this is the “purpose of the good,” to sound somewhat Aristotelian, then the criterion for distribution should follow from it. Those who live in a particular community have a reciprocal relationship of a sort – the capacity to put others at risk of COVID-19 infection and the capacity to be put at risk by the COVID-19 infections of others. This remains just as true whether one is a citizen/resident or an undocumented person.

B How to Treat Part-Time Residents?

How does this criterion of distribution apply to the non-citizen/part-time resident? It seems to me that their entitlement claim scales up in proportion to their comparative risk of infecting or being infected by others in the community. Someone who lives in Florida for six months of the pandemic but then goes home is at substantial risk of being infected or infecting others in Florida during those six months. It would make sense from a public health/purpose of the good perspective to give them an entitlement to the vaccine during their period of Florida residency.

Now, perhaps one might agree that the part-time resident has an entitlement to the vaccine (or, to put this perhaps better, it would not be unjust to provide them a dose) but suggest that they ought to be of lower priority than the citizen/full-time resident, or even the non-citizen/full-time resident. To put this practically, a state such as Florida might roll out its vaccine in waves that put the part-time resident behind similarly situated full-time residents. One way of thinking about this is through a kind of “expected value” analysis tied to the purpose of the good. If the purpose of vaccinating Floridians is to prevent people in Florida from being infected or infecting others and allow the reopening in Florida, then vaccinating a four-month, part-time resident might generate a reduced advance toward that goal in contrast to vaccinating a full-time resident.Footnote 18

As a back-of-the-envelope metric, that may sound plausible, but as we delve deeper into modeling this, I suspect it would show that things are actually considerably more complicated. For example, if we look back at the COVID-19 data, we would likely find that the difference in “expected value” for vaccinating the part-time versus the full-time resident depends on when in the various waves of the virus we were discussing, where the part-time versus full-time residents lived (including where they fall on the social vulnerability index compared to full-time residents), their ages and health statuses, as compared to full-time residents, etc. I suspect we would find as much within-group variability amongst part-time residents as one would between part- and full-time residents, if not more. At the very least, as a matter of principled policy-setting, we ought to demand consistency. That is, if a state favored reduced priority for the part-time resident for this reason, then it should also apply the same reasoning within its full-time resident population and give more priority based on a similar expected value analysis. Perhaps we can characterize some of the decisions that states made regarding priority for the elderly and health care workers in this way.

At some point, though, I think we will reach a place familiar to the law of asking about what has been called “administrability” or “formal realizability” concerns, where the difficulty of administering a rule might matter as much as its fairness.Footnote 19 That is, even if sub-rules that parse the part-time resident community would be more ethically justifiable, at some point the benefits are outweighed by the complexity of the undertaking and the game is no longer worth a candle. Perhaps this point is particularly salient in the COVID-19 vaccine context when we remember how huge an undertaking it was to begin rolling out the vaccine and the goal of doing so as quickly as possible.

Where has all this landed? I have argued that when a state such as Florida decides to whom it should make COVID-19 vaccines available, it certainly should make them available to full-time US citizens who are residents of Florida, as well as full-time non-citizen residents of Florida. I think there is a strong argument for also extending it to part-time residents of Florida so long as they substantially meet the communitarian principle for which I have argued: having the reciprocal capacity to put others at risk of COVID-19 infection and the capacity to be put at risk by the COVID-19 infections of others.Footnote 20

By the same token, a state such as Florida should reject providing the vaccine to those who visit for a temporary stay, the true vaccine tourists. Why? First, providing them vaccines incentivizes this kind of travel, which is problematic for all the reasons with which I began.

Second, non-citizen/non-residents who are temporary visitors have no strong claims on the communitarian or citizenship theories of entitlement I have sketched out; all they can offer is territoriality as a basis for their claim. But the nature of this good is such that mere temporary presence in the territory does not generate a strong claim to the good. To be fair, it is true that even on that temporary visit one might put others at risk of infection or be put at risk of infection, but the surest way to guard against that risk is not to encourage travel for the purpose of getting vaccines. Further, while in some sense non-citizen/non-residents who are temporary visitors are extremely temporary members of the community, lines must be drawn and this one does not seem that hard as an exclusionary one.Footnote 21

IV Some Objections and Last Thoughts

Having now set up the basic structure of the argument, I want to consider a few objections. The first objection is one I addressed earlier – that the starting assumption that any vaccine doses belong to a home country is problematic from a global justice perspective.

A second objection is that vaccine tourism plays an important role in bringing money back to hard-hit communities. That is, attracting vaccine tourists from abroad will fill hotel rooms, restaurants, and planes in a way that helps hard-hit communities. I have several responses. First, it is far from clear to me that the descriptive claim is correct: It may depend on how many places are offering doses to outsiders and how they compete. For example, many vaccine tourists might flock to flight hubs such as New York or Los Angeles, rather than Fairbanks, Alaska, such that the expected gain to the Fairbanks community never arises. Second, even if the gain were real, I think some might argue from the “purpose of the good” that this justification – bringing in money for hard-hit communities – is nevertheless not permissible. Vaccine doses are not, the argument goes, general purpose goods to make people’s lives go better but instead have a particular function – preventing infection – that guides their distribution. This can be connected to a bioethics literature on “indirect” versus “direct” benefits and “separate spheres”: Some argue that in decisions about allocation, the further away one gets from the purpose of the good in how it provides benefits, the less justified we are in counting that benefit in deciding allocation priority.Footnote 22

The easiest way to illustrate this would be to imagine another allocation scheme that the state of Alaska could adopt which might be even better at creating income to be given to the poorest people in the state: auctioning off doses to the highest bidders from outside the states. If that would be impermissible, the argument goes, why is deliberately attracting vaccine tourists to bring in money for hard-hit communities any better? When to count indirect benefits requires swimming in choppy philosophical waters, but the easiest lifesaver one can throw is to say whether it is all-things-considered ethically permissible. When the allocator (the US government) shares vaccine doses, surely enabling the state to make money is not the allocators’ criteria for distribution – it distributes doses based on population size, not the degree to which a state is economically depressed. There may be other forms of allocation of federal funds that are meant for this latter problem, but vaccine doses are not such an allocation. It would be as though a friend lent you his or her car to take your mother to the hospital and you instead used it to make money off Uber rides. That would be impermissible because the car (or vaccine doses) was given for one purpose but you are using it for something very different. This is all the more so when, as with vaccine doses, there are multiple rival claimants, instead of a car that is merely sitting idle.

One final point before I close: Does the argument look different when we are discussing interstate medical tourism within a country (say travelers from New York to Florida) as opposed to people coming from abroad? A little. The communitarian arguments for excluding temporary visitors to the state persist in the interstate case, but are admittedly a bit weaker. Why weaker?

The New Yorker’s tax dollars have gone to support the purchase of the vaccine doses just as much as the Floridian’s, so that is not distinguishing. And while it is true that only the Floridian has the reciprocal relationship of putting others at risk and being put at risk of infection in Florida, we might go up a level of generality and say both have the same reciprocal relationship as to infection in the United States as a whole, which begs the question of why Florida and not the United States is the right level of analysis.

There is an answer but it is a little less satisfying – that is, that the United States decided to allocate doses to individual states initially based on population per capita above the age of eighteen.Footnote 23 It follows from that decision that any time New Yorkers take doses in Florida, that is one less dose of the share Florida was allocated for Floridians. At the extreme, imagine if the entire population of New York City were to arrive in Miami and claim doses. That would mean that New Yorkers had received more than they were entitled to and Floridians less. That would frustrate the logic of allocation the federal government settled on, as well as bring with it the risk of infection spread discussed earlier. It might also stymie attempts to key the reopening of a state to vaccination metrics. If that feels a little less satisfying as a reason, it is because the initial choice to distribute by state by population feels like more of an artifact of the need to quickly administer these vaccines rather than the result of a deeper moral reason connected to entitlement. One could have imagined rolling out the vaccine across the United States by population age, for example, irrespective of state.

This points to a bigger truth: The opportunity for interstate medical tourism is itself the result of vaccine federalism, or, more accurately, federalism in the way in which allocation criteria were set. Individual states got to decide whether and for how long to prioritize certain age bands, essential workers, and so on. Those differences inevitably provided incentives for interstate medical travel. This could have been avoided – the federal government could have done more to set uniform allocation policy (compare, for example, the allocation of organs to transplant where there are national rules rather than individual states setting their own policies). Perhaps in future planning, the decision to allocate doses to individual states initially based on population per capita above the age of eighteen is worth revisiting.

Footnotes

Introduction

22 COVID-19 and National Public Health Regimes Whither the Post-Washington Consensus in Public Health?Footnote 1

1 For further explanation of the methodologies used in this chapter, please see the Methodological Appendix at https://petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/assets/publications/Chapter_22_-_Wise_-_Final_Version_-_appendix.pdf.

2 Ctr. for Strategic & Int’l Stud., Preventing the Next Pandemic: A Conversation with the World Bank President (June 2, 2016), www.youtube.com/watch?v=tXWJWHkgl8k&t=1825s.

3 Id.; Dean T. Jamison et al., Global Health 2035: A World Converging Within a Generation, 382 Lancet 1898, 1944 (2013).

4 John Williamson, Democracy and the “Washington Consensus,” 21 World Dev. 1329, 1332 (1993).

5 Dani Rodrik, Goodbye Washington Consensus, Hello Washington Confusion? A Review of the World Bank’s Economic Growth in the 1990s: Learning From a Decade of Reform, 44 J. Econ. Literature 973, 973 (2006); Ali Burak Güven, Whither the Post-Washington Consensus? International Financial Institutions and Development Policy Before and After the Crisis, 25 Rev. Int’l. Pol. Econ. 392 (2018).

6 John Williamson, A Short History of the Washington Consensus, in The Washington Consensus Reconsidered: Towards a New Global Governance 28 (Narcís Serra & Joseph E. Stiglitz eds., 2008).

7 Rick Rowden, From the Washington Consensus to the Wall Street Consensus 17 (2019). On the increased use of financial markets for development, see Peter Volberding, Leveraging Financial Markets for Development: How KfW Revolutionized Development Finance (2021).

8 Najmul Haider et al., The Global Health Security Index and Joint External Evaluation Score for Health Preparedness Are Not Correlated with Countries’ COVID-19 Detection Response Time and Mortality Outcome, 148 Epidemiology & Infection e210 (2020). On the Joint External Evaluation Tool, see World Health Organization, Joint External Evaluation, Zoonotic Diseases Action Package Conference (2017). On the Global Health Security Index, see Nuclear Threat Initiative & Johns Hopkins University Centre for Health Security, Global Health Security Index (2019).

9 Sheena Asthana & Joyce Halliday, Developing an Evidence Base for Policies and Interventions to Address Health Inequalities: The Analysis of “Public Health Regimes,” 84 Milbank Q. 577 (2006).

10 Center for Systemic Peace, www.systemicpeace.org/.

11 Alberto Alesina et al., Fractionalization, 8 J. Econ. Growth 155, 158 (2003).

12 See supra note 4.

13 Narcís Serra, Shari Spiegel & Joseph E. Stiglitz, Introduction: From the Washington Consensus Towards a New Global Governance, in The Washington Consensus Reconsidered: Towards a New Global Governance 3 (Narcís Serra & Joseph E. Stiglitz eds., 2008).

14 Id.; Güven, supra note 5, at 392 (2018).

15 Joseph E. Stiglitz, Is there a Post-Washington Consensus Consensus?, in The Washington Consensus Reconsidered: Towards a New Global Governance 41 (Narcís Serra & Joseph E. Stiglitz eds., 2008).

16 Christiane Arndt, The Politics of Governance Ratings, 11 Int’l. Pub. Mgmt. 275, 275 (2008).

17 Thomas Hale et al., Oxford COVID-19 Government Response Tracker, Blavatnik Sch. of Gov’t (2020).

18 Ensheng Dong, Hongru Du & Lauren Gardner, An Interactive Web-Based Dashboard to Track COVID-19 in Real Time, 20 Lancet Infect. Dis. 533, 533 (2020).

19 Lene Mikkelsen et al., A Global Assessment of Civil Registration and Vital Statistics Systems: Monitoring Data Quality and Progress, 386 Lancet 1395, 1395 (2015).

20 Jungsik Noh & Gaudenz Danuser, Estimation of the Fraction of COVID-19 Infected People in US States and Countries Worldwide, 16 PloS one e0246772 (2021).

21 The government containment score comes from the OxCGRT data and contains measures of school closures (0 = no measures to 3 = require closing all levels), workplace closures (0 = no measures to 3 = require closing all but essential workplaces), canceling of public events (0 = no measures to 2 = required cancelling), restrictions on gatherings (0 = no restrictions to 4 = restrictions on gatherings of fewer than ten people), public transport closings (0 = no measures to 2 = required closings), public information campaigns (0 = no public information campaigns to 2 = coordinated public information campaign), stay-at-home measures (0 = no measures to 3 = required not leaving the house with minimal exceptions), restrictions on internal movement (0 = no measures to 2 = restricted movement), international travel controls (0 = no measures to 4 = total border closure), testing policy (0 = no testing policy to 3 = open public testing), contact tracing (0 = no contact tracing to 2 = comprehensive contact tracing), face covering policies (0 = no policy to 4 = required outside the home at all times), and vaccination policy (0 = no vaccine availability to 5 = universal vaccine availability). These indicators were combined and scaled to create an index varying between 1 and 100.

22 Justin Yifu Lin, Against the Consensus: Reflections on the Great Recession 99 (2013).

23 With more space, we would have liked to include a Cluster 4 (low-development semi democracy) country, but these countries are the most hampered by low rates of data collection on COVID-19, especially in the early stages of the pandemic. See Kevyah Cardoso, Measuring Africa’s Data Gap: The Cost of Not Counting the Dead, BBC News (Feb. 22, 2021), www.bbc.com/news/world-africa-55674139.

24 Talha Burki, China’s Successful Control of COVID-19, 20 Lancet Infect. Dis. 1240, 1240 (2020).

25 Id. at 1240.

26 Id. at 1241.

27 China’s Vaccine Campaign Hits a Few Bumps, Nat’l Pub. Radio (Feb. 3, 2021).

28 See, for example, Responding to COVID-19: The Rules of Good Governance Apply Now More Than Ever!, OECD, www.oecd.org/governance/public-governance-responses-to-covid19.

29 Freedom House, Freedom in the World 2020: Thailand, Freedomhouse (2020), https://freedomhouse.org/country/thailand/freedom-world/2020.

30 Kanang Kantamaturapoj et al., Legislating for Public Accountability in Universal Health Coverage, Thailand, 98 Bull. World Health Organ 117, 117 (2020).

31 Id.

33 Id.

34 Viroi Tangcharoensathien et al., Are Overwhelmed Health Systems an Inevitable Consequence of COVID-19? Experiences from China, Thailand, and New York State, 372 Brit Med. J. 1, 2 (2021).

35 Id.

36 See supra note 30.

37 Wijitbusaba Marome & Rajib Shaw, COVID-19 Response in Thailand and Its Implications on Future Preparedness, 18 Int’l J. Env’t Res. Pub. Health. 1089, 1095 (2021).

38 Eyal Leshem, Arnon Afek & Yitshak Kreiss, Buying Time with COVID-19 Outbreak Response, Israel, 26 Emerg. Infect. Dis. 2251, 2251 (2020).

39 Glenn I. Cohen, Lawrence Gostin & Daniel Weitzner, Digital Smartphone Tracking for COVID-19: Public Health and Civil Liberties in Tension, 323 JAMA 2371, 2371 (2020).

40 Daphna Birenbaum-Carmeli & Judith Chassida, COVID-19 in Israel: Socio-Demographic Characteristics of First Wave Morbidity in Jewish and Arab Communities, 19 Int’l J. for Equity in Health 1 (2020).

41 Id.

42 Shelly Simana, Is Israel Trading Medicine Information for Vaccines? Ethical and Legal Considerations, The Bill of Health (Jan. 25, 2021), https://blog.petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/2021/01/25/israel-covid-vaccine-health-data/.

43 David Wallace-Wells, How the West Lost COVID-19, Intelligencer, NY Magazine (Mar. 15, 2021), https://nymag.com/intelligencer/2021/03/how-the-west-lost-covid-19.html.

44 Sylvia Walby, The COVID Pandemic and Social Theory: Social Democracy and Public Health in the Crisis, 24 Eur. J. Soc. Theory 22, 24 (2021).

23 Mapping COVID-19 Legal Responses: A Functionalist Analysis

1 Robin West, Reconsidering Legalism, 88 Minn. L. Rev. 119, 130–35 (2003).

2 Id.

3 Donald W. Light, Universal Health Care: Lessons from the British Experience, 93 Am. J. Pub. Health 25, 26 (2003).

4 Vicente Navarro, Production and the Welfare State: The Political Context of Reforms, 21 Int’l J. Health Servs. 585, 614 (1991).

5 For all country reports, see Joelle Grogan, Introduction and List of Country Reports, VerfBlog (Apr. 6, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/introduction-list-of-country-reports/.

6 For all country reports, see Bill of Health, Global Responses to COVID-19: Rights, Democracy, and the Law, https://blog.petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/category/blog-symposia/global-responses-covid19/.

7 See, for example, COVID-19 Government Response Tracker, Oxford, www.bsg.ox.ac.uk/research/research-projects/covid-19-government-response-tracker; COVID-19 Law Lab, https://covidlawlab.org. Subsequently, other researchers, including the Lex-Atlas project and the CompCoRe projects, developed a more extensive and detailed compendium of comparative legal analyses. See Lex-Atlas: COVID-19, UCL, https://lexatlas-c19.org/; CompCoRe, https://compcore.cornell.edu/.

8 David Dyzenhaus, The Constitution of Law: Legality in a Time of Emergency 41–43 (2006).

9 Tom Ginsburg & Mila Versteeg, Binding the Unbound Executive: Checks and Balances in Times of Pandemic, Int’l J. of Const. L. (June 24, 2021), www.law.virginia.edu/scholarship/publication/mila-versteeg/1334721.

10 Tom Daly, Democratic Decay: Conceptualising an Emerging Research Field, 11 Hague J. Rule L. 9, 9–11 (2019).

11 See Cassandra Emmons, International Human Rights Law and COVID-19 States of Emergency, VerfBlog (Apr. 25, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/international-human-rights-law-and-covid-19-states-of-emergency.

12 See, for example, Eur. Convention on Hum. Rts., Fact Sheet, Derogation in Time of Emergency (updated Sept. 2020), www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Derogation_ENG.pdf.

13 See, for example, UN HRC, General Comment No. 29, Article 4 (States of Emergency): International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (2001); ECHR, Guide, Article 15 (Derogation in Time of Emergency): European Convention on Human Rights (updated Apr. 30, 2021), www.echr.coe.int/documents/Guide_Art_15_ENG.pdf.

14 Joelle Grogan, States of Emergency, VerfBlog (May 26, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/states-of-emergency.

15 See Niall Coghlan, Dissecting COVID-19 Derogations, VerfBlog (May 5, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/dissecting-covid-19-derogations/; Emmons, supra note 11.

16 See Martin Scheinin, ‘To Derogate or Not to Derogate,’ OpinioJuris (Apr. 6, 2020), http://opiniojuris.org/2020/04/06/covid-19-symposium-to-derogate-or-not-to-derogate/.

17 Kriszta Kovács, Hungary’s Orbánistan: A Complete Arsenal of Emergency Powers, VerfBlog (Apr. 6, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/hungarys-orbanistan-a-complete-arsenal-of-emergency-powers/.

18 Jakub Jaraczewski, An Emergency By Any Other Name? Measures Against the COVID-19 Pandemic in Poland, VerfBlog (Apr. 24, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/an-emergency-by-any-other-name-measures-against-the-covid-19-pandemic-in-poland/.

19 See Laurent Pech, Patryk Wachowiec & Dariusz Mazur, Poland’s Rule of Law Breakdown: A Five-Year Assessment of EU’s (In)Action, 13 Hague J. Rule L. 1, 1–43 (2021); Laurent Pech & Kim Lane Scheppele, Illiberalism Within: Rule of Law Backsliding in the EU, 19 Camb. Yearb. Eur. Leg. Stud. 3, 19–26 (2017).

20 Joelle Grogan & Alice Donald, Lessons for a “Post-Pandemic” Future, in Joelle Grogan & Alice Donald, Routledge Handbook of Law and the COVID-19 Pandemic (2022).

21 Comments of Justice Alfredo Gutiérrez Ortiz Mena, Constitutional Democracy and the Role of High Courts in Times of Crisis: The Case of Mexico (Oct. 23, 2020), https://petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/events/details/constitutional-democracy-and-the-role-of-high-courts-in-times-of-crisis.

22 See Sheila Jasanoff & Stephen Hilgartner, A Stress Test for Politics: A Comparative Perspective on Policy Responses to COVID-19, in Joelle Grogan & Alice Donald, Routledge Handbook of Law and the COVID-19 Pandemic, 294–98 (2022); Grogan & Donald, supra note 20, at 483–84.

23 See, for example, Ian Bremmer Best Responses to COVID-19, Time (June 12, 2020), https://time.com/5851633/best-global-responses-covid-19/; Tom Frieden, Which Countries Have Responded Best to COVID-19?, Wall St. J. (Jan. 1, 2021), www.wsj.com/articles/which-countries-have-responded-best-to-covid-19-11609516800.

24 See Alicia Ely Yamin, Global Responses to COVID-19: An Inflection Point for Democracy, Rights, and Law, Bill of Health (June 12, 2020), https://blog.petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/2020/06/12/global-responses-covid19-reflections/.

25 Alicia Ely Yamin & Tara Boghosian, Democracy and Health: Situating Health Rights within a Republic of Reasons, 19 Yale J. Health Pol’y, L. Ethics 87, 87–123 (2020).

26 Alicia Ely Yamin, When Misfortune Becomes Injustice: Evolving Human Rights Struggles for Health and Social Equality 94–98, 128–30 (2020).

27 Id. at 94–99.

28 Roberto Gargarella, The Engine Room of the Constitution: Latin American Constitutionalism, 1810–2010, at viii (2013).

29 Rudolf Virchow, Disease, Life, and Man (1958).

30 See, generally, Adele E. Clarke et al., Biomedicalization: Technoscience, Health, and Illness in the US (2010); Viviane Quirke & Jean-Paul Gaudillière, The Era of Biomedicine: Science, Medicine, and Public Health in Britain and France after the Second World War, 52 Med. Hist. 441 (2008).

31 Nika Bačić Selanec, Croatia’s Response to COVID-19: On Legal Form and Constitutional Safeguards in Times of Pandemic, VerfBlog (May 9, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/croatias-response-to-covid-19-on-legal-form-and-constitutional-safeguards-in-times-of-pandemic/.

32 Antoine Buyse & Roel de Lange, The Netherlands: Of Rollercoasters and Elephants, VerfBlog (May 8, 2020), https://verfassungsblog.de/the-netherlands-of-rollercoasters-and-elephants/; Brigit Toebes, COVID-19, the Netherlands, and Human Rights: A Balancing Act, Bill of Health (May 26, 2020), https://blog.petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/2020/05/26/netherlands-global-responses-covid19/.

33 Devi Sridhar, Good Morning Britain (Nov. 5, 2020), https://twitter.com/gmb/status/1324272948820267008.

34 Sheila Jasanoff, Science and Public Reason 168 (2012).

35 See Jonathan Mann et al., Health and Human Rights, 1 Health Hum. Rts. 7, 16 (1994).

36 Jasanoff & Hilgartner, supra note 22, at 297–98.

37 Example, P.M. Maarten et al., Stakeholder Participation for Legitimate Priority Setting: A Checklist, 7 Int’l J. of Health Pol’y & Mgmt. 973, 976 (2018); WHO Consultative Group on Equity and Universal Health Coverage, Making Fair Choices on the Path to Universal Health Coverage (2014); see also Alicia Ely Yamin & Tara Boghosian, Democracy and Health: Situating Health Rights within a Republic of Reasons, 19 Yale J. of Health Pol’y, L. Ethics 87, 110–21 (2020).

39 Scott Burris, From Health Care to the Social Determinants of Health: A Public Health Law Research Perspective, 159 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1649, 1655 (2011).

40 Jededihah Britton-Purdy et al., Building a Law-and-Political-Economy Framework: Beyond the Twentieth-Century Synthesis, 129 Yale L. J. 1784, 1827 (2020).

24 A Tale of Two Crises COVID-19, Climate Change, and Crisis Response

1 Benjamin Bowe et al., Burden of Cause-Specific Mortality Associated with PM2.5 Air Pollution in the United States, JAMA Network Open (Nov. 20, 2019), https://jamanetwork.com/journals/jamanetworkopen/fullarticle/2755672.

2 Xiao Wu, Rachel C. Nethery, M. Benjamin Sabath, Danielle Braun & Francesca Dominici, Air Pollution and COVID-19 Mortality in the United States: Strengths and Limitations of an Ecological Regression Analysis, Sci. Advances (2020), https://advances.sciencemag.org/content/6/45/eabd4049. This result was consistent with the findings of other researchers. Id. For a survey of the literature, including studies from countries other than the United States, see Thomas Bourdrel, Isabella Annesi-Maesano, Barrak Alahmad, Cara N. Maesano & Marie-Abèle Bind, The Impact of Outdoor Air Pollution on COVID-19: A Review of Evidence from In Vitro, Animal, and Human Studies, 30 Eur. Respir. Rev. 200242 (2021).

3 Renee N. Salas, James Shultz & Caren G. Solomon, The Climate Crisis and Covid-19 – A Major Threat to the Pandemic Response, New Eng. J. Med. (July 15, 2020), www.nejm.org/doi/full/10.1056/NEJMp2022011.

4 Corinne Le Quéré et al., Temporary Reduction in Daily Global CO2 Emissions during the COVID-19 Forced Confinement, 10 Nature Climate Change 647 (2020).

5 US Energy Info. Agency, Short-Term Outlook (Nov. 10, 2020), www.eia.gov/outlooks/steo/. These estimates are based on data regarding fuel consumption and energy output. It is more difficult to detect the emission changes from measurements of atmospheric concentrations, partly because of the large seasonal variation in concentration levels. See also Zhu Liu et al., Near-Real-Time Monitoring of Global CO2 Emissions Reveals the Effects of the COVID-19 Pandemic, Nature Commc’ns (Oct. 14, 2020), www.nature.com/articles/s41467-020-18922-7.

6 Alexander Kaufman, COVID-Related Emissions Drop “Just a Tiny Blip” in Long-term Climate Trends, Yale360, (Nov. 25, 2020), https://e360.yale.edu/digest/covid-related-emissions-drop-just-a-tiny-blip-in-long-term-climate-trends.

7 Liu et al., supra note 5, at fig. 2b.

8 Energy Monitor, A New Coal Boom in China: Country Accelerates New Coal Plant Permitting and Proposals (June 2020), https://globalenergymonitor.org/wp-content/uploads/2021/01/China-coal-plant-brief-June-2020Eng.pdf.

9 Id.

10 Frank Schneider & Allie Schwartz, The New World of COVID-19: Paradigm Shifts in the Oil and Gas Industry, Nat’l L. Rev. (Sept. 30, 2020), www.natlawreview.com/article/new-world-covid-19-paradigm-shifts-oil-and-gas-industry.

11 Id.

12 Id.

13 Danica Kirka, Shell Takes $22 Billion Hit on Lower Oil, Gas Prices, Associated Press (June 30, 2020), https://apnews.com/article/0d7adddd9a596eba2f34b736fce1f030.

14 According to the Washington Post:

Led by a new chief executive, BP is trying to reinvent itself as an energy company in the age of climate change. The company is shrinking its oil and gas business, revving up offshore wind power and developing solar and battery storage. It is even considering installing electric car charging kiosks at its U.S. gas stations, part of a drive to eliminate or offset its carbon emissions to a net zero level by 2050.

Steven Mufson, Big Oil’s Green Makeover, Wash. Post (Sept. 15, 2020), www.washingtonpost.com/climate-solutions/2020/09/15/bp-climate-change-transition/.

15 Emily Pontecorvo, Abandonment Issues, Grist (Dec. 1, 2020), https://grist.org/energy/plugging-abandoned-oil-wells-carbon-offsets/.

16 RAND Corp., Telecommuting and Work in the COVID-19 Pandemic: Are Workers Returning to the Workplace or Staying in Their Home Offices? (2020), www.rand.org/pubs/research_reports/RRA308-11.html. Internationally, the degree of telecommuting varied between countries, although complete global data does not seem to be available. In the European Union, telecommuting increased everywhere, but with substantial versions in the extent of the increase between countries. See Eur. Comm’n, Telework in the EU Before and After the COVID-19: Where We Were, Where We Head To (2020), https://ec.europa.eu/jrc/sites/default/files/jrc120945_policy_brief_-_covid_and_telework_final.pdf.

17 Christina Goldbaum & Will Wright, ‘Existential Peril’: Mass Transit Faces Huge Service Cuts Across U.S., NY Times (Dec. 6, 2020), www.nytimes.com/2020/12/06/nyregion/mass-transit-service-cuts-covid.html.

18 Robert J. Shiller, Why We Can’t Foresee the Pandemic’s Long-Term Effects, NY Times, (May 29, 2020, updated Aug. 4, 2020).

19 Id.

20 Tao Zhang, Opening Remarks – COVID-19: Opportunities for a Green Recovery (May 22, 2020), www.imf.org/en/News/Articles/2020/05/22/sp052220-opening-remark-zhang.

21 Int’l Energy Agency, World Energy Outlook Special Report: Sustainable Recovery (June 2020), www.iea.org/reports/sustainable-recovery.

22 Id.

23 See Rhodium Grp., It’s Not Easy Being Green: Stimulus Spending in the World’s Major Economies 5 (Sept. 2, 2020), https://rhg.com/research/green-stimulus-spending/.

24 Kate Abnett, Factbox: Key Climate Spending in EU’s ‘Green Recovery’ Plan, Reuters (May 27, 2020), www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2020-07-21/eu-approves-biggest-green-stimulus-in-history-with-572-billion-plan. A key part of the plan is the €672 billion Recovery and Resilience Facility, which countries can tap to finance their recovery plans. Thirty-seven percent of the funds must be devoted to climate-related initiatives. Eur. Comm’n, The Recovery and Resilience Facility, https://ec.europa.eu/info/business-economy-euro/recovery-coronavirus/recovery-and-resilience-facility_en. The recovery plan builds on previous EU planning for a “Green Deal.” See Sebastiano Sabato & Boris Fronteddu, A Socially Just Transition Through the European Green Deal? (Aug. 2020), www.etui.org/publications/socially-just-transition-through-european-green-deal.

25 Ewa Krukowska & Laura Millan Lombrana, EU Approves Biggest Green Stimulus in History With $572 Billion Plan, Bloomberg Green (July 21, 2020), www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2020-07-21/eu-approves-biggest-green-stimulus-in-history-with-572-billion-plan.

26 Renee Cho, COVID-19’s Long-Term Effects on Climate Change – For Better or Worse (June 25, 2020), https://news.climate.columbia.edu/2020/06/25/covid-19-impacts-climate-change/.

27 Id.

28 Her Majesty’s Gov’t, The Ten Point Plan for a Green Industrial Revolution (Nov. 2020), www.gov.uk/government/publications/the-ten-point-plan-for-a-green-industrial-revolution. Given that spending will extend until 2030, it is not clear how much of the funding should be considered “green stimulus,” though it is probably no coincidence that the plan was announced during the pandemic.

29 Yamide Dagnet & Joel Jaeger, Not Enough Climate Action in Stimulus Plans (Sept. 15, 2020), www.wri.org/blog/2020/09/coronavirus-green-economic-recovery/.

30 Alex Dewar, Raad Alkadiri, Rebecca Fitz & Jamie Webster, How COVID-19 is Changing the Pace of Energy Transitions 2 (Sept. 2020), https://web-assets.bcg.com/4d/1b/1fab91c1439bad272a22a8596952/bcg-how-covid-19-is-changing-the-pace-of-energy-transitions-sep-2020.pdf.

31 Rhodium Grp., supra note 23, at 7. It can be difficult to separate recovery-related spending from background funding plans, given the general lack of transparency in China. Id.

32 See Dewar et al., supra note 30, at 5 (estimating $200 billion in Chinese green stimulus measures).

33 Id. at 7–8. For a detailed description of Korea’s ambitious plan, see Jae-Hyup Lee & Jisuk Woo, Green New Deal Policy of South Korea: Policy Innovation for a Sustainability Transition, 12 Sustainability 10191 (2020), www.mdpi.com/2071-1050/12/23/10191/pdf.

34 Dagnet & Jaeger, supra note 29.

35 Rhodium Grp., supra note 23, at 6.

36 On the new legislation and its effects, see The Rapid Policy Evaluation and Analysis Tool Kit project (REPEAT) at Princeton REPEAT, Preliminary Report: The Climate and Energy Impacts of the Inflation Reduction Act of 2022, at 7 (August 2022); Megan Mahajan, Olivia Ashmoore, Jeffrey Rissman, Robbie Orvis, and Anand Gopal, Modeling The Inflation Reduction Act Using The Energy Policy Simulator (Aug. 2022), https://energyinnovation.org/wp-content/uploads/2022/08/Modeling-the-Inflation-Reduction-Act-with-the-US-Energy-Policy-Simulator_August.pdf.

37 Shannon Osaka, Obama’s Recovery Act Breathed Life into Renewables. Now They Need Rescuing., Grist (June 1, 2020), https://grist.org/energy/obamas-recovery-act-breathed-life-into-renewables-now-they-need-rescuing/.

38 Id.

39 Joel Jaeger, Michael Westphal & Corey Park, Lessons Learned on Green Stimulus: Case Studies from the Global Financial Crisis 15 (Nov. 20, 2020), https://wriorg.s3.amazonaws.com/s3fs-public/lessons-learned-on-green-stimulus-case-studies-from-the-global-financial-crisis.pdf.

40 Id. at 3.

41 Id.

42 Id; see also Dewar et al., supra note 30, at 2. For a survey of the available information about green stimulus during the Great Recession and discussion of methodological problems, see Shardul Agrawala, Damien Dussaux & Norbert Monti, What Policies for Greening the Crisis Response and Economic Recovery? Lessons Learned from Past Green Stimulus Measures and Implications for the COVID-19 Crisis 25–28 (May 2020), https://doi.org/10.1787/c50f186f-en. The economic benefits of green stimulus programs seem clear. Id. at 31.

43 Mary Dobbs, National Governance of Public Health Response in a Pandemic?, 11 Eur. J. Risk Reg. 240 (June 2020). Apart from the WHO, international financial institutions such as the International Monetary Fund or regional development banks have also played significant roles. See David Klenert, Franziska Funke, Linus Mattauch & Brian O’Callaghan, Five Lessons from COVID-19 for Advancing Climate Change Mitigation 13 (Aug. 2020), https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/32836842/.

44 See Philip Bump, Scott Atlas Will Forever be the Face of Surrender to the Coronavirus, Wash. Post. (Dec. 1, 2020), www.washingtonpost.com/politics/2020/12/01/scott-atlas-will-forever-be-face-surrender-coronavirus/. Atlas is a retired physician who moved from being a health policy analyst at a conservative think tank to being President Trump’s closest adviser on the pandemic.

45 Katie Rogers & Apoorva Mandavilli, Trump Administration Signals Formal Withdrawal From W.H.O., NY Times (Oct. 22, 2020), www.nytimes.com/2020/07/07/us/politics/coronavirus-trump-who.html. For an overview of the role of the WHO and other international institutions in the pandemic context, see Armin von Bogdandy & Pedro Villarreal, International Law on Pandemic Response: A First Stocktaking in Light of the Coronavirus Crisis (Mar. 26, 2020), https://ssrn.com/abstract=3561650.

46 Kirsten Engel, Climate Federalism in the Time of COVID-19: Can the States “Save” American Climate Policy?, 47 N. Ky. L. Rev. 115, 127 (2020). In Brazil, a similar dynamic took place, with individual states taking strong public health measures, despite the opposing view of the populist Bolsonaro regime. See Terrence McCoy, Should a Coronavirus Vaccine Be Mandatory? In Brazil’s Most Populous State, It Will Be., Wash. Post (Dec. 7, 2020), www.washingtonpost.com/world/the_americas/virus-mandatory-vaccine-brazil-bolsonaro/2020/12/06/31767b4a-33e5-11eb-8d38-6aea1adb3839_story.html.

47 Shana Kushner Gadarian, Sara Wallace Goodman & Thomas Pepinsky, Partisanship, Health Behavior, and Policy Attitudes in the Early Stages of the COVID-19 Pandemic (Mar. 27, 2020), https://ssrn.com/abstract=3562796.

48 Lisa Friedman, U.S. Quits Paris Climate Agreement: Questions and Answers, NY Times (Nov. 4, 2020), www.nytimes.com/2020/11/04/climate/paris-climate-agreement-trump.html. For further discussion of the Paris Agreement, see Daniel A. Farber & Cinnamon P. Carlarne, Climate Change L. 67–72 (2018).

49 Engel, supra note 45, at 116.

50 Id. at 119.

51 Id. at 116–17.

52 For more about state climate-related policies, see Farber & Carlarne, supra note 47, at 185–89.

53 Nat’l Renewable Energy Lab., Renewable Portfolio Standards (Mar. 21, 2020), www.nrel.gov/state-local-tribal/basics-portfolio-standards.html.

54 SB 350 (de León), Chapter 8.5, Statutes of 2015, codified at Cal. Health & Safety Code § 44258.5 et seq.

55 AB 32 (Nuñez), Chapter 488, California Statutes of 2006, codified at Cal. Health & Safety Code § 38500 et seq.

57 Klenert et al., supra note 42, at 14.

58 See Antonia Noori Farzan & Miriam Berger, Bolsonaro Says Brazilians Must not be ‘Sissies’ about Coronavirus, as ‘All of Us Are Going to Die One Day,’ Wash. Post. (Nov. 11, 2020), www.washingtonpost.com/world/2020/11/11/bolsonaro-coronavirus-brazil-quotes/.

59 According to the Guardian, “Brazil’s foreign minister, Ernesto Araújo, has warned that climate change was a plot by ‘cultural Marxists[,]’ and President Jair Bolsonaro made a campaign promise to pull Brazil out of the Paris climate accord before reluctantly backing off.” Dom Phillips, Resistance to the ‘Environmental Sect’ is a Cornerstone of Bolsonaro’s Rule, Guardian (July 27, 2020), www.theguardian.com/global-development/2020/jul/27/resistance-to-the-environmental-sect-is-a-cornerstone-of-bolsonaro-rule-brazil.

60 See Klenert et al., supra note 42, at 7.

61 Id. at 9.

62 Id. at 14.

63 See Christopher Avery et al., An Economist’s Guide to Epidemiology Models of Infectious Disease, 35 J. Econ. Persp. 79, 99–100 (2020).

64 Klenert et al., supra note 42, at 14.

65 Id. at 15–16.

25 Vaccine Tourism, Federalism, Nationalism

* I thank Prue Brady for excellent research assistance with this chapter.

1 Florida Officials Cracking Down on COVID-19 “Vaccine Tourism,” CBS (Jan. 21, 2021), www.cbsnews.com/news/florida-covid-vaccine-tourism/?ftag=CNM-00-10aab7e&linkId=109654223.

2 Id.

3 Id.

4 Id.

5 Jane Musgrave & John Pacenti, COVID-19 Vaccine Tourism? Florida Could Be Hot Spot as Governor Discourages Outsiders, USA Today (Jan. 12, 2021), www.usatoday.com/story/travel/news/2021/01/12/covid-vaccine-tourism-florida-discourages-outsiders-seeking-shot/6626445002/.

6 Megan Reeves & Allison Ross, Florida Limits Coronavirus Vaccines to Permanent, Seasonal Residents, Tampa Bay Times (Jan. 21, 2021), www.tampabay.com/news/health/2021/01/21/is-florida-vaccinating-non-residents-or-not-its-hard-to-get-an-answer/. For its part, the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) COVID-19 Vaccine Task Force took different positions as supply changed. As it describes its position, “when there were limited supplies of COVID-19 vaccine available, [the] CDC allowed states to limit COVID-19 vaccination to residents and others temporarily living in the state to assure that all such individuals would have the opportunity for timely vaccination.” CDC, COVID-19 Vaccine Task Force Position on Citizenship and Residency, www.cdc.gov/vaccines/covid-19/citizenship-residency-position.html (last updated Oct. 21, 2021). By contrast, its later position was: “Now that COVID-19 vaccine supply availability has increased, there is no longer a public health rationale for excluding individuals who are not residents of a state or locality from being vaccinated in another state or locality. Therefore, residents and others who live in any state or locality should be allowed to get vaccinated in any state.” Id.

7 I. Glenn Cohen, Patients with Passports (2014).

8 Id. This is in contrast to “circumvention tourism” involving travel for a service illegal in a patient’s home country (e.g., abortion, aid in dying) or travel for services illegal in both the patient’s home and destination country (e.g., travel to purchase a kidney for transplant). Id.

9 Of course, there is no guarantee that a country such as the United States will donate such “excess” doses. Many high-income countries, such as the United States and Canada, have made plans to stockpile more doses than they will use. If the choice is between a particular dose adding to a stockpile versus being used for a vaccine tourist, the latter seems less objectionable, even if less ethically good than the alternative of donation to a low-income country.

10 Cohen, supra note 7, at 48–50.

11 More accurately, perhaps three “intuitive” or “plausible” principles – one could certainly imagine many more.

12 Example, John Rawls, A Theory Of Justice § 39, at 244–46 (1971).

13 I. Glenn Cohen, Organs Without Borders? Allocating Transplant Organs, Foreigners, and the Importance of the Nation-State (?), 77 Law Contemp. Probs. 175 (2014).

14 Id. at 197–205.

15 But see Cécile Fabre, Whose Body Is It Anyway? 72–123 (2006) (offering some provocative arguments to the contrary).

16 What should we make of the fact that the vaccine doses were also the result of US investment in their development? It would be tempting to tether the argument to the multi-billion dollar investment by the United States in COVID-19 vaccine clinical trials, production scale-up, procurement, and delivery as part of Operation Warp Speed. But this might generate some unusual implications. First, while it would offer a hook for Moderna and Johnson & Johnson vaccines, Pfizer did not accept funding from the program. Example, Assistant Secretary for Public Affairs, Health & Hum. Servs., Fact Sheet: Explaining Operation Warp Speed (Jan. 21, 2021), www.hhs.gov/coronavirus/explaining-operation-warp-speed/index.html [https://perma.cc/U5DF-FF9R]. That would seem to suggest one set of entitlements and priorities for one vaccine but not the others. Second, it would seem to suggest that to determine if a particular non-US citizen/non-US resident had an entitlement claim to a particular vaccine, we would need to determine what investment his or her home country had made to its development such that we might draw distinctions between different home countries in terms of who could justifiably travel to the United States for vaccine tourism. Neither of these implications doom the argument, but they do make it less appealing.

One might also worry that the argument would generate obvious distributional effects between wealthier countries who invested in development and poorer ones who did not. But, of course, similar distributional effects follow from allowing the United States to prefer its own citizens for vaccinations because it was able to make advance purchasing agreements at prices that Liberia, for example, was not. Thus, this seems to me a strong argument against allowing claim rights for investment-to-innovate only if one was also prepared to make the stronger argument that the United States is not justified in prioritizing its citizen-residents for the doses it actually purchased. This relates back to the assumption I introduced earlier.

17 Indeed, undocumented immigrants frequently pay into the US tax system through Social Security and other tax resources from which they do not draw. Example, Henry Ordower, Taxing Others in the Age of Trump: Foreigners (and the Politically Weak) as Tax Subjects, 62 St. Louis U. L.J. 157, 171 (2017). Is it possible that there are some undocumented persons who do not pay taxes? Perhaps, though if we broaden the scope to include things such as sales tax, it becomes increasingly unlikely. Moreover, there are also citizens who do not pay taxes – lawfully or otherwise – but we do not, for example, restrict them from sending their children to public schools or other taxpayer-funded benefits. This seems no different. In any event, even if this communitarian principle was understood to exclude them, the second one I discuss will bring them back in.

18 If part of the goal of COVID-19 vaccination is to enable the return of the workforce, one might make a similar point that part-time residents are much less likely to be full-time workers in the state. Moreover, one might suggest that for full-time residents the benefit of the vaccination is carried forward for an indefinite time since residency in the state is for an indefinite time, whereas the part-time visitor may never come back. This might be used to develop more subtle forms of prioritization, but I suspect that adding the extra complexity may not be worth it.

19 Example, Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685, 1688 (1976); J. M. Balkin, The Crystalline Structure of Legal Thought, 39 Rutgers L. Rev. 1, 43 (1986).

20 But, as I suggested earlier, it may be justifiable to give such individuals less priority in proportion to how much they are a part of the community in a relevant sense. This strikes me as a place where things are less clear.

21 One might find an echo of this question in, of all places, the constitutional law of personal jurisdiction in US civil procedure. In Burnham v. Superior Court, 495 US 604 (1990), Justice Brennan and Justice Scalia famously dueled on whether mere presence in a state with service of process was enough as a basis for personal jurisdiction (Scalia’s view) versus the idea that even in such a brief visit, the individual had formed enough connection with the state to have purposefully availed himself enough of its protection, thereby justifying personal jurisdiction (Brennan’s view).

22 See, for example, Dan W. Brock, Separate Spheres and Indirect Benefits, Cost Effectiveness & Res. Allocation [pincite] (2003), https://resource-allocation.biomedcentral.com/track/pdf/10.1186/1478-7547-1-4.pdf; Frances M. Kamm, Morality, Mortality: Death and Whom to Save from It 107–15 (1993). For my own thoughts on this debate, see I. Glenn Cohen, Rationing Legal Services, 5 J. L. Anal. 221, 275–82 (2013).

23 Example, Lisa Simunaci, US Dep’t of Def., Pro Rata Vaccine Distribution is Fair, Equitable (Dec. 11, 2020), www.defense.gov/News/News-Stories/Article/Article/2441698/pro-rata-vaccine-distribution-is-fair-equitable/.

Figure 0

Table 22.1 Global indicators of public health

Figure 1

Figure 22.1 PCA results

Figure 2

Table 22.2 Public health regimes and key characteristics

Figure 3

Figure 22.2 Five clusters – our selected grouping

Figure 4

Figure 22.3 Max government containment vs. speed of spread

Figure 5

Table 22.3 Public health regimes, speed of spread, government response

Figure 6

Figure 22.4 Percent sixty-five plus vs. days to reach 10 COVID-19 deaths per million population

Figure 7

Table 22.4 China, Thailand, Israel, and United States pandemic outcomes

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×