Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-q6k6v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-09T17:23:05.638Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Representation, imitation, and resemblance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Richard Eldridge
Affiliation:
Swarthmore College, Pennsylvania
Get access

Summary

Representation and aboutness

Art products and performances seem in some rough sense to be about something. Even when they do not carry any explicitly statable single message, they nonetheless invite and focus thought. Marcel Duchamp’s readymades, Sol Le Witt’s constructions, Vito Acconci’s performance pieces, and Louise Lawler’s conceptual art are all put forward, in Duchamp’s phrase, “at the service of the mind,” in that they are intended to set up in an audience a line of thinking about a subject matter. Most literary works clearly undertake to describe an action, situation, or event. Works of dance typically have a narrative-developmental structure, and even works of architecture seem both to proceed from and to invite thoughts about how space is and ought to be experienced and used. Works of textless pure or absolute music have beginnings, middles, and ends that have seemed to many listeners to model or share shapes with broad patterns of human action. The abstract painter Hans Hoffmann in teaching used to have his students begin by putting a blue brush stroke on a bare canvas and then asking them to think about its relations to the space “behind,” “in front of,” and around it, as though the mere stroke were already a means of incipiently presenting a three-dimensional world on a two-dimensional surface.

Yet these facts about presentation of a subject matter in the arts raise considerable problems. How is representation achieved in various media? Does representation centrally involve any likeness or resemblance (as seems to be the case in much visual depiction) between representer and represented, or does it involve centrally the manipulation of syntactically structured conventional codes (as in linguistic representation)? Is the same sense of “representation” (with different means of achieving it) involved in different media of art? Does the value of a work of art depend upon what it represents, and if so, how? Is representationality even necessary for art? Is it sufficient?

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Duchamp, Marcel, “Interview with James Johnson Sweeney,” in “Eleven Europeans in America,” Bulletin of the Museum of Modern Art (New York) 12, 4–5 (1946), pp. 19–21; reprinted in Theories of Modern Art, ed. Herschel B. Chipp (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1968), p. 394Google Scholar
Maus, Fred Everett, “Music as Drama,” in Music and Meaning, ed. Robinson, Jenefer (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1997), pp. 105–30Google Scholar
Dahlhaus, Carl, The Idea of Absolute Music, trans. Lustig, Roger (University of Chicago Press, 1989).Google Scholar
Aristotle, , Poetics, trans. Janko, Richard (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1987), p. 1Google Scholar
Woodruff, Paul, “Aristotle on Mimesis,” in Essays on Aristotle’s Poetics, ed. Rorty, A. (Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 73–95 at p. 81.Google Scholar
Carroll, Noël, Philosophy of Art: A Contemporary Introduction (London: Routledge, 1999), p. 26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sheppard, Anne, Aesthetics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art (Oxford University Press, 1987), p. 16.Google Scholar
Shorey, Paul, notes to Plato, Republic I, trans. Shorey, Paul (London: Heinemann [Loeb Classical Library], 1930), p. 224Google Scholar
Spackman, John, “Expressiveness, Ineffability, and Nonconceptuality,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 70, 3 (summer 2012), pp. 311B, 3312A.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eldridge, Richard, “Hegel on Music,” in Hegel and the Arts, ed. Houlgate, Stephen (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2007), pp. 119–45.Google Scholar
Kramer, Lawrence, Classical Music and Postmodern Knowledge (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995), p. 21.Google Scholar
Walton, Kendall, Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 56.Google Scholar
McIver Lopes, Dominic M., “Representation: Depiction,” in Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, ed. Kelly, Michael (Oxford University Press, 1998), vol. IV, pp. 139B–143B at p. 139B.Google Scholar
Plato, , Republic, trans. Grube, G. M. A., revised C. D. C. Reeve (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1992), book X, 598b, p. 268.Google Scholar
Goodman, Nelson, The Languages of Art, 2nd edn (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1976), p. 4.Google Scholar
Schier, Flint, Deeper into Pictures: An Essay on Pictorial Representation (Cambridge University Press, 1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Picasso, ’s Bull’s Head (1943) appears on the cover of the paperback edition of Walton’s book
Wollheim, Richard, Painting as an Art (Princeton University Press, 1987), p. 46.Google Scholar
Newell, Michael usefully surveys this recent work in What is a Picture? Depiction, Realism, Abstraction (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011), pp. 11–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schier, Flint, Deeper into Pictures (Cambridge University Press, 1986), pp. 43–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hopkins, Robert, Picture, Image and Experience (Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 53–63.Google Scholar
Hyman, John, The Objective Eye: Color, Form, and Reality in the Theory of Art (University of Chicago Press, 2006), p. 73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lopes, Dominic, “Pictorial Color: Aesthetics and Cognitive Science,” Philosophical Psychology 12 (1999), pp. 415–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lopes, Dominic, Understanding Pictures (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), p. 157.Google Scholar
Tomasello, Michael, The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 8–9Google Scholar
Eldridge, Richard, On Moral Personhood: Philosophy, Literature, Criticism, and Self-Understanding (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1987), p. 31 and p. 193Google Scholar
Davidson, D., Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001), pp. 107–21 at pp. 117–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×