Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-5wvtr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T19:53:05.891Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

13 - Legitimating the international rule of law

from Part IV - Projects of international law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 July 2015

B. S. Chimni
Affiliation:
Jawaharlal Nehru University
James Crawford
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Martti Koskenniemi
Affiliation:
University of Helsinki
Get access

Summary

Meaning of the ‘rule of law’

The ‘rule of law’ signifies that all persons (natural or juridical), including organs of the state, should comply with laws adopted through prescribed constitutional procedures. Its essence is the prohibition of the exercise of arbitrary power. The scope of the rule of law includes the procedural guarantees of general laws and an ‘impartial’ due process (Neumann 1985, 265–267; Sypnowich 1990, 55). It has also come to be associated with the protection of core human rights. But despite a certain common understanding, the rule of law ‘is an exceedingly elusive notion’; ‘contrasting meanings are held’ by reasonable people (Tamanaha 2004, 3). There are several reasons for this.

First, the differences can be traced to the use of a positivist as against a deliberative conception of law. The validity of a legal rule is usually traced to adherence to a prescribed procedure, most often laid down in a written constitution. But as Jürgen Habermas points out, rules based only on positive enactment may sometimes lack legitimacy for ‘the belief in legality can produce legitimacy only if we already presuppose the legitimacy of the legal order that lays down what is legal. There is no way out of this circle’ (Habermas 1987, 265). Legitimacy can be secured only if both particular laws and the legal order are justified by good arguments as opposed to drawing strength from compliance with formal processes or being the outcome of the mere exercise of power. Thus if the legal order is based on some originating violence, as it often is, the legitimacy of legal rules tends to be undermined (Derrida 1992, 6). This is of particular relevance when the relationship between colonialism and international law is explored. Habermas’ understanding of the rule of law is however a regulative ideal. The extent to which it is complied with will bestow a greater or lesser degree of legitimacy on the legal order.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexandrowicz, C. H., 1967. International Law in the East Indies: Sixteenth, Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries, Oxford: ClarendonGoogle Scholar
Anghie, A, 1999. ‘Finding the Peripheries: Sovereignty and Colonialism in Nineteenth Century International Law’, Harvard International Law Journal, 40, 1–80Google Scholar
Anghie, A., 2006. ‘Of Critique and the Other’, in Orford, A. (ed.), International Law and its Others, Cambridge University Press, 389–401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bedjaoui, M. 1979. Towards a New International Economic Order, Paris: Holmes & MeirGoogle Scholar
Charlesworth, H. and Chinkin, C., 2000. The Boundaries of International Law: A Feminist Analysis, Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar
Chatterjee, H., 1958. International Law and Inter-state Relations in Ancient India, Calcutta: MukhopadhyayGoogle Scholar
Chimni, B. S., 2004. ‘International Institutions Today: A Global Imperial state in the Making’, European Journal of International Law, 15, 1–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chimni, B. S., 2010. ‘Prolegomenon to a Class approach to International Law’, European Journal of International Law, 21, 57–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derrida, J., 1992. ‘Force of Law: The “Mystical Foundation of Authority”’, in Cornell, D., Rosenfeld, M. and Carlson, D. G. (eds.), Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, New York: Routledge, 3–67Google Scholar
Franck, T., 1992. ‘The Emerging Right to Democratic Governance’, American Journal of International Law, 86, 46–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franck, T., 2006. ‘The Power of Legitimacy and the Legitimacy of Power: International Law in an Age of Disequilibrium’, American Journal of International Law, 100, 88–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gandhi, M. K., 1938. Hind Swaraj, Ahmedabad: Navijivan Publishing HouseGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A., 1971. Selection from Prison Notebooks, London: Lawrence & WishartGoogle Scholar
Habermas, J., 1987. Theory of Communicative Action, Cambridge: PolityGoogle Scholar
Kaviraj, S., 2005. ‘An Outline of a Revisionist Theory of Modernity’, Archives of European Sociology, XLVI, 497–526CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koskenniemi, M., 2005. From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument. Reissue with a New Epilogue, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Marks, S., 2003. The Riddle of all Constitutions: International Law, Democracy, and the Critique of Ideology, Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mehta, U. S., 1999. Liberalism and Empire: India in British Liberal Thought, Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Meinecke, F., 1984. Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d’état and its Place in Modern History, Boulder, CO: Westview PressGoogle Scholar
Menski, W., 2006. Comparative Law in the Global Context: The Legal Systems of Asia and Africa, Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S., 1984. ‘A Few Words on Non-intervention’, in Essays on Equality, Law and Education, University of Toronto Press, 111–124Google Scholar
Morgenthau, H. J., 1948. Politics among Nations, New York: Alfred A. KnopfGoogle Scholar
Morgenthau, H. J., 1981. In Defense of the National Interest, New York: Alfred A. KnopfGoogle Scholar
Mukerji, D. P., 1942. Sociology of Indian Culture, Jaipur: RawatGoogle Scholar
Neumann, F., 1985. The Rule of Law: Political Theory and the Legal System in Modern Society, Leamington Spa: BergGoogle Scholar
Orford, A., 2009. ‘Jurisdiction without Territory: From the Holy Roman Empire to the Responsibility to Protect’, Michigan Journal of International Law, 30, 984–1014Google Scholar
Parekh, B., 2007. ‘Composite Culture and Multicultural Society’, in Chandra, B. and Mahajan, S., (eds.), Composite Culture in a Multinational Society, Delhi: National Book Trust, 3–17Google Scholar
Pollock, S., 2000. ‘Cosmopolitan and Vernacular in History’, Public Culture, 12, 591–625CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roht-Arriaza, N., 2004. ‘Universal Jurisdiction: Steps Forward, Steps Back’, Leiden Journal of International Law, 17, 375–389CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A., 2005. The Argumentative Indian, London: Allen LaneGoogle Scholar
Singh, N., 1973. India and International Law: Ancient and Mediaeval, vol. I, New Delhi: S. ChandGoogle Scholar
Aurobindo, Sri, 1970. The Ideal of Human Unity, Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo AshramGoogle Scholar
Sypnowich, C., 1990. The Concept of Socialist Law, Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Tamanaha, B., 2004. On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory, Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, C., 1979. Hegel and Modern Society, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Taylor, C., 1992. Sources of the Self: The Making of Modern Identity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Thapar, R., 2003. Cultural Pasts: Essays in Early Indian History, Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E. P., 1975. Whigs and Hunters: The Origins of the Black Act, New York: PantheonGoogle Scholar
Unger, R. M., 1976. Law in Modern Society, New York: Free PressGoogle Scholar
Weeramantry, C. G., 1997. ‘The Function of the International Court of Justice in the Development of International Law’, Leiden Journal of International Law, 10, 309–340CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×