Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m42fx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T21:34:49.649Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 6 - The Peripatos

from Part 1 - GREEK PHILOSOPHY FROM PLATO TO PLOTINUS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

The Peripatetic School from Theophrastus to Andronicus and Boethus

The development of the Peripatos down to the time of Strato exhibits two main aspects. First, philosophic-speculative interest is largely replaced by interest in all kinds of special and empirical knowledge, this knowledge no longer to serve as foundation for something higher, but terminal. Secondly, to the extent that philosophic interest is preserved at all, it often finds its satisfaction in non-theological, naturalistic, or even materialistic doctrines. For us only the latter aspect is important, as Plotinus' interest in empirical sciences is minimal.

Clearchus still seems to have refused to follow Aristotle's denial of the substantial character of the soul and presented him in a dialogue as having become convinced by what we should today call a telepathic experiment, that the soul can leave its body and return to it. He, then, would represent Aristotle's original Platonism.

As to Theophrastus, his so-called metaphysical fragment clearly proves that he retained Aristotle's speculative and theological interests. There is particularly no trace that he ever envisioned first philosophy to be anything but theology. The whole fragment is, from our point of view, remarkable mainly for three reasons. First, it shows to what extent Theophrastus connected the problems of Aristotle's Metaphysics with problems of the Two-opposite-principles system, including the derivation of everything from these principles and including the relation between these principles and evil. Secondly, it shows to what extent Theophrastus takes for granted that fundamentally all reality is divided into the spheres of the intelligible and the sensible, the former either including, or consisting of, mathematicals. Thirdly, it shows to what extent Theophrastus takes it for granted that knowledge of first principles will be of a particular type, non-discursive and described best as a kind of touching, so that one can be ignorant of these principles but not mistaken about them.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1967

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Albinus, ed. Hermann, C. F. in Platonis Dialogi, 6 vols. Leipzig, 1921–36; vol. VI.Google Scholar
Albinus, Épitomé, ed. Louis, P.. Paris, 1945.Google Scholar
,Alexander of Aphrodisias Commentaries on Aristotle, in Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca, I–III. Berlin, 1891–9. Minor Works, ed. Bruns, I., in Supplementum Aristotelicum, II, 1–2. Berlin, 1887, 1892.
Anonymous Commentary on the Theaetetus ed. Diels, H. and Schubart, W.. Berlin, 1905.Google Scholar
Antiochus, Fragments, ed. Luck, G. in Der Akademiker Antiochus. Bern, 1953.
Apuleius, De Philosophia libri, ed. Thomas, P.. Leipzig, 1908.Google Scholar
,AristoclesFragments, ed. Heiland, H., Aristoclis Messenii reliquiae.Giessen, 1925.
Armstrong, A., ‘The Background of the Doctrine “That the Intelligibles are not Outside the Intellect”’, Les Sources de Plotin, Entretiens, V (1960)Google Scholar
Atticus, Fragments, in Eusebius, Praeparatio evangelica XI 1–2; XV 4–12; ed. Baudry, J.. Paris, 1931.Google Scholar
Baeumker, C.Das Problem der Materie in der griechischen Philosophie.Munich, 1890 (reprinted Frankfurt, 1963).Google Scholar
Barbotin, E., La Théorie aristotélicienne de l'intellect d'après Théophraste (1954).
Beutler, R., ‘Ocellus’, Realencyclopa¨die der klassischen Altertumswissensch, XVII/2 (1937);Google Scholar
Brink, K. O., ‘Peripatos’, Realencyclopa¨die der klassischen Altertumswissensch, Suppl. VII (1940), esp. col. 914–23; 926–49;Google Scholar
Duhem, P., Le Système du monde II (1914) –6; IV (1916), p. 134;
Fernanda, Trabucco, ‘Il problema del “de philosophia” di Aristocle di Messene e la sua dottrina’, Acme, XI (1958).Google Scholar
Grumach, E., Physis und Agathon (1932), p. 49 n. 64;
Hamelin, O.La théorie de l' intellect d'après Aristote et ses commentateurs.Paris, 1953.Google Scholar
Immisch, C.Agatharchidea’, in Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie d. Wissenschaften, philos.-hist. Kl. 1919.7 (1919).Google Scholar
Jaeger, W., Aristoteles (21955), p. n. 1.
Krämer, H. J.Der Ursprung der Geistmetaphysik.Amsterdam, 1964.Google Scholar
Levi, A., ‘Il concetto del tempo nella filosofia dell'etá romana’, Rivista Critica di Storia della Filosofia, VII (1952).Google Scholar
Merlan, P., ‘Aristotle's Unmoved Movers’, Traditio, IV (1946).Google Scholar
Merlan, P.From Platonism to Neoplatonism, 2nd edn. The Hague, 1960.Google Scholar
Merlan, P.Monopsychism, Mysticism, Metaconsciousness.The Hague, 1963.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merlsn, P., Monopsychism, Mysticism, Metaconsciousness (1963), p. 9.CrossRef
Moraux, P.Quinta essentia’, in Paulys Realencyclopädie, 24.1 (1963).Google Scholar
Moraux, P.Alexandre d'Aphrodise.Paris, 1942.Google Scholar
Nicomachus, Introductio arithmetica, ed. Hoche, R.. Leipzig, 1866.Google Scholar
Numenius, Fragments, ed. Leemans, E. A.. Brussels, 1937.Google Scholar
,PanaetiusFragments, ed. Straaten, M., 3rd edn. Leyden, 1962.Google Scholar
,PeripateticsFragments, ed. Wehrli, F. (Die Schule des Aristoteles), 10 vols. Basel, 1944–59.
Plezia, M., De Andronici Rhodii studiis aristotelicis (1946), important also for Nicostratus, Albinus, and others.
Plutarch, Moralia, ed. Hubert, C., Pohlenz, M., etc.: in progress. Leipzig, 1952–.Google Scholar
Plutarch, Moralia, ed. Bernardakis, G. N., 7 vols. Leipzig, 1888–96.Google Scholar
Plutarch, Moralia, ed. and tr. Babbitt, F. C., etc. (Loeb Classical Library): in progress. London, 1927–.Google Scholar
Pohlenz, M.Die Stoa, 2 vols., 3rd edn. Göttingen, 1964.Google Scholar
,PosidoniusFragments, ed. Bake, I.. Posidonii Rhodii reliquiae.Leyden, 1820.
,ProclusElements of Theology, ed. and tr. Dodds, E. R., 2nd edn. Oxford, 1963.Google Scholar
,Pseudo-Aristotlede mundo ed. and tr. Furley, D. J. (Loeb Classical Library). London, 1955.Google Scholar
Regenbogen, O., ‘Theophrastos’, Realencyclopa¨die der klassischen Altertumswissensch, Suppl. VII (1940), col. 1393; 1395; 1496; 1547 f.Google Scholar
Robin, L.La théorie platonicienne des idées et des nombres d'après Aristote.Paris, 1908 (reprinted Hildesheim, 1963).Google Scholar
Rutten, C., Les Catégories du monde sensible dans les ‘Ennéades’ de Plotin (1961).
Sambursky, S.The Physical World of Late Antiquity.London, 1962.Google Scholar
Solmsen, F., Aristotle's System of the Physical World (1960).
Speusippus, Fragments, ed. Lang, P. in De Speusippi Academici scriptis. Bonn, 1911 (reprinted Frankfurt, 1964).
Spoerri, W., Späthellenistische Berichte über Welt, Kultur und Götter (1959).
,the older stoaStoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, ed. Arnim, J., 4 vols. Leipzig, 1903–24.Google Scholar
Theiler, W.Plotin und die an tike Philosophie’, in Museum Helveticum, 1 (1944).Google Scholar
Theiler, W.Die Vorbereitung des Neuplatonismus.Berlin, 1930.Google Scholar
Theophrastus, Metaphysics, ed. and tr. Ross, W. D. and Fobes, F. H.. Oxford, 1929.Google Scholar
Thillet, P.Un traité inconnu d'Alexandre d'Aphrodise sur la Providence dans une version inédite’, in Actes du Premier Congrès International de Philosophie Médiévale: L'Homme et son destin (Louvain, 1960).Google Scholar
Witt, R. E.Albinus and the History of Middle Platonism.Cambridge, 1937.Google Scholar
Wolfson, H. A.Philo, 2 vols. Cambridge (Mass.), 1947.Google Scholar
Xenocrates, Fragments, ed. Heinze, R.. Leipzig, 1892.Google Scholar
Ziegler, K.Plutarchos’, in Paulys Realencyclopädie, 21.1 (1951).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • The Peripatos
  • Edited by A. H. Armstrong
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521040549.007
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • The Peripatos
  • Edited by A. H. Armstrong
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521040549.007
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • The Peripatos
  • Edited by A. H. Armstrong
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521040549.007
Available formats
×