Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-q6k6v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T11:19:14.688Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

26 - Science and certainty

from IV - Soul and knowledge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2011

Robert Pasnau
Affiliation:
University of Colorado Boulder
Get access

Summary

When James of Venice translated the Posterior Analytics from Greek into Latin, in the second quarter of the twelfth century, European philosophy got one of the great shocks of its long history. John of Salisbury famously remarked that “it has nearly as many obstacles as it has chapters, if indeed there are not more obstacles than chapters” (Metalogicon IV.6). Latin philosophers had taken themselves to have a grip on Aristotle’s logic, but what they were discovering in the twelfth century was that their grasp extended only to what would be called the Old Logic, the ars vetus, leaving untouched the New Logic of the Topics, the Sophistical Refutations and, most importantly, the Prior and Posterior Analytics.Moreover, as the Latin philosophical canon swelled in the later twelfth century to include not just the full Aristotelian corpus but also the riches of Arabic philosophy, European authors realized just what a central role the Posterior Analytics in particular played in all this work. Although we now tend to focus on the recovery of Aristotle’s natural philosophy, metaphysics, and ethics, it is arguably the Posterior Analytics – not the Ethics, the Metaphysics, the Physics, or the De anima – that had the most pervasive influence on scholastic thought. For it is here that Aristotle sets out the methodological principles that are to be followed in the pursuit of systematic, scientific knowledge: what the Latin tradition would call scientia.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bermon, Pascale, L’assentiment et son objet chez Grégoire de Rimini (Paris: Vrin, 2007).Google Scholar
Black, Deborah L., “Knowledge (ʿilm) and Certitude (yaqīn) in al-Fārābī’s Epistemology,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 16 (2006).Google Scholar
Brower-Toland, Susan, “Facts vs. Things: Adam Wodeham and the Later Medieval Debate over Objects of Judgment,” Review of Metaphysics 60 (2006).Google Scholar
Horowitz, T. and Janis, A. (eds.), Scientific Failure, (Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994).Google Scholar
Jabre, Farid, La notion de certitude selon Ghazali dans ses origines psychologiques et historiques (Paris: Vrin, 1958).Google Scholar
Khalidi, Muhammad Ali, Medieval Islamic Philosophical Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, Peter, “Jean Buridan’s Philosophy of Science,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 18 (1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marrone, Steven P., The Light of Thy Countenance: Science and Knowledge of God in the Thirteenth Century (Leiden: Brill, 2001).Google Scholar
McGinnis, Jon, “Scientific Methodologies in Medieval Islam,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moody, E. A., “A Quodlibetal Question of Robert Holcot, O.P. on the Problem of the Objects of Knowledge and of Belief,” Speculum 39 (1964).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasnau, Robert, Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. III: Mind and Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Pasnau, Robert, “Henry of Ghent and the Twilight of Divine Illumination,” Review of Metaphysics 49 (1995).Google Scholar
Reisman, D. C., Classical Arabic Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2007).Google Scholar
Reynolds, Philip, “Properties, Causality, and Epistemic Optimism in Thomas Aquinas,” Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévale 68 (2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Serene, Eileen, “Demonstrative Science,” in Kretzmann, N. et al. (eds.) The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Thijssen, J. and Zupko, J. (eds.) The Metaphysics and Natural Philosophy of John Buridan (Leiden: Brill, 2001).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×