Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-7drxs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-18T20:06:21.878Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

14 - Moral Epistemology, 1788–1870

from V - Ethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2012

Allen W. Wood
Affiliation:
Stanford University, California
Songsuk Susan Hahn
Affiliation:
Université Concordia, Montréal, Québec
Get access

Summary

The aftermath of the French Revolution forced European thinkers to confront the problem of restoring and preserving social stability. Could a revitalized Christianity ensure that the great mass of the population would not be swept up again in revolutionary fervor? If Christianity could no longer perform the task of teaching contentment with their lot to the disenfranchised and poor, what could do so? The consequences of trying to reform society had proven devastating in France. No one wanted to bring such upheavals upon Europe again. Was every reformist doctrine as dangerous as the doctrine of the rights of man? Or was some sort of reform a price to be paid for the restoration of order?

Revolutions and reform movements during the first two-thirds of the century kept such questions alive. In British and French moral philosophy between the French Revolution and the Franco-Prussian War the question of the role of intuition in providing moral knowledge was a central theme. The recurrent social and political crises of the period help explain why. Those who shaped opinion agreed that general acceptance of Christianity was essential to social stability. Philosophers who took intuition to provide the basis of morality were taken to be supporting religion. Most of those who rejected intuitionism were not. On both sides, the epistemological issue had two parts. One concerned the ultimate justification for moral belief. Almost no one thought morality was wholly a matter of feeling. What rational warrant, then, could it have? The other concerned the extent to which warranted moral beliefs are available to everyone whose conduct they should guide. Can we all think out for ourselves what we ought to do, or must some people – perhaps the majority – take their morals on authority from others?

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bentham, Jeremy. A Fragment on Government and An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Ed. Harrison, Wilfrid. Oxford: Blackwell, 1948.Google Scholar
Brooks, John I. The Eclectic Legacy: Academic Philosophy and the Human Sciences in Nineteenth-Century France. Newark: University of Delaware Press, 1998.Google Scholar
Cousin, Victor. Fragments philosophiques. Paris: Didier, 1856.Google Scholar
Destutt de Tracy, Antoine Louis Claude. Élemens d’idéologie. Paris: Mme Lévi, 1801–5.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. Fichtes sämmtliche Werke. Ed. Fichte, I. H.. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1970.Google Scholar
Fries, Jacob Friedrich. Anthropologische Kritik der Vernunft. Heidelberg: Mohr & Winter, 1838.Google Scholar
Fries, Jacob FriedrichHandbuch der Praktischen Philosophien. Heidelberg: Mohr & Winter, 1818.Google Scholar
Fries, Jacob FriedrichNeue Kritik der Vernunft. Heidelberg: Mohr, 1807.Google Scholar
Grote, John. Treatise on the Moral Ideals. Ed. Mayor, Joseph Bickersteth. Cambridge: Deighton, Bell, 1876.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Werke: Theoriewerkausgabe. Eds. Moldenhauer, Eva and Michel, Karl Markus. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970–.Google Scholar
Jouffroy, Theodore. Introduction to Ethics. Boston: Hilliard, Gray, 1840.Google Scholar
Kant, Imannuel. Kants Gesammelte Schriften. Ed. Preussische, Königlich (later Deutsche und Berlin-Brandenburgische) Akademie der Wissenschaften, 29 vols. Berlin: G. Reimer (later Walter de Gruyter), 1900–.Google Scholar
Lotze, Rudolf Hermann. Microcosmus. Trans. Hamilton, Elizabeth and Constance Jones, E. E.. New York: Scribner, 1890.Google Scholar
Lotze, Rudolf HermannMikrokosmus: Ideen zur Naturgeschichte und Geschichte der Menschheit. Versuch einer Anthropologie. 3 vols. Leipzig: Hirzel, 1856, 1858, 1864.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Ed. Robson, John M.. 33 vols. Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963–91.Google Scholar
Reid, Thomas. The Works of Thomas Reid, D.D. Now Fully Collected, With Selections from His Unpublished Letters. Preface, notes, and supplementary dissertations by Sir William Hamilton. 9th ed. Edinburgh, 1895.Google Scholar
William H. Channing’s “Preface” to his translation of Theodore Jouffroy, Introduction to Ethics, 2 vols. (Boston, 1848), 12–13
Reid, Thomas, Works, ed. Sir William Hamilton, 9th ed. (Edinburgh, 1895) [hereafter Reid, Works). His moral philosophy is in his Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind (Edinburgh, 1789)Google Scholar
Schneewind, J. B., Sidgwick’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), chap. 2.iGoogle Scholar
I cite from A Fragment on Government and An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. Wilfrid Harrison (Oxford, Blackwell, 1948). The work was set in type in 1780, but Bentham held back publication
Empiricism was represented not only by Locke and Condillac but also by Destutt de Tracy, who reformulated it in his Élemens d’idéologie (Paris, 1801–5). He says nothing about moral philosophy
Cousin, Victor, Fragments philosophiques (Paris: Didier, 1856), 238Google Scholar
I cite from the English translation: The True, the Beautiful, and the Good, trans. O. W. Wight (New York: D. Appleton, 1854)
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, Fichtes sämmtliche Werke, ed. I. H. Fichte (Berlin: Walter De Gruyter, 1971)Google Scholar
Fries, J. F., Neue Kritik der Vernunft (Heidelberg: Mohr, 1807)Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F., Werke: Theoriewerkausgabe, eds. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl Markus Michel (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970) [henceforth Hegel, Werke]. Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen W. Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet, 3rd ed. (Cambridge Cambridge University Press, 1991), 149Google Scholar
Lotze, Rudolf Hermann, Mikrokosmus: Ideen zur Naturgeschichte und Geschichte der Menschheit. Versuch einer Anthropologie, 3 vols. (Leipzig, 1856, 1858, 1864)Google Scholar
Microcosmus, trans. Elizabeth Hamilton and E. E. Constance Jones (New York: Scribner, 1890) (cited as Mikrokosmos, by page or by chapter and section in vol. 1)
Lotze, , System der Philosophie. Erster Teil: Drei Bücher der Logik (Leipzig, 1874)Google Scholar
Logic, trans. Bernard Bosanquet (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1888) (cited as Logic, by page number or section number). The account of “the world of ideas” occurs in bk. III, chap. II, §§313–21

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×