Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-7nlkj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-27T17:26:11.080Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Originalism’s Constitution

from Part Three - Originalism and Constitutional Settlement

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 October 2011

Grant Huscroft
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario
Bradley W. Miller
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario
Get access

Summary

Introduction

What is originalism? Given the breadth and depth of scholarship on the matter, the question may suffer from an embarrassment of different answers. One might appeal to the “old originalism” with its focus on the intentions of the founders or the “new originalism” with its focus on the public meaning at the founding; in turn, one might review the range of originalisms that animate constitutional scholarship since the turn to new originalism. Proceeding in this way would reveal that the answer to our question is not obvious or, rather more accurately, any single answer purporting to identify a single account of originalism would likely be contestable. The contest would be raised not only within the family of originalists, but also over who may be admitted therein, as not all self-proclaimed originalists are recognized by others to be members of the same set. But proceeding with this genre of answer would already assume a prior answer to our question. For before one seeks to identify the commands and commitments of originalism, one must situate originalism within the world of constitutional theory, namely as a theory of interpretation.

Originalism, of course, is usually situated alongside other theories of constitutional interpretation. In the United States, it is contrasted with living constitutionalism or, in rather less descriptive and more encompassing terms, with “non-originalism.” At other times or in other jurisdictions, competing theories of interpretation may include textualism or intratextualism, purposive or progressive interpretation, moral principles, representation-reinforcing interpretation, structural or unwritten constitutional principles, and living-tree constitutionalism, to name but a few. Much of the debate surrounding originalism has focused on its inherent and comparative merits as a theory of interpretation. Reasons supporting originalism have been first-order (inherent to originalism's methodology) and second-order (comparative to other interpretive approaches and instrumental to pursuing good ends), as well as directed to what the task of interpretation must of necessity be and what it should be. These debates have contributed in important ways to our understanding of originalism. But just as the focus on originalism as a theory of interpretation has assisted in focusing attention on specific commitments of originalism, it has also privileged one vantage point over others, perhaps keeping from view other related commitments. How might these be brought to light?

Type
Chapter
Information
The Challenge of Originalism
Theories of Constitutional Interpretation
, pp. 147 - 178
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barnett, Randy E. 2004
1999
Hogg, Peter W.Goldsworthy, Jeffrey 2006
Dworkin, Ronald 1996
Ely, John Hart 1980
Dyzenhaus, David 2008
Waluchow, W. J. 2007
Smith, Steven D.Huscroft, Grant 2008
2009
Rubenfeld, Jed 2001
Waldron, Jeremy 1999
Scalia, AntoninGutmann, Amy 1997
Whittington, Keith E. 1999
Brodie, IanConstitutionalism in the Charter Era 2004 CanadaGoogle Scholar
Loughlin, M.Walker, N.Loughlin, MartinWalker, Neil 2007
Scalia, AntoninOriginalism: The Lesser Evil 57 U. Cin. L. Rev 1989Google Scholar
Barnett, Randy E.Scalia's Infidelity: A Critique of ‘Faint-Hearted’ Originalism75 U. Cin. L. Rev 7 2006Google Scholar
2006
Powell, H. Jefferson 2002
Tushnet, Mark 1999
Sajó, Andras 1999
Allan, T.R.S. 2003
2006
2007
Bork, Robert H. 1990
Scalia, AntoninThe Rule of Law as a Law of Rules56 University Chicago L. Rev 1175 1989Google Scholar
Bickel, Alexander M. 1986
Ackerman, B. 1991
Rubenfeld, Jeb 2005
Hart, H. L. A. 1994
Raz, JosephAlexander, L. 1998
George, Robert P. 1992
Whittington, 2001
Rehnquist, W. H. 1976
Webber, Grégoire C. N. 2009
1996

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×