Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-xq9c7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-08T14:20:44.542Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 January 2011

Noa Naaman-Zauderer
Affiliation:
Tel-Aviv University
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Descartes' Deontological Turn
Reason, Will, and Virtue in the Later Writings
, pp. 205 - 212
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alanen, L. 1990. “Cartesian Ideas and Intentionality,” Acta Philosophica Fennica 49: 344–69.Google Scholar
Alanen, L. 1994. “Sensory Ideas, Objective Reality, and Material Falsity,” in Cottingham, (ed.), pp. 229–50.
Alanen, L. 2003. Descartes's Concept of Mind, Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Alanen, L. 2008. “Omnipotence, Modality, and Conceivability,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 353–71.
Alquié, F. 1950. La découverte métaphysique de l'homme chez Descartes, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Alquié, F. (ed.) 1967. Oeuvres philosophiques de Descartes, vol. ii, Paris: Éditions Garnier Frères.
Aquinas, St. Thomas. 1975. Summa Contra Gentiles [1259–1264/54], ed. and trans. Bourke, V. J., Dame, Notre and London: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Ariew, R., and Garber, D. (eds. and trans.) 1989. G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Essays, Indianapolis and Cambridge, MA: Hackett Publishing Company.
Aristotle, . 1985. Nicomachean Ethics [c. 325 BC], trans. Irwin, T., Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Ayers, M. 1998. “Ideas and Objective Being,” in Garber, and Ayers, (eds.), pp. 1062–107.
Beck, L. J. 1952. The Method of Descartes: A Study of the Regulae, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Beyssade, J.-M. 1992. “Descartes on Material Falsity,” in Cummins, and Zoeller, (eds.), pp. 5–20.
Beyssade, J.-M. 1993. “On the Idea of God: Incomprehensibility or Incompatibilities?,” in Voss, (ed.), pp. 85–94.
Beyssade, M. 1994. “Descartes's Doctrine of Freedom: Differences between the French and Latin Texts of the Fourth Meditation,” in Cottingham, (ed.), pp. 191–206.
Bolton, M. B. 1986. “Confused and Obscure Ideas of Sense,” in Rorty, (ed.), pp. 389–403.
Bordo, S. R. 1987. The Flight to Objectivity: Essays on Cartesianism and Culture, Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Broughton, J. 2002. Descartes's Method of Doubt, Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Broughton, J. 2008. “Self-Knowledge,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 179–95.
Broughton, J. and Carriero, J. (eds.) 2008. A Companion to Descartes, Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, D. J. 2006. Descartes and the Passionate Mind, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, D. J. 2008. “Descartes on True and False Ideas,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 196–215.
Butler, R. J. (ed.) 1972. Cartesian Studies, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Campbell, J. K. 1999. “Descartes on Spontaneity, Indifference, and Alternatives,” in Gennaro, R. J. and Huenemann, C. (eds.), New Essays on the Rationalists, Oxford University Press, pp. 179–99.Google Scholar
Carriero, J. 2008. “The Cartesian Circle and the Foundations of Knowledge,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 302–18.
Caton, H. 1975. “Will and Reason in Descartes's Theory of Error,” Journal of Philosophy 72: 87–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chappell, V. 1986. “The Theory of Ideas,” in Rorty, (ed.), pp. 177–98.
Chappell, V. 1994. “Descartes's Compatibilism,” in Cottingham, (ed.), pp. 177–90.
Chappell, V. 1997. “Descartes's Ontology,” Topoi 16: 111–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, D. M. 1982. Descartes' Philosophy of Science, Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, D. M. 2003. Descartes's Theory of Mind, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clatterbaugh, K. C. 1980. “Descartes' Causal Likeness Principle,” Philosophical Review 89: 379–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coolidge, F. P. 1991. “The Insufficiency of Descartes' Provisional Morality,” International Philosophical Quarterly 31: 275–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costa, M. J. 1983. “What Cartesian Ideas Are Not,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 21: 537–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cottingham, J. 1996. “Cartesian Ethics: Reason and the Passions,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 50: 193–216.Google Scholar
Cottingham, J. 1997. “Descartes, Sixth Meditation: The External World, ‘Nature’ and Human Experience,” in V. Chappell (ed.), Descartes's Meditations: Critical Essays, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 207–23.Google Scholar
Cottingham, J. 1998. Philosophy and the Good Life: Reason and the Passions in Greek, Cartesian and Psychoanalytic Ethics, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cottingham, J. 2002. “Descartes and the Voluntariness of Belief,” Monist 85: 343–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cottingham, J. 2008a. “The Role of God in Descartes's Philosophy,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 288–301.
Cottingham, J. 2008b. Cartesian Reflections: Essays on Descartes's Philosophy, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cottingham, J. (ed.) 1992. The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Cottingham, J. 1994. Reason, Will, and Sensation: Studies in Descartes's Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cottingham, J. (trans. with Introduction and Commentary) 1976. Descartes' Conversation with Burman, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Cover, J. A., and Kulstad, M. (eds.) 1990. Central Themes in Early Modern Philosophy, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
Cress, D. 1994. “Truth, Error, and the Order of Reason: Descartes' Puzzling Synopsis of the Fourth Meditation,” in Cottingham, (ed.), pp. 141–55.
Cronin, T. J. 1966. Objective Being in Descartes and Suárez, Rome: Gregorian University Press.Google Scholar
Cumming, R. 1955. “Descartes' Provisional Morality,” Review of Metaphysics 9: 207–235.Google Scholar
Cummins, P. D., and Zoeller, G. (eds.) 1992. Minds, Ideas and Objects: Essays on the Theory of Representation in Modern Philosophy, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Press.Google Scholar
Cunning, D. 2003. “True and Immutable Natures and Epistemic Progress in Descartes'sMeditations,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11: 235–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curley, E. M. 1975. “Descartes, Spinoza and the Ethics of Belief,” in Mandelbaum, M. and Freeman, E. (eds.), Spinoza, Essays in Interpretation, LaSalle, IL: Open Court, pp. 159–89.Google Scholar
Curley, E. M. 1978. Descartes against the Skeptics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curley, E. M. 1986. “Analysis in the Meditations: The Quest for Clear and Distinct Ideas,” in Rorty, (ed.), pp. 153–76.
Curley, E. M. 1993. “Certainty: Psychological, Moral, and Metaphysical,” in Voss, (ed.), pp. 11–30.
Curley, E. M. (ed. and trans.) 1985. The Collected Works of Spinoza, Princeton University Press.
Danto, A. 1978. “The Representational Character of Ideas and the Problem of the External World,” in Hooker, (ed.), pp. 287–98.
Davies, R. 2001. Descartes: Belief, Scepticism and Virtue, London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Della Rocca, M. 2005. “Descartes, the Cartesian Circle, and Epistemology without God,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70: 1–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Della Rocca, M. 2006. “Judgment and Will,” in Gaukroger, (ed.), pp. 142–59.
Della Rocca, M. 2008. “Causation without Intelligibility and Causation without God in Descartes,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 235–50.
Doney, W. 2005. “True and Immutable Natures,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13: 131–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Espinas, A. 1925. Descartes et la morale, Paris: Éditions Brossard.Google Scholar
Evans, J. L. 1963. “Error and the Will,” Philosophy 38: 136–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, R. W. 1993. “Descartes on the Material Falsity of Ideas,” Philosophical Review 102: 309–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1970. Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes's Meditations, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1977. “Descartes on the Creation of Eternal Truths,” Philosophical Review 86: 36–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1978. “Descartes on the Consistency of Reason,” in Hooker, (ed.), pp. 26–39.
Friedman, M. 2008. “Descartes and Galileo: Copernicanism and the Metaphysical Foundations of Physics,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 69–83.
Garber, D. 1992. Descartes' Metaphysical Physics, University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Garber, D. 1993. “Descartes and Experiment in the Discourse and Essays,” in Voss, (ed.), pp. 288–310 (repr. in Garber 2001, pp. 85–110).
Garber, D. 2001. Descartes Embodied: Reading Descartes through Cartesian Science, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Garber, D. and Ayers, M. (eds.) 1998. The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy, 2 vols., Cambridge University Press.
Garber, D. and Nadler, S. (eds.) 2006. Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, Oxford University Press.
Gaukroger, S. 1995. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Gaukroger, S. (ed.) 1998. The Soft Underbelly of Reason: The Passions in the Seventeenth Century, London and New York: Routledge.CrossRef
Gewirth, A. 2006. The Blackwell Guide to Descartes' Meditations, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gebhardt, C. (ed.) 1925. Spinoza Opera, 4 vols., Heidelberg: Carl Winter.
Gewirth, A. 1941. “The Cartesian Circle,” Philosophical Review 50: 368–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gewirth, A. 1943. “Clearness and Distinctness in Descartes,” Philosophy 18: 17–36. Page numbers refer to reprinting in W. Doney (ed.) 1967. Descartes: A Collection of Critical Essays, New York: Doubleday, pp. 250–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gewirth, A. 1970. “The Cartesian Circle Reconsidered,” Journal of Philosophy 67: 668–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, A. B. 1987. The Philosophy of Descartes, New York and London: Garland Publishing.Google Scholar
Gilbert, C. 2005. “Grades of Freedom: Augustine and Descartes,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86: 201–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilson, É. 1913. La liberté chez Descartes et la théologie, Paris: Alcan.Google Scholar
Gilson, É. 1967. Études sur le rôle de la pensée médiévale dans la formation du système cartésien, Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Gilson, É. (ed.) 1947. Discours de la Méthode: texte et commentaire, Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Grene, M. 1985. Descartes, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Gueroult, M. 1984. Descartes' Philosophy Interpreted according to the Order of Reasons, 2 vols., trans. Ariew, R., Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Hatfield, G. 1986. “The Sense and the Fleshless eye: The Meditations as Cognitive Exercise,” in Rorty, (ed.), pp. 45–80.
Hobbes, Thomas. 1840. “Of Liberty and Necessity” [1654], in W. Molesworth (ed.), The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, vol. iv, London: John Bohn, pp. 229–78.Google Scholar
Hoffman, P. 1996. “Descartes on Misrepresentation,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 34: 357–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, P. 2002. “Direct Realism, Intentionality, and the Objective Being of Ideas,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83: 163–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, P. 2003. “The Passions and Freedom of Will,” in Williston, and Gombay, (eds.), pp. 261–99.
Hoffman, P. 2009. Essays on Descartes, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hooker, M. (ed.) 1978. Descartes: Critical and Interpretative Essays, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Imlay, R. A. 1982. “Descartes and Indifference,” Studia Leibnitiana 14: 87–97.Google Scholar
James, S. 1997. Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
James, S. 1998. “Explaining the Passions: Passions, Desires, and the Explanation of Action,” in Gaukroger, (ed.), pp. 17–33.
Jolley, N. 1990. The Light of the Soul: Theories of Ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kaufman, D. 2000. “Descartes on the Objective Reality of Materially False Ideas,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 81: 385–408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaufman, D. 2003a. “Infimus gradus libertatis? Descartes on Indifference and Divine Freedom,” Religious Studies 39: 391–406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaufman, D. 2003b. “Divine Simplicity and the Eternal Truths in Descartes,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11: 553–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaufman, D. 2005. “God's Immutability and the Necessity of Descartes's Eternal Truths,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 43: 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keefe, T. 1972. “Descartes's ‘Morale Provisoire’: A Reconsideration,” French Studies 26: 129–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, A. 1968. Descartes: A Study of His Philosophy, New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1970. “The Cartesian Circle and the Eternal Truths,” Journal of Philosophy 57: 685–700.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, A. 1972. “Descartes on the Will,” in Butler, (ed.), pp. 1–31.
Larmore, C. 1984. “Descartes' Psychologistic Theory of Assent,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1: 61–74.Google Scholar
Dœuff, M. 1989. The Philosophical Imaginary, trans. Gordon, C., London: Athlone Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John. 1995. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding [1689], New York: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Loeb, L. E. 1990. “The Priority of Reason in Descartes,” Philosophical Review 99: 3–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loeb, L. E. 1992. “The Cartesian Circle,” in Cottingham, (ed.), pp. 200–35.
Loemker, L. E. 1969. G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters, 2nd edn., Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. 1996. Stoic Studies, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
MacKenzie, A. W. 1994. “The Recognition of Sensory Experience,” in Cottingham, (ed.), pp. 251–72.
Marion, J.-L. 1991. Sur la théologie blanche de Descartes, 2nd edn., Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Marion, J.-L. 1993. “Generosity and Phenomenology: Remarks on Michel Henry's Interpretation of the Cartesian Cogito,” in Voss, (ed.), pp. 52–74 (repr. in Marion, J.-L. 1999. Cartesian Questions: Method and Metaphysics, University of Chicago Press, pp. 96–117).Google Scholar
Markie, P. 1986. Descartes's Gambit, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. 1998. Descartes' Moral Theory, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. 2003. “Descartes' Morale par Provision,” in Williston, and Gombay, (eds.), pp. 191–238.
McRae, R. 1972. “Descartes' Definition of Thought,” in Butler, (ed.), pp. 55–70.
Menn, S. 1998. Descartes and Augustine, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, V. 1994. Foundations of Cartesian Ethics, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Moyal, G. J. D. 1987. “The Unity of Descartes' Conception of Freedom,” International Studies in Philosophy 19: 33–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mullin, A. 2000. “Descartes and the Community of Inquirers,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 17: 1–27.Google Scholar
Naaman-Zauderer, N. 2000. “Descartes: Error without Falsity,” in Senderowicz, Y. and Wahl, Y. (eds.), Descartes: Reception and Disenchantment, Tel Aviv: University Publishing Projects, pp. 173–93.Google Scholar
Naaman-Zauderer, N. 2004. “The Loneliness of the Cartesian Thinker,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 21: 43–62.Google Scholar
Naaman-Zauderer, N. 2007. Descartes: The Loneliness of a Philosopher, Tel Aviv University Press [in Hebrew].Google Scholar
Naaman-Zauderer, N. 2008. “The Place of the Other in Leibniz's Rationalism,” in M Dascal (ed.) Leibniz: What Kind of Rationalist?Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 315–27.Google Scholar
Nadler, S. 1989. Arnauld and the Cartesian Philosophy of Ideas, Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nadler, S. 2006. “The Doctrine of Ideas,” in Gaukroger, (ed.), pp. 86–103.
Nelson, A. 1996. “The Falsity in Sensory Ideas: Descartes and Arnauld,” in Kremer, E. J. (ed.), Interpreting Arnauld, University of Toronto Press, pp. 13–32.Google Scholar
Nelson, A. 1997. “Descartes' Ontology of Thought,” Topoi 16: 163–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, A. 2008. “Cartesian Innateness,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 319–33.
Newman, L. 1999. “The Fourth Meditation,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59: 559–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newman, L. 2008. “Descartes on the Will in Judgment,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 334–52.
Nolan, L. 1997. “The Ontological Status of Cartesian Natures,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78: 169–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Normore, C. 1986. “Meaning and Objective Being: Descartes and His Sources,” in Rorty, (ed.), pp. 223–41.
Patterson, S. 2008. “Clear and Distinct Perception,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 216–34.
Perin, C. 2008. “Descartes and the Legacy of Ancient Skepticism,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 52–65.
Ragland, C. P. 2006a. “Descartes on the Principle of Alternative Possibilities,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 44: 377–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ragland, C. P. 2006b. “Alternative Possibilities in Descartes's Fourth Meditation,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14: 379–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ragland, C. P. 2006c. “Is Descartes a Libertarian?,” in Garber, and Nadler, (eds.), pp. 57–90.
Rodis-Lewis, G. 1970. La morale de Descartes, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Rodis-Lewis, G. 1987. “Le dernier fruit de la métaphysique cartésienne: la générosité,” Etudes Philosophiques 1: 43–54.Google Scholar
Rodis-Lewis, G. 1989. “Introduction,” in Voss, (ed. and trans.), pp. xv–xxv.
Rodis-Lewis, G. 1990. “Liberté et égalité chez Descartes,” Archives de Philosophie 53: 421–30.Google Scholar
Rodis-Lewis, G. 1998. Descartes: His Life and Thought, trans. Todd, J. M., Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, A. O. (ed.) 1986. Essays on Descartes' Meditations, Berkeley: University of California Press.
Rosenthal, D. M. 1986. “Will and the Theory of Judgment,” in Rorty, (ed.), pp. 405–34.
Rubin, R. 1977. “Descartes's Validation of Clear and Distinct Apprehension,” Philosophical Review 86: 197–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutherford, D. 2004. “On the Happy Life: Descartes vis-à-vis Seneca,” in Strange, S. K. and Zupko, J. (eds.), Stoicism: Traditions and Transformations, New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 177–97.Google Scholar
Schmaltz, T. M. 1991. “Platonism and Descartes' View of Immutable Essences,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 73: 129–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmaltz, T. M. 1994. “Human Freedom and Divine Creation in Malebranche, Descartes and the Cartesians,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2: 3–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmaltz, T. M. 2000. “The Disappearance of Analogy in Descartes, Spinoza, and Regis,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30: 85–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Secada, J. 2000. Cartesian Metaphysics: The Late Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, L. 1999. “Cartesian Generosity,” in T. Aho and M. Yrjonsuuri (eds.), Norms and Modes of Thinking in Descartes, Acta Philosophica Fennica 64: 249–75.Google Scholar
Spinoza, Benedictus 2008. “Descartes's Ethics,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 445–63.
Shapiro, L. (ed. and trans.) 2007. The Correspondence between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes, University of Chicago Press.
Simmons, A. 1999. “Are Cartesian Sensations Representational?,” Nous 33: 347–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, K. 2001. “A General Theory of Cartesian Clarity and Distinctness Based on the Theory of Enumeration in theRules,” Dialogue 40: 279–309.Google Scholar
Suárez, Francisco. 1965. Disputationes metaphysicae [1597], Hildesheim: Olms (repr. from Opera omnia, vols. xxv–xxvi, Paris: Louis Vivès, 1856–59).Google Scholar
Sutton, J. 1998. “Controlling the Passions: Passions, Memory, and the Moral Physiology of Self in Seventeenth-Century Neurophilosophy,” in Gaukroger, (ed.), pp. 115–46.
Taylor, C. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tierno, J. T. 1997. Descartes on God and Human Error, Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Pitte, F. 1988. “Intuition and Judgment in Descartes's Theory of Truth,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 26: 453–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vinci, T. C. 1998. Cartesian Truth, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voss, S. (ed.) 1993. Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Voss, S. (ed. and trans.), 1989. René Descartes: The Passions of the Soul, Indianapolis and Cambridge, MA: Hackett Publishing Company.
Wee, C. 2006a. Material Falsity and Error in Descartes's Meditations, London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wee, C. 2006b. “Descartes and Leibniz on Human Free Will and the Ability to Do Otherwise,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36: 387–414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wells, N. J. 1984. “Material Falsity in Descartes, Arnauld, and Suárez,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 22: 25–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wells, N. J. 1990. “Objective Reality of Ideas in Descartes, Caterus and Suárez,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 28: 33–61.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1973. Problems of the Self, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. 1978. Descartes: The Project of Pure Inquiry, New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Williston, B. 1997. “Descartes on Love and/as Error,” Journal of the History of Ideas 58: 429–44.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Williston, B. 1999. “Akrasia and the Passions in Descartes”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7: 33–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williston, B. and Gombay, A. (eds.) 2003. Passion and Virtue in Descartes, Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.
Wilson, C. 2008. “Descartes and Augustine,” in Broughton, and Carriero, (eds.), pp. 33–51.
Wilson, M. D. 1978. Descartes, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, M. D. 1990. “Descartes on the Representationality of Sensation,” in Cover, and Kulstad, (eds.), pp. 1–22.
Wilson, M. D. 1993. “Descartes on the Perception of Primary Qualities,” in Voss, (ed.), pp. 162–76.
Wilson, M. D. 1994. “Descartes on Sense and ‘Resemblance’,” in Cottingham, (ed.), pp. 209–28.
Yolton, J. W. 1984. Perceptual Acquaintance from Descartes to Reid, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Noa Naaman-Zauderer, Tel-Aviv University
  • Book: Descartes' Deontological Turn
  • Online publication: 10 January 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511778995.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Noa Naaman-Zauderer, Tel-Aviv University
  • Book: Descartes' Deontological Turn
  • Online publication: 10 January 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511778995.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Noa Naaman-Zauderer, Tel-Aviv University
  • Book: Descartes' Deontological Turn
  • Online publication: 10 January 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511778995.009
Available formats
×