Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-g78kv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-26T03:17:42.023Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - For Whose Good Does Natural Selection Work?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 December 2009

Timothy Shanahan
Affiliation:
Loyola Marymount University, California
Get access

Summary

Birds' wings are obviously “for” flying, spider webs are for catching insects, chlorophyll molecules are for photosynthesis, DNA molecules are for. … What areDNA molecules for. … [This] is the forbidden question. DNA is not “for” anything … all adaptations are for the preservation of DNA; DNA just is.

(Dawkins 1982a, p. 45)

Introduction

Natural selection operates by favoring those individuals whose characteristics confer any slight advantage in what Darwin termed “the struggle for existence.” As selection operates generation after generation, distinguishing the fit from the less fit, adaptations evolve and are passed on to offspring, which in turn engage in the struggle anew, resulting in “the improvement of each organic being in relation to its organic and inorganic conditions of life” (Darwin 1859, p. 84). Hence the astounding array of complex adaptations characterizing living things. On this all evolutionists agree.

Darwin maintained again and again that “natural selection works solely by and for the good of each being” (Darwin 1859, p. 489; 1959, p. 758). But there are many “beings” involved in the evolutionary process. By whose and for whose “good” does natural selection work? As we have seen, although Darwin generally thought of selection as operating on and for the good of organisms (i.e., as improving the adaptations characterizing the individual organisms constituting an evolving lineage), when the situation warranted it he was also willing to countenance selection operating and forging adaptations at the level of communities or groups.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Evolution of Darwinism
Selection, Adaptation and Progress in Evolutionary Biology
, pp. 63 - 90
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×