Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-09T15:02:19.395Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Universe from bit

from Part II - Physics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 December 2010

Paul Davies
Affiliation:
Arizona State University
Niels Henrik Gregersen
Affiliation:
University of Copenhagen
Get access

Summary

“I refute it thus!” Samuel Johnson famously dismissed Bishop George Berkeley's argument for the unreality of matter by kicking a large stone (Boswell, 1823). In the light of modern physics, however, Johnson's simple reasoning evaporates. Apparently solid matter is revealed, on closer inspection, to be almost all empty space, and the particles of which matter is composed are themselves ghostly patterns of quantum energy, mere excitations of invisible quantum fields, or possibly vibrating loops of string living in a ten-dimensional space–time (Greene, 1999). The history of physics is one of successive abstractions from daily experience and common sense, into a counterintuitive realm of mathematical forms and relationships, with a link to the stark sense data of human observation that is long and often tortuous. Yet at the end of the day, science is empirical, and our finest theories must be grounded, somehow, “in reality.” But where is reality? Is it in acts of observation of the world made by human and possibly non-human observers? In records stored in computer or laboratory notebooks? In some objective world “out there”? Or in a more abstract location?

THE GROUND OF REALITY

When a physicist performs an experiment, he or she interrogates nature and receives a response that, ultimately, is in the form of discrete bits of information (think of “yes” or “no” binary answers to specific questions), the discreteness implied by the underlying quantum nature of the universe (Zeilinger, 2004).

Type
Chapter
Information
Information and the Nature of Reality
From Physics to Metaphysics
, pp. 65 - 91
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aaronson, S. (2005). Are quantum states exponentially long vectors? Proceedings of the Oberwolfach Meeting on Complexity Theory, arXiv: quant-ph/0507242v1, accessed 8 March 2010 (http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0507242).
Barrow, J. D. (2002). The Constants of Nature. New York and London: Random House.Google Scholar
Bekenstein, J. D. (1973). Black holes and entropy. Physical Review D, 8: 2333–2346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bekenstein, J. D. (1981). Universal upper bound on the entropy-to-energy ratio for bounded systems. Physical Review D, 23: 287–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benioff, P. (2002). Towards a coherent theory of physics and mathematics. Foundations of Physics, 32: 989–1029.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boswell, J. (1823). The Life of Samuel Johnson, vol. 1. London: J. Richardson & Co.Google Scholar
Carroll, S. (2007). Edge: The Third Culture. Accessed 8 March 2010 (www.edge.org/discourse/science_faith.html).
Cramer, M., and Eisert, J. (2006). Correlations, spectral gap and entanglement in harmonic quantum systems on generic lattices. New Journal of Physics, 8: 71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, P. C. W., and Davis, T. M. (2003). How far can the generalized second law be generalized?Foundations of Physics, 32: 1877–1889.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, P. (2006). The Goldilocks Enigma: Why Is the Universe Just Right for Life?London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1630). Letter to Mersenne, 15 April 1630. In Descartes' Philosophical Letters, trans. and ed. Kenny, A. (1970). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Spinoza, B. (1670). Theological–Political Treatise, 2nd ed, trans. Shirley, S.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 75.Google Scholar
Dirac, P. A. M. (1937). The cosmological constants. Nature, 139: 323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drake, S. (1957). Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo. New York: Doubleday-Anchor.Google Scholar
Eddington, A. S. (1931). Preliminary note on the masses of the electron, the proton, and the universe. Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 27: 15–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Everett, H. (1957). Relative state formulation of quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 29: 454–462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbons, G. W., and Hawking, S. W. (1977). Cosmological event horizons, thermodynamics, and particle creation. Physical Review D, 15: 2738–2751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, B. (1999). The Elegant Universe. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Hawking, S. W. (1975). Particle creation by black holes. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 43: 199–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawking, S. (1988). A Brief History of Time. New York: Bantam.Google Scholar
Landauer, R. (1967). Wanted: A physically possible theory of physics. IEEE Spectrum, 4: 105–109, accessed 8 March 2010 (http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/xpl/freeabs_all.jsp?arnumber=5215588).
Landauer, R. (1986). Computation and physics: Wheeler's meaning circuit?Foundations of Physics, 16(6): 551–564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laplace, P. (1825). Philosophical Essays on Probabilities. Trans. Emory, F. L. and Truscott, F. W. (1985). New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Lloyd, S. (2002). Computational capacity of the universe. Physical Review Letters, 88: 237901.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lloyd, S. (2006). The Computational Universe. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Milburn, G. (1991). Intrinsic decoherence in quantum mechanics. Physical Review A, 44: 5401–5406.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Milburn, G. (2006). Quantum computation by communication. New Journal of Physics, 8: 30.Google Scholar
Rees, M. (2001). Our Cosmic Habitat. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Russell, B. (1957). Why I Am Not A Christian. New York: Touchstone.Google Scholar
Shannon, C. E. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27: 379–423, 623–656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smolin, L. (2008). On the reality of time and the evolution of laws. Online video lecture and PDF, accessed 8 March 2010 (http://pirsa.org/08100049/).
Susskind, L. (1995). The world as a hologram. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 36: 6377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Susskind, L. (2005). The Cosmic Landscape: String Theory and the Illusion of Intelligent Design. New York: Little, Brown.Google Scholar
Szilard, L. (1929). Uber die Entropieverminderung in einem thermodynamischen System bei eingriffen intelligenter Wesen. Zeitschrift für Physik, 53: 840–856.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szilard, L. (1964). On the decrease of entropy in a thermodynamic system by the intervention of intelligent beings. Behavioral Science, 9(4): 301–310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tegmark, M. (2003). Parallel universes. Scientific American, May 31, 2003.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
't Hooft, G. (1993). Dimensional reduction in quantum gravity. arXiv: gr-qc/ 9310026v1, accessed 8 March 2010 (http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9310026v1).
Ward, K. (1982). Rational Theology and the Creativity of God. New York: Pilgrim Press.Google Scholar
Wheeler, J. A. (1979). Frontiers of time. In Problems in the Foundations of Physics, ed. G. Toraldo di Francia. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 395–497.Google Scholar
Wheeler, J. A. (1983). On recognizing ‘law without law’. American Journal of Physics, 51: 398–404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wheeler, J. A. (1989). Information, physics, quantum: The search for links. Proceedings of the Third International Symposium on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Tokyo), 354.Google Scholar
Wheeler, J. A. (1994). At Home in the Universe. New York: AIP Press.Google Scholar
Wheeler, J. A., and Ford, K. (1998). It from bit. In Geons, Black Holes & Quantum Foam: A Life in Physics. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Wigner, E. P. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1): 1–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1921). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. Pears, D. and McGuinness, B. (1961). London: Routledge.
Zeilinger, A. (2004). Why the quantum? It from bit? A participatory universe? Three far-reaching, visionary questions from John Archibald Wheeler and how they inspired a quantum experimentalist. In Science and Ultimate Reality: Quantum Theory, Cosmology, and Complexity, eds Barrow, J. D., Davies, P. C. W., and Harper, C. L.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 201–220.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×