Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-s9k8s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-03T11:08:28.143Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 July 2010

David McCabe
Affiliation:
Colgate University, New York
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Modus Vivendi Liberalism
Theory and Practice
, pp. 244 - 253
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackerman, Bruce, Social Justice in the Liberal State, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980.Google Scholar
Ahmed, Leila, Women and Gender in Islam: Historical Roots of a Modern Debate, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1992.Google Scholar
Al-Hibri, Azizah, “Is Western Patriarchal Feminism Good for Third World/Minority Women?,” in Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, ed. Cohen, Joshua, Howard, Matthew, and Nussbaum, Martha, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, 41–6.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard, “Human Flourishing versus Desire Satisfaction,” Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (Winter 1999), 113–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard, and Shapiro, Ian, “Democratic Autonomy and Religious Freedom,” in Political Order: NOMOS 38, ed. Shapiro, Ian and Hardin, Russell, New York: New York University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert, Religious Commitment and Secular Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert, and Wolterstorff, Nicholas, Religion in the Public Square: The Place of Religious Convictions in Political Debate, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997.Google Scholar
Baber, Harriet, “Adaptive Preference,” paper presented March 28, 2004, at the APA Mini-conference on Global Justice, Pasadena, CA.
Barry, , Brian, , Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Barry, , Brian, , Justice as Impartiality, New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.Google Scholar
Barry, , Brian, , The Liberal Theory of Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973.Google Scholar
Benditt, Theodore, “Compromising Interests and Principles,” in Compromise in Ethics, Law and Politics: NOMOS 29, ed. Pennock, J.R. and Chapman, J.W., New York: New York University Press, 1979, 26–37.Google Scholar
Benedict, Ruth, “Anthropology and the Abnormal,” Journal of General Psychology 10 (1934), 59–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla, The Claims of Culture, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003.Google Scholar
Benjamin, Martin, Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics, Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press, 1990.Google Scholar
Benn, Stanley, “Freedom, Autonomy, and the Concept of a Person,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 66 (1975–6), 109–30.Google Scholar
Benn, Stanley, A Theory of Freedom, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkowitz, Peter, Virtue and the Making of Modern Liberalism, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah, “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in Four Essays on Liberty, New York: Oxford University Press, 1969, 118–72.Google Scholar
Billig, Michael, Arguing and Thinking: A Rhetorical Approach to Social Psychology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Bird, Colin, “Mutual Respect and Neutral Justification,” Ethics 107 (October 1996), 62–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brighouse, Harry, “Channel One, the Anti-Commercial Principle, and the Discontinuous Ethos,” in Philosophy of Education: An Anthology, ed. Curren, Randall, Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2007, 208–20.Google Scholar
Brighouse, Harry, “Civic Education and Liberal Legitimacy,” Ethics 108 (1998), 719–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brighouse, Harry, School Choice and Social Justice, New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Brower, Bruce, “The Limits of Public Reason,” Journal of Philosophy 91 (January 1994), 5–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burkett, Elinor, “God Created Me to Be a Slave,” New York Times Magazine, October 12, 1997, 56–60.Google Scholar
Burtt, Shelley, “Comprehensive Educations and the Liberal Understanding of Autonomy,” in Citizenship and Education in Liberal-Democratic Societies, ed. Feinberg, Walter and McDonough, Kevin, New York: Oxford University Press, 2003, 179–207.Google Scholar
Caldwell, John C., “Routes to Low Mortality in poor Countries,” Population and Development Review 12 (1986), 171–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callan, Eamonn, “Autonomy, Child-Rearing, and Good Lives,” in The Moral and Political Status of Children, ed. Archard, David and Macleod, Colin, New York: Oxford University Press, 2002, 118–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callan, Eamonn, Creating Citizens, New York: Clarendon Press, 1997.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callan, Eamonn, “Liberal Legitimacy, Justice, and Civic Education,” Ethics 111 (October 2000), 141–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callan, Eamonn, “Political Liberalism and Political Education,” Review of Politics 58 (Winter 1996), 5–33.Google Scholar
Caney, Simon, “Liberal Legitimacy, Reasonable Disagreement and Justice,” in Pluralism and Liberal Neutrality, ed. Bellamy, Richard and Hollis, Martin, Ilford: Frank Cass, 1999, 19–36.Google Scholar
Card, Claudia, “Rape as a Terrorist Institution,” in Violence, Terrorism and Justice, ed. Frey, R.G. and Morris, Christopher, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991, 296–319.Google Scholar
Carens, Joseph, and Williams, Melissa, “Muslim Minorities in Liberal Democracies: The Politics of Misrecognition,” in Secularism and its Critics, ed. Bhargava, Rajeev, Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998, 137–73.Google Scholar
Carrera, Michael, et al., “Knowledge about Reproduction, Contraception, and Sexually Transmitted Infections among Young Adolescents in American cities,” Social Policy 30, no. 3 (Spring 2000), 41–50.Google Scholar
Anne, Case, “Health, Income and Economic Development,” in Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics 2001/2002, ed. Pleskovic, B. and Stern, N., Washington DC: World Bank, 2002, 221–41.Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas, “The Incoherence of Hobbesian Justifications of the State,” American Philosophical Quarterly 31 (January 1994), 23–38.Google Scholar
Cladis, Mark, A Communication Defense of Liberalism: Emile Durkheim and Contemporary Social Theory, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1992.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua, “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” in The Idea of Democracy, ed. Copp, Davidet al., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993, 270–91.Google Scholar
Cookson, Catharine, Regulating Religion: The Courts and the Free Exercise Clause, New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowder, George, Liberalism and Value Pluralism, New York: Continuum, 2002.Google Scholar
Crowder, George, “Pluralism and Liberalism,” Political Studies 42 (1994), 293–305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dagger, Richard, Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism, New York: Oxford University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
D'Agostino, Fred, Free Public Reason: Making it Up As We Go, New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Diamond, Jared, “Vengeance is Ours,” New Yorker, April 21, 2008, 74ff.Google Scholar
Donner, Wendy, The Liberal Self: John Stuart Mill's Moral and Political Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991.Google Scholar
Double, Richard, “Two Types of Autonomy Accounts,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22, no. 1 (March 1992), 65–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Gerald, “Autonomy and Behavior Control,” Hastings Center Report 6 (February 1976), 23–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dworkin, Gerald, “Non-Neutral Principles,” in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989, 124–40.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Gerald, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, “Justice and Rights,” in Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977, 150–83.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Elster, Jon, Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, vol. iii: Harm to Self, New York: Oxford University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Finnis, John, Natural Law and Natural Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.Google Scholar
Fishkin, James, “Liberty vs. Equal Opportunity,” Social Philosophy and Policy 5 (1978), 32–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, Philippa, “Utilitarianism and the Virtues,” in Consequentialism and its Critics, ed. Scheffler, Samuel, New York: Oxford University Press, 1988, 224–42.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Equality as a Moral Ideal,” Ethics 98 (October 1987), 21–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,” in Free Will, ed. Watson, Gary, New York: Oxford University Press, 1982, 81–95.Google Scholar
Fried, Charles, Right and Wrong, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galston, William, “Civil Education in the Liberal State,” in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Rosenblum, Nancy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Galston, William, Liberal Pluralism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galston, William, Liberal Purposes, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galston, William, The Practice of Liberal Pluralism, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Galston, William, “Two Concepts of Liberalism,” Ethics 105 (April 1995), 516–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaut, Berys, “Moral Pluralism,” Philosophical Papers 22, no. 1 (1993), 17–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaut, Berys, “Rawls and the Claims of Liberal Legitimacy,” Philosophical Papers 24 (1995), 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, Robert P, Making Men Moral, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993.Google Scholar
George, Robert P, “Natural Law and International Order,” in International Society, ed. Mapel, David and Nardin, Terry, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998, 54–69.Google Scholar
Gilles, Stephen, review of Stephen Macedo, Diversity and Distrust, Education Next 1, no. 1 (Spring 2001), www.hoover.org/publications/ednext.
Gilman, Sander, “‘Barbaric’ Rituals?,” in Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, ed. Joshua Cohen, Matthew Howard, and Nussbaum, Martha, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, 53–8.Google Scholar
Goldsmith, M.M., “Hobbes' ‘Mortall God’: Is There a Fallacy in Hobbes' Theory of Sovereignty?,” History of Political Thought 1 (1980), 33–50.Google Scholar
Gray, John, Enlightenment's Wake: Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age, New York: Routledge, 1995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, John, Isaiah Berlin, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Gray, John, Two Faces of Liberalism, New York: New Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Gray, John, “Two Liberalisms of Fear,” Hedgehog Review 2 (Spring 2000), 9–23.Google Scholar
Green, Leslie, “Internal Minorities and Their Rights,” in The Rights of Minority Cultures, ed. Kymlicka, Will, New York: Oxford University Press, 1995, 256–72.Google Scholar
Greenawalt, Kent, Private Consciences and Public Reasons, New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenberg, Blu, On Women and Judaism: A View from Tradition, Philadelphia, PA: Jewish Publication Society of America, 1981.Google Scholar
Greene, Jay P., “The Surprising Consensus on School Choice,” The Public Interest 144 (Summer 2001), www.thepublicinterest.com.Google Scholar
Griffin, James, “Are There Incommensurable Values?,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 7 (1977), 39–59.Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, “Children, Paternalism, and Education: A Liberal Argument,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (1980), 338–58.Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, “Civic Education and Social Diversity,” Ethics 105 (April 1995), 557–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, Democratic Education, rev. edn., Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, “How Limited is Liberal Government?,” in Liberalism Without Illusions: Essays on Liberal Theory and the Political Vision of Judith Shklar, ed. Yack, Bernard, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1996, 64–81.Google Scholar
Haffner, Debra, “Foreword: Sexuality Education in Policy and Practice,” in Sexuality and the Curriculum, ed. Sears, James T., New York: Teachers College Press, 1992, vii–viii.Google Scholar
Hampshire, Stuart, Innocence and Experience, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Hampshire, Stuart, Justice is Conflict, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Haworth, Lawrence, Autonomy: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology and Ethics, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haworth, Lawrence, “Autonomy and Utility,” in The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, ed. Christman, John, New York: Oxford University Press, 1989, 155–69.Google Scholar
Higgins, Tracy, “Why Feminists Can't (or Shouldn't) Be Liberals,” Fordham Law Review 72 (April 2004), 1629–41.Google Scholar
Hill, Thomas, “The Problem of Stability in Political Liberalism,” in Respect, Pluralism, and Justice: Kantian Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000, 237–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honig, Bonnie, “‘My Culture Made Me Do It’,” in Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, ed. Cohen, Joshua, Howard, Matthew, and Nussbaum, Martha, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, 35–40.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas, Perfectionism, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas, “Why Value Autonomy?,” Social Theory and Practice 13, no. 3 (Fall 1987), 361–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ignatieff, Michael, Isaiah Berlin: A Life, London: Chatto & Windus, 1998.Google Scholar
Jones, R., “Sex Education in Personal and Social Education,” in Personal and Social Education: Philosophical Perspectives, ed. White, P., London: Kogan Page, 1989, 54–7.Google Scholar
Kekes, John, “Cruelty and Liberalism,” Ethics 106 (July 1996), 834–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekes, John, The Morality of Pluralism, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Kraybill, Donald, The Riddle of Amish Culture, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Kuflik, Arthur, “Morality and Compromise,” in Compromise in Ethics, Law and Politics: NOMOS 29, ed. Pennock, J.R. and Chapman, J.W., New York: New York University Press, 1979, 38–65.Google Scholar
Kukathas, Chandran, “Are There Any Cultural Rights?,” Political Theory 20, no. 1 (February 1992), 105–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kukathas, Chandran, “Is Feminism Bad for Multiculturalism?,” Public Affairs Quarterly 15 (April 2001), 83–98.Google Scholar
Kukathas, Chandran, The Liberal Archipelago, New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kymlicka, Will, “Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality,” Ethics 99 (July 1989), 883–905.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kymlicka, Will, Liberalism, Community and Culture, New York: Oxford University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will, Multicultural Citizenship, New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will, “The Rights of Minority Cultures: Reply to Kukathas,” Political Theory 20, no. 1 (February 1992), 140–6.
Larmore, Charles, The Morals of Modernity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, Charles, Patterns of Moral Complexity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, Meira, The Demands of Liberal Education, New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Levinson, Sanford, “The Confrontation of Religious Faith and Civil Religion: Catholics Becoming Justices,” DePaul Law Review 39 (1990), 1047–82.Google Scholar
Lleras-Muney, Adriana, “The Relationship between Education and Adult Mortality in the US,” Review of Economic Studies 72, no. 1 (January 2005), 189–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lomasky, Loren, “But is it Liberalism?,” Critical Review 4 (Winter 1990), 86–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lukes, Steven, Liberals and Cannibals: The Implications of Diversity, New York: Verso, 2003.Google Scholar
McCabe, David, “Knowing About the Good: A Problem with Anti-Perfectionism,” Ethics 110 (January 2000), 311–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stephen, Macedo, Diversity and Distrust: Civic Education in a Multicultural Society, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Stephen, Macedo, “Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls,” Ethics 105 (April 1995), 468–96.Google Scholar
Macedo, StephenLiberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism, New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.Google Scholar
Macedo, StephenThe Politics of Justification,” Political Theory 18 (May 1990), 280–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macedo, Stephen, and Wenar, Leif, “The Diversity of Rights in Contemporary Ethical and Political Thought,” in The Nature of Rights at the American Founding and Beyond, ed. Shain, Barry, Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press, 2007, 280–302.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue, 2nd edn., Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984.Google Scholar
McLaren, Peter, “Foreword: Border Anxiety and Sexuality Politics,” in Sexuality and the Curriculum, ed. Sears, James T., New York: Teachers College Press, 1992, ix–xiv.Google Scholar
Maddock, Kenneth, The Australian Aborigines: A Portrait of Their Society, Ringwood: Penguin, 1972.Google Scholar
Madison, James, The Federalist no. 10, in The Federalist Papers, ed. Rossiter, Clinton, New York: Penguin, 1961.Google Scholar
Mason, Andrew, Community, Solidarity, and Belonging, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, Simon Cabulea, “Principled Compromise and the Abortion Controversy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (Fall 2005), 317–48.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty (1859), various editions.
Mill, John Stuart, Utilitarianism (1863), various editions.
Mills, Claudia, “‘Not a Mere Modus Vivendi’: The Bases for Allegiance to the Just State,” in The Idea of a Political Liberalism, ed. Davion, Victoria and Wolf, Clark, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000, 190–203.Google Scholar
Mirhosseini, Akram, “After the Revolution: Violations of Women's Human Rights in Iran,” in Women's Rights, Human Rights, ed. Peters, Julie and Wolper, Andrea (New York: Routledge, 1995), 72–7.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Basil, “Introduction,” in The Philosophy of Religion, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971.Google Scholar
Moon, J. Donald, Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Moore, Margaret, “On Reasonableness,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 13 (1996), 167–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy,” in Authority, ed. Raz, Joseph, New York: New York University Press, 1990, 300–24.Google Scholar
Narayan, Uma, Dislocating Cultures: Identities, Traditions, and Third-World Feminism, New York: Routledge, 1997.Google Scholar
Neal, Patrick, Liberalism and its Discontents, New York: New York University Press, 1997.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neal, Patrick, “Perfectionism with a Liberal Face? Nervous Liberals and Raz's Political Theory,” Social Theory and Practice 20, no. 1 (Spring 1994), 25–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander, Nietzsche: Life as Literature, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Gay Science, trans. Kaufmann, Walter, New York: Vintage, 1974.Google Scholar
Noggle, Robert, “The Public Conception of Autonomy and Critical Self-Reflection,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 35 (1997), 495–515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha, “A Plea for Difficulty,” in Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, ed. Cohen, Joshua, Howard, Matthew, and Nussbaum, Martha, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, 105–14.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha, Sex and Social Justice, New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha, Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakeshott, Michael, Morality and Politics in Modern Europe, ed. Letwin, Shirley, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakeshott, Michael, On Human Conduct, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller, “Feminism and Multiculturalism: Some Tensions,” Ethics 108, no. 4 (July 1998), 661–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller, “Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?,” in Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, ed. Cohen, Joshua, Howard, Matthew, and Nussbaum, Martha, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, 9–24.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller, “Justice and Gender: An Unfinished Debate,” Fordham Law Review 72 (April 2004), 1537–67.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller, Justice, Gender, and the Family, New York: Basic Books, 1989.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller, “Mistresses of Their Own Destiny: Group Rights, Gender, and Realistic Rights of Exit,” Ethics 112 (January 2002), 205–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laurie, Olsen, Made in America: Immigrant Students in Our Public Schools, New York: New Press, 1997.Google Scholar
Owen, J. Judd, Religion and the Demise of Liberal Rationalism, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Parekh, Bikhu, Rethinking Multiculturalism: Cultural Diversity and Political Theory, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Parekh, Bikhu, “A Varied Moral World,” in Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, ed. Cohen, Joshua, Howard, Matthew, and Nussbaum, Martha, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, 69–75.Google Scholar
Paris, David, “The ‘Theoretica l Mystique’: Neutrality, Plurality, and the Defense of Pluralism,” American Journal of Political Science 31 (November 1987), 909–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patten, Alan, “Democratic Secession from a Multinational State,” Ethics 112 (April 2002), 558–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Post, Robert, “Between Norms and Choices,” in Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, ed. Cohen, Joshua, Howard, Matthew, and Nussbaum, Martha, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999, 65–8.Google Scholar
Quinn, Warren, “Putting Rationality in its Place,” in Virtues and Reasons: Philippa Foot and Moral Theory, ed. Hursthouse, Rosalindet al., Oxford: Clarendon, 1995, 181–208.Google Scholar
Rachels, James, and Ruddick, William, “Lives and Liberty,” in The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, ed. Christman, John, New York: Oxford University Press, 1989, 221–33.Google Scholar
Rawls, John, “Fairness to Goodness,” Philosophical Review 84, no. 4 (October 1975), 536–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7 (1987), 1–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John, The Law of Peoples: with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,”Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Rawls, John, Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971; rev. edn. 1999.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, Ethics in the Public Domain, New York: Oxford University Press, 1994.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, “Facing Up: A Reply,” Southern California Law Review 62 (1989), 1153–235.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986.Google Scholar
Regan, Donald, “Authority and Value: Reflections on Raz's Morality of Freedom,” Southern California Law Review 62 (1989), 995–1095.Google Scholar
Regan, Donald, “The Value of Rational Nature,” Ethics 112 (January 2002), 267–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reich, Rob, “Testing the Boundaries of Parental Authority over Education,” in Moral and Political Education: NOMOS 43, ed. Macedo, Stephen and Tamir, Yael, New York: New York University Press, 2002, 275–313.Google Scholar
Reiss, Michael J., “Conflicting Philosophies of School Sex Education,” in Philosophy of Education: An Anthology, ed. Curren, Randall, Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2007, 553–60.Google Scholar
Rose, Carole, “Women and Property: Gaining and Losing Ground,” Virginia Law Review 78 (1992), 521–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Safi, Omid, ed., Progressive Muslims: On Justice, Gender, and Pluralism, Oxford: Oneworld, 2003.
Sangari, Kumkum, and Sudesh, Vaid, eds., Recasting Women: Essays in Indian Colonial History, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1990.
Sartre, Jean-Paul, Existentialism and Human Emotions, trans. Frechtman, Bernard, New York: Philosophical Library, 1957.Google Scholar
Schoeman, Ferdinand, “Rights of Children, Rights of Parents, and the Moral Basis of the Family,” Ethics 91 (October 1980), 6–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya, “More than One Hundred Million Women are Missing,” New York Review of Books 37, no. 20 (1990), 61–6.Google Scholar
Shachar, Ayelet, Multicultural Jurisdictions: Cultural Differences and Women's Rights, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sher, George, Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sher, George, and Bennett, William, “Moral Education and Indoctrination,” Journal of Philosophy 79 (November 1982), 665–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shklar, Judith, Legalism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964.Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith, “The Liberalism of Fear,” in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Rosenblum, Nancy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989, 21–38.Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith, Ordinary Vices, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Shweder, Richard A., “‘What About Female Genital Mutilation?’ and ‘Why Cultural Understanding Matters’,” in Why do Men Barbecue? Recipes for Cultural Psychology, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003, 168–216.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John, Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Smart, J.J.C., “An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics,” in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against, York, New: Cambridge University Press, 1963, 3–74.Google Scholar
Spinner-Halev, Jeffrey, The Boundaries of Citizenship, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994.Google Scholar
Spinner-Halev, Jeffrey, “Feminism, Multiculturalism, Oppression, and the State,” Ethics 112 (October 2001), 84–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spinner-Halev, Jeffrey, Surviving Diversity: Religion and Democratic Citizenship, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael, Plural and Conflicting Values, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990.Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael, “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories,” Journal of Philosophy 73 (August 1976), 453–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, Cass, Free Markets and Social Justice, New York: Oxford University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
Talisse, Robert, “Liberalism, Pluralism, and Political Justification,” Harvard Review of Philosophy 13 (2005), 57–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tamir, Yael, “The Land of the Fearful and the Free,” Constellations 3 (1997), 296–314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Charles, “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Rosenblum, Nancy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989, 159–82.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles, “What is Human Agency?,” in Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers, vol. i, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985, 15–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teson, Fernando, “Kantian International Liberalism,” in International Society: Diverse Ethical Perspectives, ed. Mapel, D. and Nardin, T., Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998, 103–13.Google Scholar
Tuck, Richard, “Rights and Pluralism,” in Philosophy in an Age of Pluralism: The Philosophy of Charles Taylor in Question, ed. Tully, James, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994, 159–70.Google Scholar
Wadud, Amina, Inside the Gender Jihad: Women's Reform in Islam, Oxford: Oneworld, 2006.Google Scholar
Wadud, Amina, Qu'ran and Woman: Reading the Sacred Text from a Woman's Perspective, 2nd edn., New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, “Autonomy and Perfectionism in Raz's Morality of Freedom,” Southern California Law Review 62 (1989), 1097–152.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, “A Right to do Wrong?,” Ethics 92 (October 1981), 21–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, “Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism,” Philosophical Quarterly 37 (April 1987), 127–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, “Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution,” in John Locke: A Letter Concerning Toleration in Focus, ed. Horton, John and Mendus, Susan, London: Routledge, 1991, 98–124.Google Scholar
Wall, Stephen, Liberalism, Perfectionism, and Restraint, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael, “On Involuntary Association,” in Freedom of Association, ed. Gutmann, Amy, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998, 64–74.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad, Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1994.Google Scholar
Weinstock, Daniel, “Beyond Exit Rights: Reframing the Debate,” in Minorities within Minorities: Equality, Rights and Diversity, ed. Eisenberg, Avigail and Spinner-Halev, Jeffrey, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005, 227–46.Google Scholar
Weinstock, Daniel, “The Graying of Berlin,” Critical Review 11, no. 4 (Fall 1997), 481–501.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Introduction” to Isaiah Berlin, Concepts and Categories, New York: Viking, 1979, xi–xviii.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan, “Sanity and the Metaphysics of Responsibility,” in Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions, ed. Schoeman, F., New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988, 46–62.Google Scholar
Wolfe, Alan, “Two Levels of Pluralism,” Ethics 102 (July 1992), 785–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfe, Alan, One Nation, After All, New York: Viking, 1998.Google Scholar
Young, Robert, Personal Autonomy, London: Croom Helm, 1986.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • David McCabe, Colgate University, New York
  • Book: Modus Vivendi Liberalism
  • Online publication: 06 July 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511750359.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • David McCabe, Colgate University, New York
  • Book: Modus Vivendi Liberalism
  • Online publication: 06 July 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511750359.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • David McCabe, Colgate University, New York
  • Book: Modus Vivendi Liberalism
  • Online publication: 06 July 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511750359.011
Available formats
×