Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gvh9x Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-21T09:22:05.506Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 October 2018

Joshua I. Weinstein
Affiliation:
The Herzl Institute, Jerusalem
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Adam, J. 1902. The Republic of Plato. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Allen, T. 1917–1920. Homeri Opera. 4 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, A. 1967. Plotinus. Vol. 3: Ennead 3. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle. 2 vols. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bloom, A. 1968. The Republic of Plato. New York, NY: Basic.Google Scholar
Burnet, J. 1900–1907. Platonis Opera. 5 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J., ed. 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. 1941. The Republic of Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dyson, R. 1994. Augustine. City of God against the Pagans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Edelstein, L. and Kidd, I.. 1989. Posidonius. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. and Griffith, T.. 2000. Plato. The Republic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grube, G. 1974. Plato's Republic. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Hicks, R. 1931. Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers. 2 vols. New York, NY: Putnam.Google Scholar
Jones, H. and Powell, J.. 1942. Thucydidis Historiae. 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jones, W. 1948. Hippocrates: On Airs, Waters and Places. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
King, J. 1966. Cicero: Tusculan Disputations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lattimore, R. 1951. The Iliad of Homer. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lattimore, R. 1965. The Odyssey of Homer. New York, NY: Harper.Google Scholar
Slings, S. 2003. Plato's Republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Adkins, A. 1960. Merit and Responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Allen, D. 2000. “Envisaging the Body of the Condemned: The Power of Platonic Symbols.” Classical Philology 95.2: 133–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1981. An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1999. Platonic Ethics, Old and New. Ithaca, NY: Cornell.Google Scholar
Appiah, K. 2010. The Honor Code: How Moral Revolutions Happen. New York, NY: Norton.Google Scholar
Austin, J. 1957. “A Plea for Excuses.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57: 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, J. 2012. “Justice Writ Large.” In R. Kamtekar, ed. Virtue and Happiness: Essays in Honour of Julia Annas, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Supplementary Volume: 3149.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 2001. “Platonism, Moral Nostalgia and the ‘City of Pigs.’” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 17: 207–27.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 2016. “What Kind of Theory is the Theory of the Tripartite Soul?Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 31: 5383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barney, R., Brennan, T. and Brittain, C., eds. 2012. Plato and the Divided Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Blössner, N. 2007. “The City-Soul Analogy.” In Ferrari, G., ed., 345–85.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2001. “Akrasia and Agency in Plato's Laws and Republic.” In Wagner, E., ed., 203–37.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2002. Plato's Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2007. “Plato on Akrasia and Knowing Your Own Mind.” In Bobonich, C. and Destrée, P., eds., 4160.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. and Destrée, P., eds. 2007. Akrasia in Greek Philosophy: From Socrates to Plotinus. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. 1987. Intention, Plans and Practical Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, E. 2004. “Minding the Gap in Plato's Republic.” Philosophical Studies 117.1: 275302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, E. 2012. “The Unity of the Soul in Plato's Republic.” In Barney, R. et al. eds., 5373.Google Scholar
Brennan, T. 2012. “The Nature of the Spirited Part of the Soul and Its Object.” In Barney, R. et al. eds., 102–27.Google Scholar
Burnet, J. 1930. Early Greek Philosophy. 4th ed. London: Black.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 1976. “Plato on the Grammar of Perceiving.” Classical Quarterly, n.s. 26.1: 2951.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 1999. “Culture and Society in Plato's Republic.” Tanner Lectures on Human Values 20: 215324.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 2000. “Plato on Why Mathematics is Good for the Soul.” In Smiley, T., ed., Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 2006. “The Truth of Tripartition.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cairns, D. 1993. Aidōs: The Psychology and Ethics of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greek Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cairns, D. 2014. “Ψυχή, Θυμός, and Metaphor in Homer and Plato.” Études Platoniciennes 11. on-line 15 April 2015, last accessed 6 June 2018. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/etudesplatoniciennes/566; DOI: 10.4000/etudesplatoniciennes.566Google Scholar
Carone, G. 2001. “Akrasia in the Republic: Does Plato Change his Mind?” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20: 107–48.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. 1988. Matter and Consciousness: A Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind, rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. 1984. “Plato's Theory of Human Motivation.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1: 321.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. 1912. “Psychology and Social Structure in the Republic of Plato.” Classical Quarterly 6: 246–65.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. 1930. “The Division of the Soul.” Hibbert Journal 28: 206–19.Google Scholar
Coumoundouros, A. and Polansky, R.. 2011. “Function, Ability and Desire in Plato's Republic.” In Anagnostopoulos, G., ed., Socratic, Platonic and Aristotelian Studies: Essays in Honor of Gerasimos Santas. Philosophical Studies Series 117. Berlin and New York: Springer, 205–18.Google Scholar
Craig, L. 1994. The War Lover: A Study of Plato's Republic. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Crombie, I. 1962. An Examination of Plato's Doctrines. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Cross, R. and Woozley, A.. 1964. Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 1963. “Actions, Reasons and Causes.” Journal of Philosophy 60.23: 685700.Google Scholar
De Courcy, K. 1976. Intelligence Digest. London: Intelligence Digest.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1971. “Intentional Systems.” Journal of Philosophy 68.4: 87106.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. 1979. “Socrates’ First City in the Republic.” Apeiron 13.1: 3640.Google Scholar
Dodds, E. 1951. The Greeks and the Irrational. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Donovan, B. 2003. “The Do-It-Yourselfer in Plato's Republic.” American Journal of Philology 124.1: 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorter, K. 2006. The Transformation of Plato's Republic. Lanham, MD: Lexington.Google Scholar
Duncombe, M. 2015. “The Role of Relatives in Plato's Partition Argument, Republic 4, 436b9–439c9.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 48:3760.Google Scholar
Edwards, J. 1834. “Thoughts on the Revival of Religion in New England.” In Hickman, E., ed., The Works of Jonathan Edwards, vol. 1. Edinburgh and Carlisle, PA: Banner of Truth.Google Scholar
Erginel, M. 2011. “Plato on the Psychology of Pleasure and Pain.” Phoenix 65.3/4: 288314.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. 2003. City and Soul in Plato's Republic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. ed. 2007a. The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. 2007b. “The Three-Part Soul.” In Ferrari, G., ed., 165201.Google Scholar
Fisher, N. 1992. Hybris. Warminster: Aris and Philips.Google Scholar
Fine, G. 2003. Plato on Knowledge and Forms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzpatrick, K. 2014. “Forbidden Delicacies: The Ideal City, the Luxurious City, and the Marketplace in Plato's Republic.” In Trepanier, L., ed., The Free Market and the Human Condition: Essays on Economics and Culture. Lanham, MD: Lexington, 1125.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1983. The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. 1970. “On the Antecedents of Aristotle's Bipartite Psychology.” Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 11: 233–50.Google Scholar
Freud, S. [1900]1953. The Interpretation of Dreams. London: Hogarth.Google Scholar
Frost, K. 2014. “On the Very Idea of Direction of Fit.” Philosophical Review 123.4: 429–84.Google Scholar
Fuqua, C. 1991. “Proper Behavior in the Odyssey.” Illinois Classical Studies 16.1/2: 4958.Google Scholar
Ganson, T. 2009. “The Rational/Non-rational Distinction in Plato's Republic.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 36: 179–97.Google Scholar
Garnsey, P. 1988. Famine and Food Supply in the Graeco-Roman World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garnsey, P. 1998. Cities, Peasants and Food in Classical Antiquity. Scheidel, Walter, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerson, L. 2003. Knowing Persons: A Study in Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2014. “Plato's Rational Souls.” Review of Metaphysics 68: 3759.Google Scholar
Gilhuly, K. 2014. “Corinth, Courtesans and the Politics of Place.” In Gilhuly, K. and Worman, N., eds., Space, Place, and Landscape in Ancient Greek Literature and Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 171–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gill, C. 2013. “What is the Point of the Tripartite Psyche in Plato's Republic?” In Nōtomi, N. and Brisson, L., eds., 161–67.Google Scholar
Goodall, J. 2000. Through a Window: My Thirty Years with the Chimpanzees of Gombe. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. 1960. “Republic Book V: τὰ πολλὰ ϰαλά, etc.” Phronesis 5.2: 116–28.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. 1973. Plato. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gould, D. 1980. “The Uncertain Fate of a Princely Diversion – An Historical Survey of Tops.” Expedition 22.3: 4347.Google Scholar
Graeser, A. 1969. Probleme der platonischen Seelenteilungslehre. Munich: Beck.Google Scholar
Gregory, A. 1996. “Astronomy and Observation in Plato's Republic.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27.4: 451–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grube, G. 1935. Plato's Thought. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Hanson, V. 1995. The Other Greeks. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Hardie, W. 1936. A Study in Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harrison, E. 1953. “The Origin of thumoeidēs.” Classical Review, n.s., 3: 138–40.Google Scholar
Hayek, F. 1948. Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. [1927]1962. Being and Time. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Hitz, Z. 2010. “Degenerate Regimes in Plato's Republic.” In McPherran, , ed., 103–31.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. [1651]1996. Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbs, A. 2000. Plato and the Hero: Courage, Manliness and the Impersonal Good. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hölldobler, B. and Wilson, E.. 1995. Journey to the Ants. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.Google Scholar
Holton, R. 2009. Willing, Wanting, Waiting. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Humberstone, I. 1992. “Direction of Fit.” Mind 101.401: 5983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. [1738]2000. A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurley, S. 2003. “Animal Action in the Space of Reasons.” Mind and Language 18.3: 231–56.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1977a. Plato's Moral Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1977b. “Plato's Heracleiteanism.” Philosophical Quarterly 27.106: 113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. 1995. Plato's Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. 1946. “A New Greek Word in Plato's Republic.” Eranos 44: 123–30.Google Scholar
Johnstone, M. 2009. Tripartition and the Rule of the Soul in Plato's Republic. Ph.D. Dissertation. Princeton University, Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Johnstone, M. 2011. “Changing Rulers in the Soul: Psychological Transitions in Republic 8–9.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 41: 139–67.Google Scholar
Johnstone, M. 2013. “Anarchic Souls: Plato's Depiction of the ‘Democratic Man.’” Phronesis 58:139–59.Google Scholar
Johnstone, M. 2015. “Tyrannized Souls: Plato's Depiction of the ‘Tyrannical Man.’” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23.3: 423–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jonas, M., Nakazawa, Y. and Braun, J.. 2012. “Appetite, Reason and Education in Socrates’ ‘City of Pigs.’” Phronesis 57: 332–57.Google Scholar
Joseph, H. 1935. Essays in Ancient and Modern Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. 1993. “Proleptic Composition in the Republic, or Why Book 1 Was Never a Separate Dialogue.” Classical Quarterly 43.1: 131–42.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1973. “Mental Health in Plato's Republic.” In The Anatomy of the Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Klosko, G. 1988. “The ‘Rule’ of Reason in Plato's Psychology.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 5.4: 341–56.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2005. “Review of G. Santas, Goodness and Justice: Plato, Aristotle, and the Moderns.” Ancient Philosophy 25: 446–63.Google Scholar
Larrabee, M. 1993. An Ethic of Care: Feminist and Interdisciplinary Perspectives.> London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lear, J. 1992. “Inside and Outside the Republic.” Phronesis 37.2: 184215.Google Scholar
Liddell, H., Scott, R. and Jones, H.. 1996. Greek-English Lexicon. 9th ed. with supplement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Liebert, R. 2013. “Pity and Disgust in Plato's Republic: The Case of Leontius.” Classical Philology 108.3: 179201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd-Jones, H. 1983. The Justice of Zeus. 2nd ed. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2004. “Desire and Reason in Plato's Republic.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27: 83116.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2006a. The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2006b. “The Analysis of the Soul in Plato's Republic.” In Santas, G., ed., 146–65.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2008. “Plato on the Soul.” In Fine, G., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 243–66.Google Scholar
McCoy, M. 2015. “The City of Sows and Sexual Differentiation in the Republic.” In Bell, J. and Naas, M., eds., Plato's Animals. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
McKeen, C. 2004. “Swillsburg City Limits (The ‘City Of Pigs’: Republic 370c–372d).” Polity 2004 1–2: 7092.Google Scholar
McPherran, M., ed. 2010. Plato's Republic: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, M. 2007. “Beginning the ‘Longer Way.’” In Ferrari, G., ed., 310–44.Google Scholar
Milliken, J. 2008. “In a Fitter Direction: Moving Beyond the Direction of Fit Picture of Belief and Desire.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11. 5: 563–71.Google Scholar
Modrak, D. 2008. “Desires and Faculties in Plato and Aristotle.” Philosophical Inquiry 30.3/4: 163–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moline, J. 1978. “Plato on the Complexity of the Psyche.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 60: 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, M. 2006. “Akrasia in the Protagoras and the Republic.” Phronesis 51.3: 195229.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2005. “Shame, Pleasure, and the Divided Soul.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29: 137–70.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2006. “Pleasure and Illusion in Plato.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72.3: 503–35.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2008. “Appearances and Calculations: Plato's Division of the Soul.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34: 3568.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2015. Draft: “Against Bare Urges and Good-Independent Desires: Appetites in Republic IV.” Provisionally forthcoming in the Proceedings of the Keeling Colloquium. URL: http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/moss/Bare%20Urges.pdf. Last accessed 6 June 2018.Google Scholar
Munn, M. 2000. The School of History: Athens in the Age of Socrates. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, N. 1951. The Interpretation of Plato's Republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A. 1975. “Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World.” American Philosophical Quarterly 12.2: 105–17.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A. 1982. “Plato on Imitation and Poetry.” In Moravcsik, J. and Temko, P., eds., Plato on Beauty, Wisdom and the Arts. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 4778.Google Scholar
Nettleship, R. 1925. Lectures on the Republic of Plato. 2nd ed. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. [1887]1974. The Gay Science. New York, NY: Vintage.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. [1887]1967. On the Genealogy of Morals. New York, NY: Vintage.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. [1889]1982. Twilight of the Idols. In The Portable Nietzsche. New York, NY: Viking-Penguin.Google Scholar
Nōtomi, N. and Brisson, L., eds. 2013. Dialogues on Plato's Politeia (Republic): Selected Papers from the Ninth Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin: Akademia.Google Scholar
Peitgen, H-O., Jurgens, H. and Saupe, D.. 2004. Chaos and Fractals. Berlin and New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penner, T. 1971. “Thought and Desire in Plato.” In Vlastos, G., ed., Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays, vol. 2. Garden City: Anchor, 96118.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1990. “Plato and Davidson: Parts of the Soul and Weakness of Will.” In Copp, D., ed. Canadian Philosophers: Celebrating Twenty Years of the Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Supplementary Vol. 16: 3574.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1996. “Knowledge vs. True Belief in the Socratic Psychology of Action.” Apeiron 29: 199230.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1997. “Socrates on the Strength of Knowledge: Protagoras 351b–357e.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79: 117–49.Google Scholar
Pinker, S. 1997. How the Mind Works. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Price, A. 1995. Mental Conflict. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Price, A. 2009. “Are Plato's Soul-parts Psychological Subjects?Ancient Philosophy 29.1: 115.Google Scholar
Price, J. 2001. Thucydides and Internal War. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rahula, W. 1974. What the Buddha Taught. New York, NY: Grove.Google Scholar
Redfield, J. 1994. Nature and Culture in Iliad. Durham, NC: Duke.Google Scholar
Rees, D. 1957. “Bipartition of the Soul in the Early Academy.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 77: 112–18.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. 1988. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato's Republic. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Renaut, O. 2013. “La fonction du thumos dans la République de Platon.” In N. Nōtomi and L. Brisson, 179188.Google Scholar
Riedinger, J. 1976. “Rémarques sur la timê chez Homère.” Révue des Études Grècques 89: 244–64.Google Scholar
Riedinger, J. 1980. “Les deux aidôs chez Homère.” Révue de Philologie, de Littérature et d'Histoire Anciennes 54: 6279.Google Scholar
Robinson, R. 1971. “Plato's Separation of Reason from Desire.” Phronesis 16: 3848.Google Scholar
Robinson, T. 1995. Plato's Psychology. 2nd ed. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Roochnik, D. 2003. Beautiful City: The Dialectical Character of Plato's Republic. Ithaca, NY: Cornell.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. 2007. Plato and the Art of Philosophical Writing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Santas, G. X. 1988. Plato and Freud: Two Theories of Love. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Santas, G. X. 2001. Goodness and Justice: Plato, Aristotle and the Moderns. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Santas, G. X. ed. 2006. The Blackwell Guide to Plato's Republic. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sartre, J.-P. 1946. No Exit. New York, NY: Knopf.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 2000. “Plato's Critique of the Democratic Character.” Phronesis 45: 1937.Google Scholar
Schmitt, C. [1932]1996. The Concept of the Political. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. 2006. Plato: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. 2010. “Music all pow'rful.” In M. McPherran, ed., 229–48.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1976. “A Classification of Illocutionary Acts.” Language in Society 5.1: 123.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2001. “Simple Souls.” In Wagner, E., ed., 137–56.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2007. “Unified Agency and Akrasia in Plato's Republic.” In Bobonich, C. and Destrée, P., eds., 6186.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2010. “Plato's Divided Soul.” In McPherran, M., ed., 147–70.Google Scholar
Silverman, A. 2002. The Dialectic of Essence. A Study of Plato's Metaphysics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Silvermintz, D. 2010. “Plato's Supposed Defense of the Division of Labor: A Reexamination of the Role of Job Specialization in the Republic.” History of Political Economy 42.4: 747–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinclair, T. 1948. “Plato's Philosophical Dog.” Classical Review 62: 6162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singpurwalla, R. 2011. “Soul Division and Mimesis in Republic X.” In Destrée, P. and Herrmann, F., eds., Plato and the Poets. Leiden: Brill, 283–98.Google Scholar
Singpurwalla, R. 2013. “Why Spirit is the Natural Ally of Reason: Spirit, Reason, and the Fine in Plato's Republic.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 44: 4165.Google Scholar
Smith, N. 1999. “Plato's Analogy of Soul and State.” Journal of Ethics 3: 3149.Google Scholar
Stalley, R. 1975. “Plato's Argument for the Division of the Reasoning and Appetitive Elements within the Soul.” Phronesis 20: 110–28.Google Scholar
Stalley, R. 2007. “Persuasion and the Tripartite Soul in Plato's Republic.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37: 6389.Google Scholar
Stocks, J. 1915. “Plato and the Tripartite Soul.” Mind 24: 207–21.Google Scholar
Storey, D. 2014. “Appearance, Perception, and Non-Rational Belief: Republic 602c–603a.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47: 81118.Google Scholar
Tait, M. 1949. “Spirit, Gentleness and the Philosophic Nature in the Republic.” Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 80: 203–11.Google Scholar
Thaler, N. 2016. “Learning to Read the Small Letters in Republic Book 2.” Apeiron 50.1: 122.Google Scholar
Van De Mieroop, M. 2007. A History of the Ancient Near East, ca. 3000–323 BC. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Vander Waerdt, P. A. 1985a. “The Peripatetic Interpretation of Plato's Tripartite Psychology.” Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 26: 283302.Google Scholar
Vander Waerdt, P. A. 1985b. “Peripatetic Soul-Division, Posidonius, and Middle Platonic Moral Psychology.” Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 26: 373–94.Google Scholar
Vander Waerdt, P. A. 1987. “Aristotle's Criticism of Soul-Division.” American Journal of Philology 108: 627–43.Google Scholar
Von Mises, L. 1990. Economic Calculation in the Socialist Commonwealth. Auburn, AL: Praxeology.Google Scholar
Von Mises, L. 1996. Human Action. 4th ed. San Francisco, CA: Fox and Wilkes.Google Scholar
Wagner, E. 2001. Essays on Plato's Psychology. Lanham, MD: Lexington.Google Scholar
Weinstein, J. 2009. “The Market in Plato's Republic.” Classical Philology 104.4: 439–58.Google Scholar
Weiss, R. 2006. The Socratic Paradox and its Enemies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 2012. “Psychic Contingency in the Republic.” In Barney, R. et al., eds., 174208.Google Scholar
Wilberding, J. 2009. “Plato's Two Forms of Second-Best Morality.” Philosophical Review 118.3: 351–74.Google Scholar
Wilberding, J. 2012. “Curbing One's Appetites in Plato's Republic.” In Barney, R. et al., eds., 128–49.Google Scholar
Wilburn, J. 2013. “Moral Education and the Spirited Part of the Soul in Plato's Laws.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 45: 63102.Google Scholar
Wilburn, J. 2014a. “Is Appetite Ever ‘Persuaded’?: An Alternative Reading of Republic 554c–d.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 31.3: 195208.Google Scholar
Wilburn, J. 2014b. “Akrasia and the Rule of Appetite in Plato's Republic and Protagoras.” Journal of Ancient Philosophy 8.2: 5791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilburn, J. 2015. “Courage and the Spirited Part of the Soul in Plato's Republic.” Philosopher's Imprint 15.26: 121.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1973. “The Analogy of City and Soul in Plato's Republic.” In Lee, E. N., Mourelatos, R. M. and Rorty, R. M., eds., Exegesis and Argument. New York: Humanities.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1993. Shame and Necessity. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willis, R. 2007. The History of Allelopathy. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Wilson, J. 1995. “Thrasymachus and the Thumos: A Further Case of Prolepsis in Republic I.” The Classical Quarterly 45.1: 5867.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. [1953]2009. Philosophical Investigations. Medford, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. 2013. “Pleasure and Truth in Republic 9.” Classical Quarterly 63.1: 110–38.Google Scholar
Woods, M. 1987. “Plato's Division of the Soul.” Proceedings of the British Academy 73: 2348.Google Scholar
Woolf, R. 2004. “The Practice of a Philosopher.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 26: 97129.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Joshua I. Weinstein
  • Book: Plato's Threefold City and Soul
  • Online publication: 19 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316756065.018
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Joshua I. Weinstein
  • Book: Plato's Threefold City and Soul
  • Online publication: 19 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316756065.018
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Joshua I. Weinstein
  • Book: Plato's Threefold City and Soul
  • Online publication: 19 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316756065.018
Available formats
×