Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-4hvwz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-29T02:21:21.155Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Report misconduct

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2013

Gary Comstock
Affiliation:
North Carolina State University, Raleigh
Get access

Summary

Fabricating, manipulating, changing, making up, falsifying, omitting: what do these verbs have in common? All are part of the Health and Human Services definition of research misconduct and all may be used, given the right context, as synonyms for cheating. As noted in Part A, the research community disapproves of cheating but an egoist need not if a particular act of cheating is in the egoist’s own best interests. So what reasons, if any, does an egoist have not to commit falsification or fabrication of data, or plagiarism?

To answer this question we must understand the complexity of the research context in which the egoist operates, and then ask how likely it is that an egoist’s actual interests will be served by surreptitious corner cutting in research. These are the goals of the next four chapters.

What is cheating?

According to the saying, it takes two to tango. It takes more than one to cheat, too, because cheating is a social act in which one person deceives another. Although we occasionally say that someone “cheats himself,” ordinarily cheating requires one who deceives and another who is deceived (Gert 2001). To deceive is to mislead or lie, to manipulate another’s expectations falsely and so to gain unearned benefits for oneself.

Not all acts of deception are objectionable. Some we not only enjoy but praise. When the basketball player Derrick Rose feints right, crosses over his opponent and drives left around him to the basket, he has definitely misled his defender. But he hasn’t cheated. Basketball rules encourage misdirection. If D. Rose sees that no official is in position to make a call and gains an advantage by touching the ball with both hands while dribbling it, his deception is now illicit because he has harmed others. That is cheating. But when he gains an advantage by deception within the rules he harms no one. His deception is legitimate.

Type
Chapter
Information
Research Ethics
A Philosophical Guide to the Responsible Conduct of Research
, pp. 39 - 57
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ariely, D. 2008a. How Honest People Cheat. Available at: [Accessed August 8, 2009].
Ariely, D. 2008b. Predictably Irrational: The Hidden Forces That Shape Our Decisions, 1st edn. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Ariely, D. 2011. Classroom Ethics 101. Available at: .
Bok, S. 1999. Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life Updated. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
Cloward, D. 2005. Plagiarism: what’s the big deal?The Academic Standard, 5(1), 29–40.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. 1992. Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 163–228.Google Scholar
Couzin-Frankel, J. 2010. Probation for biologist who admitted to misconduct. ScienceInsider. Available at: [Accessed June 8, 2011].
Dennett, D.C. 1995. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Gawrylewski, A. 2009. Fixing fraud. The Scientist, 23(3), 67–69.Google Scholar
Gert, B. 2001. Cheating. In Becker, L. & Becker, C., eds. The Routledge Encyclopedia of Ethics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Giles, J. 2005. Special Report: Taking on the cheats. Nature, 435(7040), 258–259.Google Scholar
Gunsalus, C.K. 1998. How to blow the whistle and still have a career afterwards, or. . . how to conduct professional disputes professionally. Science and Engineering Ethics, 4(1), 51–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martinson, B.C., Anderson, M.S. & de Vries, R. 2005. Scientists behaving badly. Nature, 435(7043), 737–738.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mazar, N., Amir, O. & Ariely, D. 2008c. The dishonesty of honest people: a theory of self-concept maintenance. Journal of Marketing Research, 45, 633–644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mazar, N. & Ariely, D. 2006. Dishonesty in everyday life and its policy implications, Journal of Public Policy & Marketing, 25(1). Available at: at duke.edu/~dandan/Papers/PI/dishonesty.pdf [Accessed June 20, 2011].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mazar, N., Ariely, D. & On, A. 2005d. (Dis)Honesty: a combination of internal and external rewards. Working paper, Sloan School of Management, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, as referenced in Mazar and Ariely (2006).Google Scholar
McCabe, D., Trevino, L. & Butterfield, K. 2001. Cheating in academic institutions: a decade of research. Ethics & Behavior, 11(3), 219–232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, R. 2003. “Mind the gaps”: an empirical approach to engineering ethics, 1997–2001. Science and Engineering Ethics, 9, 517–542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
National Academies (U.S.), 2009. On Being a Scientist: A Guide to Responsible Conduct in Research, 3rd edn. Washington DC: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
Psychology Department, U. of C., Santa Barbara, n.d. The Wason Selection Task. Available at: .
Rhyne, B. 2008. Comment on Dan Ariely, “Why honest people cheat.” Available at: .
Ruhlen, R. 2006. What happens to the whistleblowers? (Letter to the editor). Science, 314(5797), 251–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, K. & Couzin, J. 2006. Even retracted papers endure. Science, 312(5770), 40–41.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
University of Wisconsin, College of Agricultural and Life Sciences. 2007. College of Agricultural and Life Sciences Scientific Misconduct Policy for Graduate Students and Postdoctoral Research Associates. Available at: .

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Report misconduct
  • Gary Comstock
  • Book: Research Ethics
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511902703.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Report misconduct
  • Gary Comstock
  • Book: Research Ethics
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511902703.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Report misconduct
  • Gary Comstock
  • Book: Research Ethics
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511902703.003
Available formats
×