Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
  • Cited by 6
  • Edited by Lara Denis, Agnes Scott College, Decatur
Publisher:
Cambridge University Press
Online publication date:
January 2011
Print publication year:
2010
Online ISBN:
9780511763250

Book description

Immanuel Kant's Metaphysics of Morals (1797), containing the Doctrine of Right and Doctrine of Virtue, is his final major work of practical philosophy. Its focus is not rational beings in general but human beings in particular, and it presupposes and deepens Kant's earlier accounts of morality, freedom and moral psychology. In this volume of newly-commissioned essays, a distinguished team of contributors explores the Metaphysics of Morals in relation to Kant's earlier works, as well as examining themes which emerge from the text itself. Topics include the relation between right and virtue, property, punishment, and moral feeling. Their diversity of questions, perspectives and approaches will provide new insights into the work for scholars in Kant's moral and political theory.

Reviews

'Denis has assembled an outstanding collection of essays that are dedicated to critically exploring Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals. This is an invaluable guide for reading a crucial text within the Kantian corpus.'

Chris McTavish Source: Philosophy in Review

'The book attempts to bridge the gap between German and English-language scholarship. Flikschuh, Wood, and Byrd in particular incorporate German secondary literature.'

Georg Cavallar Source: The European Legacy

Refine List

Actions for selected content:

Select all | Deselect all
  • View selected items
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Save to Kindle
  • Save to Dropbox
  • Save to Google Drive

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

Please provide a title, maximum of 40 characters.
×

Contents

  • 1 - Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: the history and significance of its deferral
    pp 9-27
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Immanuel Kant's Metaphysics of Morals appeared in 1797. The metaphysics of morals contains all the principles that "determine action and omission a priori and make them necessary". It will be "pure morality, which is not grounded on any anthropology. Kant's Groundwork clearly meant for an antecedent of the Metaphysics of Morals. Kant had to promise that he would not publish on religious topics, but any Metaphysics of Morals had to include a discussion of the relations between morality and religion. This chapter divides Kant's deferment of the proposed Metaphysics of Morals into three periods, with the first one dating from 1762 to about 1770, the second one from 1770 to 1785, and the third period from 1785 to 1797. The lectures that were most relevant for Metaphysics of Morals were those on natural law, on ethics, and on anthropology.
  • 2 - Reason, desire, and the will
    pp 28-50
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter examines Kant's mature conception of the will, as presented in the Introduction to the Metaphysics of Morals. It also examines Kant's account of the faculty of desire, and then considers how the will is constituted through the relation reason bears to this faculty. Kant defines the faculty of desire, or the capacity to desire, as it might also be called as "the capacity to be, through one's representations, the cause of the objects of those representations". Having outlined separately Kant's conceptions of reason and desire as powers of cognition and causality, the chapter considers them together, in the idea of the will. It is noteworthy that the will is represented as having certain precedence over the power of choice, even in the latter's inner employment. Will and power of choice are distinguished through the difference between cognitive and causal self-consciousness.
  • 3 - Justice without virtue
    pp 51-70
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter suggests two sorts of objections that mere outward conformity of a person's action with general principles of justice is all that can be required by justice even if not by ethics. It engages with both these objections, though pays more attention to the first and flags the second objection. The chapter sets out the systematic objection to the possible inclusion of Kant's philosophy of Right in his moral philosophy. It also argues that if one starts from central concerns of the Doctrine of Right, the text's distinctly public morality comes into focus. This chapter draws on Kant's late Wille/Willkr distinction in order to tease out the distinctive nature of public juridical willing: surprisingly, in the political context, autonomy as self-legislation is simply irrelevant. It explores how individual political judgment relates to public willing; and discovers crucial differences between Kant's political morality and Kant-inspired current liberalism.
  • 4 - Kant's innate right as a rational criterion for human rights
    pp 71-92
  • View abstract

    Summary

    The idea of a single innate right rests, as does the entire first part of the Metaphysics of Morals, upon a double distinction. Kant differentiates between two fundamentally distinct basic questions - what is "laid down as right" and "what is right" - and two fundamentally distinct doctrines of right, an empirical and a natural one. Thereupon follows reflections concerning the moral concept of right and the moral law of right, the authorization to employ force, and the turn of phrase "by virtue of his humanity". The chapter analyzes how Kant clarifies his thesis of an innate right in four statements, which only appear to refute his singular use of "human right". The conclusion further sharpens the focus already brought to Kant's thesis by mentioning two quasi-human rights. Even though Kant considers there to be only one innate human right, two further pronouncements are relevant to human rights.
  • 5 - Intelligible possession of objects of choice
    pp 93-110
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter maps out Kant's arguments on how to have something as one's own. Kant has three concepts of possession: empirical physical possession, possession as a pure concept of the understanding, and intelligible possession. Notable about Kant's discourses on the permissive law in "Toward Perpetual Peace" is that they provide what might be called a justification for a temporary period of time to right a wrongful situation. Interpreting the permissive law as a power-conferring norm has the benefit of making the Kant text comprehensible. Kant's sole prerequisite for being permitted to take an external object into one's possession is that no one else's freedom of choice is violated through the taking. Kant's entire line of argumentation on original acquisition of external things can be applied by analogy to derived acquisition under contract or by virtue of a family relationship.
  • 6 - Punishment, retribution, and the coercive enforcement of right
    pp 111-129
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Most philosophers who have considered legal punishment suppose that penal institutions, either as they exist or at least as they would exist if they lived up to some normative concept of them, can be morally justified. Kant is best known as a subscriber to the first of the justifications of punishment. Kant's insistence on retributivism, that it is a fundamental moral principle or categorical imperative that moral evil deserves punishment is clear enough. Punishment is justified as a form of coercion used to protect right. Kant occasionally tries to present God's providential apportionment of happiness in accordance with worthiness as a case of doing retributive justice. Whatever opinions Kant himself may have held or expressed in favor of retributivism, Kantian ethics is seriously lacking as long as it cannot justify them or even consistently include them.
  • 7 - Moral feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals
    pp 130-151
  • View abstract

    Summary

    In his lectures on ethics prior to the Groundwork, Kant insisted upon an indispensable causal role for feeling in the production of moral action. Kant's discussion of the "Aesthetic Preconditions of the Mind's Receptivity to Concepts of Duty in General" in Section XII of the Introduction to the Doctrine of Virtue is brief but raises many questions. The chapter explores what causal roles do these distinct "aesthetic preconditions" play and how do they relate to the causal role or roles of the single feeling of respect Kant previously recognized. It discusses Kant's exposition and then Kant's four aesthetic preconditions. The empirical consciousness of the moral law produces a general feeling of respect that causes or at least strengthens our commitment to acting in accordance with it and that needs to be and can be cultivated.
  • 8 - What is the enemy of virtue?
    pp 152-169
  • View abstract

    Summary

    In the Doctrine of Virtue, the apparently unambiguous enemy of virtue is the inclinations, understood as a natural force. This chapter compares the two scenarios: inclinations, then a particular state of a free, rational being, as the enemy of virtue. It distinguishes Kantian and Aristotelian virtue more clearly. Inclinations are "impulses of nature", operating according to the laws of the natural world. The relationship of virtue to freedom can be best understood by exploring Kant's idea of "inner freedom". Kant suggests that vicious acts occur when the strength of one's natural inclinations overwhelms the strength of one's inner freedom. In the Groundwork, Kant describes a person tempted, through a process of rationalization, perversion, or corruption, to avert his eyes from the categorical demands of morality. Vicious acts are perverse realizations of freedom, a turning of the strength of freedom on its head as weakness.
  • 9 - Freedom, primacy, and perfect duties to oneself
    pp 170-191
  • View abstract

    Summary

    Kant attributes primacy to duties to oneself in general and perfect duties to oneself (PDS) in particular. Kant describes morality as "based on the conception of the human being as one who is free but who also, just because of that, binds himself through reason to unconditional laws". For the relationship between freedom and perfect duties to oneself to explain the primacy of PDS, especially tight, deep, or otherwise significant relations must hold between them. This chapter explicates three accounts of perfect duties to oneself. Within all three, Kant equates violating PDS with degrading oneself, subordinating one's rational freedom to other objects, impairing one's agency, and treating oneself as a thing or mere means. Kant's lectures on ethics and the Doctrine of Virtue provide distinct accounts of perfect duties to oneself.
  • 10 - Duties to and regarding others
    pp 192-209
  • View abstract

    Summary

    This chapter discusses Kant's views on the nature of the beings to whom we can owe duties. It also discusses views held by Andrews Reath and Allen Wood about what it means to have a duty to a person. The chapter discusses the relationship between duties to a person and the claims she may have on us as a result of such duties. In the Doctrine of Virtue, Kant offers a principle that he regards as the foundation of the division between obligations toward oneself and obligations toward others. Kant evidently thought that the necessity of willing our happiness together with our individual inability to achieve it implied the proposition that we cannot rationally will that everyone refuse to adopt anyone else's happiness as his end. The latter is the proposition he would need in order to gain the conclusion that the happiness of others is an obligatory end.
  • 11 - Duties regarding animals
    pp 210-233
  • View abstract

    Summary

    A better appreciation of Kant's commitments in a variety of disciplines reveals that Kant had a deeper understanding of human and non-human animals than is generally recognized and will help address, at least from Kant's perspective, many of the familiar objections to his account of our "duties regarding animals". It reviews some of Kant's core principles about the nature of moral obligation, which structure his thoughts about the moral status of human beings and non-human animals. Then, it considers Kant's account of the nature of and distinction between humans and non-human animals. With this account in hand, the chapter turns to Kant's case for claiming that we have duties to every human being and significant duties regarding non-human animals that are grounded in their nature. Finally, in "Two Kantian alternatives", this chapter considers Kant's account in relation to some recently proposed Kantian alternatives.
  • 12 - Kant's Tugendlehre as normative ethics
    pp 234-255
  • View abstract

    Summary

    In The Metaphysics of Morals, especially the Tugendlehre or Doctrine of Virtue, Kant clarifies, develops, and extends ideas that he presented in the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals and the Critique of Practical Reason. This chapter reviews some features of normative ethics that distinguish Tugendlehre from science, metaphysics, metaethics, and theories of law. It discusses the role of the basic moral principles in Kant's theory and how they relate to more specific principles. The chapter considers Kant's idea of duties to oneself and their relevance to certain contemporary discussions. Then, it discusses second-order duties to oneself that anticipate our liability to errors in moral judgment, ulterior motives, and weakness of will. Finally, the chapter notes some ways in which the Tugendlehre is incomplete. It is incomplete partly because Kant's aim was only to present the first principles of "the doctrine of virtue".
Bibliography
Achenwall, G.Ius Naturae, 5th edn., Göttingen: Bossiegel, 1763
Achenwall, G.Prolegomena Iuris Naturalis, 2nd edn., Göttingen: Bossiegel, 1763
Allison, H.E.Kant's Theory of Freedom, Cambridge University Press, 1990
Ameriks, K.Kant's Theory of Mind, Oxford University Press, 1982, 2002
Aristotle, . De Anima, Smith, J.A. (trans.), in Barnes, J. (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, Princeton University Press, 1984, vol. i, 641–92
Anima, Aristotle.Nicomachean Ethics, Broadie, S. (ed.), Rowe, C. (ed. and trans.), Oxford University Press, 2002
Anima, Aristotle.Nicomachean Ethics, Ross, W.D. (trans.), in Barnes, (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, vol. ii, 1729–867
Arnoldt, E.Gesammelte Schriften, 6 vols., Schöndörffer, O. (ed.), Berlin: B. Cassirer, 1907–09
Arntzen, S.“Kant on Duty to Oneself and Resistance to Political Authority,”Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (3) (1996), 409–24
Baranzke, H.“Tierethik, Tiernatur und Moralanthropologie im Kontext von §17 Tugendlehre,”Kant-Studien 96 (2005), 336–63
Baron, M.Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995
Baron, M., and Seymour Fahmy, M.. “Beneficence and Other Duties of Love in The Metaphysics of Morals,” in Hill, Thomas E., Jr. (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Kant's Ethics, Oxford and Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, 211–28
Baxley, A.M.“Autonomy and Autocracy,”Kant-Studien 94 (2003), 1–23.
Beck, L.W.A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason, University of Chicago Press, 1960
Brandt, R. “Das Erlaubnisgesetz, oder: Vernunft und Geschichte in Kants Rechtslehre,” in R. Brandt, (ed.), Rechtsphilosophie der Aufklärung: Symposium Wolfenbüttel 1981, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1982, 233–85
Brandt, R. “Das Problem der Erlaubnisgesetze im Spätwerk Kants,” in Höffe, O. (ed.), Immanuel Kant: Zum ewigen Frieden, Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1995, 69–86
Broadie, A., and Pybus, E.M.. “Kant's Treatment of Animals,”Philosophy 49 (1974), 375–83
Busch, W.Die Entstehung der kritischen Rechtsphilosophie Kants, 1762–1780, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1979
Byrd, B.S.“Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution,”Law and Philosophy 8 (1989), 151–200
Byrd, B.S., and Hruschka, J.. Kant's Doctrine of Right: A Commentary, Cambridge University Press, 2010
Dancy, J.Ethics without Principles, Oxford University Press, 2004
Denis, L.“Animality and Agency: A Kantian Approach to Abortion,”Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2008), 117–37
Denis, L.“Kant on the Wrongness of ‘Unnatural’ Sex,”History of Philosophy Quarterly 16 (2) (1999), 225–48
Denis, L.“Kant's Conception of Duties Regarding Animals: Reconstruction and Reconsideration,”History of Philosophy Quarterly 17 (2000), 405–23
Denis, L.“Kant's Ethics and Duties to Oneself,”Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (1997), 321–48
Denis, L.Moral Self-Regard: Duties to Oneself in Kant's Moral Theory, New York and London: Garland Publishing, 2001
Donagan, A.“Moral Dilemmas, Genuine and Spurious: A Comparative Anatomy,”Ethics 104 (1993), 7–21; reprinted in J.E. Malpas (ed.), Philosophical Papers of Alan Donagan, vol. ii, University of Chicago Press, 1994, 153–68
Donagan, A. “The Relation of Moral Theory to Moral Judgment: A Kantian Review,” in Brody, Baruch (ed.), Moral Theory and Moral Judgments in Medical Ethics, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988, 171–92; reprinted in Malpas (ed.), Philosophical Papers of Alan Donagan, vol. ii, 194–216
Donagan, A.The Theory of Morality, University of Chicago Press, 1977
Dreier, R.“Zur Einheit der praktischen Philosophie Kants,”Perspektiven der Philosophie 5 (1979), 5–37
Engstrom, S. “The Inner Freedom of Virtue,” in Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays, Oxford University Press, 2002, 289–315.
Feinberg, J.“The Expressive Function of Punishment,”Monist 49 (1965), 394–423
Feinberg, J.“The Nature and Value of Rights,”Journal of Value Inquiry 4 (1970), 243–57
Fichte, J.F.Fichtes sämtliche Werke, Fichte, I.H. (ed.), Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1970
Fichte, J.F.Foundations of Natural Right, Baur, M. (trans.), Neuhouser, F. (ed.), Cambridge University Press, 2000
Fleischacker, S.“Kant's Theory of Punishment,”Kant-Studien 79 (4) (1988), 434–49
Flikschuh, K. “Freedom and Constraint in Kant's Metaphysical Elements of Justice,” in Byrd, S. and Hruschka, J. (eds.), Kant and Law, Hants: Ashgate, 2006, 87–108
Flikschuh, K. “Hobbes and Kant on Public Authority,” Hobbes Studies (in press)
Flikschuh, K.“Ist das rechtliche Postulat ein Postulat der reinen praktischen Vernunft? Zum Endzweck der Kantischen Rechtslehre,”Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik 12 (2004), 299–330
Flikschuh, K.Kant and Modern Political Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, 2000
Flikschuh, K. “Kant's Kingdom of Ends: Metaphysical, Not Political,” in Timmermann, J. (ed.), Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide, Cambridge University Press 2009, 119–39
Flikschuh, K.“Reason, Right, and Revolution: Locke and Kant,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 36 (2008), 375–404
Freud, S. “Formulations on the Two Principles of Mental Functioning,” in The Case of Schreber, Papers on Technique and Other Works, Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, vol. xii (1911–13), Strachey, J. (ed.), London: Hogarth Press, 1958, 218–26
Freud, S. “Formulierungen über die zwei Prinzipien des psychischen Geschehens,” in Mitscherlich, A. (ed.), Studienausgabe, 8th edn., Frankfurt am Main: S. Fischer, 1997, vol. iii, 13–24
Frierson, P.“Kant's Empirical Account of Human Action,”Philosophers' Imprint 5 (7) (2005), 1–34
Gregor, M.J.Laws of Freedom: A Study of Kant's Method of Applying the Categorical Imperative in the Metaphysik der Sitten, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1963
Gregor, M.J. “Translator's Note on the Text of the Metaphysics of Morals,” in Immanuel Kant, Practical Philosophy, Gregor, M.J. (ed. and trans.), Cambridge University Press, 1996, 355–59
Grenberg, J.M.Kant and the Ethics of Humility: A Story of Dependence, Corruption, and Virtue, Cambridge University Press, 2005
Grenberg, J.M.“Replies,”Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (3) (2007), 640–54
Grimm, J. and G. (eds.). Deutsches Wörterbuch, 33 vols, Munich: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1984, vol. xxii.
Grotius, H.De Iure Belli ac Pacis, Tromp, B.J.A. de Kanter-van Hettinga (ed.), Louvain: Brill, 1939
Guevara, D.Kant's Theory of Moral Motivation, Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 2000
Guyer, P. “Duties Regarding Nature,” in Kant and the Experience of Freedom, 303–34
Guyer, P.Kant and the Experience of Freedom, Cambridge University Press, 1993
Guyer, P.Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness, Cambridge University Press, 2000
Hare, J.E.The Moral Gap, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996
Hampton, J.“The Moral Education Theory of Punishment,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (3) (1984), 208–38
Herman, B.“Making Room for Character,” in Moral Literacy, 1–28.
Herman, B.Moral Literacy, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2007
Herman, B.The Practice of Moral Judgment, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993
Herman, B. “Rethinking Kant's Hedonism,” in Moral Literacy, 176–202
Hill, Thomas E.. “Donagan's Kant,”Ethics 104 (1993), 22–52; reprinted in Thomas E. Hill, Jr., Respect, Pluralism, and Justice, Oxford University Press, 2000, 119–51
Hill, Thomas E.. “Four Conceptions of Conscience,”Nomos 40 (1998), 13–52; reprinted in Human Welfare and Moral Worth, 277–309
Hill, Thomas E.. Human Welfare and Moral Worth: Kantian Perspectives, Oxford University Press, 2002
Hill, Thomas E.. “Kant on Imperfect Duty and Supererogation,”Kant-Studien 72 (1971), 55–76
Hill, Thomas E.. “Meeting Needs and Doing Favors,” in Human Welfare and Moral Worth, 201–44
Anima, Aristotle.“Wrongdoing, Desert, and Punishment,” in Human Welfare and Moral Worth, 310–39; originally published as “Kant on Wrongdoing, Desert and Punishment,” Law and Philosophy 18 (1) (1999), 407–75
Hobbes, T.Leviathan [1651], Curley, E. (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1994
Höffe, O. “Categorical Imperatives of Right According to Ulpian,” in Kant's Cosmopolitan Theory of Law and Peace, Newton, A. (trans.), Cambridge University Press, 2006, 119–33
Höffe, O.Categorical Principles of Law: A Counterpoint to Modernity, Migotti, M. (trans.), University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2002
Höffe, O. “Der kategorishe Rechtsimperativ. ‘Einleitung in die Rechtslehre,’” in Höffe, O. (ed.), Immanuel Kant, Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre, Klassiker Auslegen XIX, Berlin: C.H. Beck-Verlag, 1999, 41–62
Höffe, O. “Kategorische Rechtsimperative nach Ulpian,” in “Königliche Völker”: Zu Kants kosmopolitischer Rechts- und Friedenstheorie, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2001, 147–60
Höffe, O.Kategorishe Rechtsprinzipien. Ein Kontrapunkt der Moderne, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1995
Höffe, O.Political Justice: Foundation for a Liberal Philosophy of Law and the State, Cohen, J.C. (trans.), Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995
Höffe, O.Politische Gerechtigkeit. Grundlegung einer kritischen Philosophie von Recht und Staat, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1987
Höffe, O. “The Principle of Justice as Categorical Imperative of Law,” in Yovel, Y. (ed.), Kant's Practical Philosophy Reconsidered, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989, 149–67
Hohfeld, W.Fundamental Legal Conceptions, Cook, W. (ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919
Hruschka, J.“The Permissive Law of Practical Reason in Kant's Metaphysics of Morals,”Law and Philosophy 23 (2004), 45–72
Hume, D.A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd edn., Selby-Bigge, L.A. and Nidditch, P.H. (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978
Hutcheson, F.An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, with Illustrations on the Moral Sense, Garret, A. (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Liberty Fund, 2002
Ilting, K.-H.“Gibt es eine kritische Ethik und Rechtsphilosophie Kants?”Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 63 (1983), 325–45
Ingensiep, H.W.“Tierseele und tierethische Argumentationen in der Deutschen philosophischen Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts,”NTM: Internationale Zeitschrift für Geschichte und Ethik der Naturwissenschaften, Technik und Medizin (N.S.) 4 (1996), 103–18
Jellinek, G.System der subjektiven öffentlichen Rechte, Tübingen: Mohr, 1892, 1905
Johnson, R.N. “Self-Improvement: An Essay in Kantian Ethics,” unpublished manuscript
Johnson, R.N. “Value and Autonomy in Kantian Ethics,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. ii, Oxford University Press, 2007, 33–48
Kain, P.“Kant's Defense of Human Moral Status,”Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (2009), 59–102
Kain, P.“Self-Legislation in Kant's Moral Philosophy,”Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 86 (2004), 257–306
Kant, I.Die Metaphysik der Sitten in zwey Theilen. Erster Teil: Metaphysische Anfangsgründeder Rechtslehre; Zweiter Teil: Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Tugendlehre, Königsberg: Friedrich Nicolovius, 1797
Kant, I.Erläuternde Anmerkungen zu der Rechtslehre, Königsberg: Friedrich Nicolovius, 1798
Kant, I.Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Hill, T.E., Jr. (ed.), Zweig, A. (trans.), Oxford University Press, 2002
Kant, I.Metaphysik der Sitten, 2nd edn., Vorländer, K. (ed.), Leipzig: Verlag der Dürr'schen Buchhandlung, 1907
Kant, I.Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre: Metaphysik der Sitten, Erster Teil, Ludwig, B. (ed.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1986, 1998
Kant, I.Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Tugendlehre: Metaphysik der Sitten, Zweiter Teil, Ludwig, B. (ed.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1990
Kant, I.Vorlesungen zur Moralphilosophie, Stark, W. (ed.), Introduction by M. Kuehn, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2004
Kelsen, H.Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory: A Translation of the First Edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or Pure Theory of Law, Litschewski Paulson, B. and Paulson, S.L. (trans.), Oxford University Press, 1997
Kelsen, H.Reine Rechtslehre, Vienna: Auflage, 1960
Kerstein, S.J. “Treating Oneself Merely as a Means,” in Betzler, M. (ed.), Kant's Ethics of Virtue, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2008, 201–18
Kersting, W.Wohlgeordnete Freiheit, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984
Köhl, H.Kants Gesinnungsethik, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1990
Korsgaard, C.M.Creating the Kingdom of Ends, Cambridge University Press, 1996
Korsgaard, C.M. “Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals,” in Peterson, G.B. (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. xxv, Salt Lake City: Utah University Press, 2005, 77–110
Korsgaard, C.M. “Interacting with Animals: A Kantian Account,” in Beauchamp, T. and Frey, R.G. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook on Ethics and Animals, Oxford University Press, in press
Korsgaard, C.M.The Sources of Normativity, O'Neill, O. (ed.), Cambridge University Press, 1996
Kuehn, M. “Introduction,” in Immanuel Kant, Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, Louden, R.B. (ed. and trans.), Cambridge University Press, 2006, vii–xxix
Kymlicka, W.Liberalism, Community, and Culture, Oxford University Press, 1991
Mackie, J.“Can There Be a Rights-Based Moral Theory?”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 3 (1978), 350–59
Meier, G.F.Philosophische Sittenlehre, Halle: Hemmerde, 1753–61, §975
Morris, H.“Persons and Punishment,”Monist 52 (1968), 475–501
Mulholland, L.Kant's System of Rights, New York: Columbia University Press, 1990
Murphy, J.G.Kant: The Philosophy of Right, London: Macmillan, 1970
Naragon, S. “Kant in the Classroom,” online at www.manchester.edu/kant/
Naragon, S.“Kant on Descartes and the Brutes,”Kant-Studien 81 (1990), 1–23
Naragon, S. “Reason and Animals: Descartes, Kant, and Mead on the Place of Humans in Nature,” unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Notre Dame (1987)
Nozick, R.Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York: Basic Books, 1974
Nussbaum, M.Frontiers of Justice: Disabilities, Nationality, Species Membership, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2006
Oberer, H.“Zur Frühgeschichte der Kantischen Rechtslehre,”Kant-Studien 64 (1973), 88–102
Oberhausen, M., and Pozzo, R. (eds.), Vorlesungsverzeichnisse der Universität Königsberg (1720–1804), 2 vols., Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog, 1999
O'Neill, O.Bounds of Justice, Cambridge University Press, 2000
O'Neill, O.Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, 1989
Pincoffs, E.The Rationale of Legal Punishment, New York: Humanities Press, 1966
Potter, N. “Does Kant Have Two Concepts of Freedom?” in Funke, G. and Kopper, J. (eds.), Akten des Vierten Internationalen Kant Kongresses, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1974, 590–96
Potter, N. “Duties to Oneself, Motivational Internalism, and Self-Deception in Kant's Ethics,” in Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays, Oxford University Press, 2002, 371–89
Potter, N. “Kant on Punishment,” in Hill, Thomas E., Jr. (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Kant's Ethics, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, 179–95
Pybus, E., and Broadie, A.. “Kant's Treatment of Animals,”Philosophy 49 (1974), 375–83
Rawls, J.Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 2000
Rawls, J. “Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy,” in Förster, E. (ed.), Kant's Transcendental Deductions: The Three “Critiques” and the “Opus postumum,”Stanford University Press, 1989, 81–113
Rawls, J.A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971
Reath, A.Agency and Autonomy in Kant's Moral Theory: Selected Essays, Oxford University Press, 2006
Reath, A. “Self-Legislation and Duties to Oneself,” in Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays, Oxford University Press, 2002, 349–70; reprinted in Agency and Autonomy, 231–49
Regan, T.The Case for Animal Rights, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984
Ripstein, A.“Authority and Coercion,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (1) (2004), 2–35
Ritter, C.Der Rechtsgedanke nach den frühen Quellen Kants, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1971
Ross, W. D.The Right and the Good, Stratton-Lake, Philip (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001
Scanlon, T.M.What We Owe Each Other, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1998
Scheid, D.E.“Kant's Retributivism,”Ethics 93 (1983), 262–82
Schleiermacher, F.Kritische Gesamtausgabe, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984
Schmucker, J. Rezension, in Die Ursprünge der Ethik Kants in seinen vorkritischen Schriften und Reflexionen, Meisenheim am Glan: A. Hain, 1961, 365–69
Schopenhauer, A.Werke in fünf Bänden, Ludger, Lüdtkehaus (ed.), Ulm: Haffmanns Verlag, 1988, vols. i and iii
Sensen, O. “Dignity and the Formula of Humanity,” in Timmermann, J. (ed.), Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide, Cambridge University Press, 2009, 102–18
Shell, S.M.“Kant on Punishment,”Kantian Review 1 (1997), 115–36
Sherman, N.Making a Necessity of Virtue, Cambridge University Press, 1997
Singer, P.Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals, New York: Random House, 1975
Thomasius, C.Fundamenta Juris Naturae et Gentium, 4th edn. [1718], Aalen: Scientia, reprint 1963
Timmermann, J.“Kant on Conscience, ‘Indirect’ Duty, and Moral Error,”International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2006), 293–308
Timmermann, J.“Kantian Duties to the Self, Explained and Defended,”Philosophy 81 (2006), 505–29
Timmermann, J.“When the Tail Wags the Dog: Animal Welfare and Indirect Duty in Kantian Ethics,”Kantian Review 10 (2005), 128–49
Timmons, M. (ed.). Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays, Oxford University Press, 2002
Unna, Y.“Kant's Answers to the Casuistical Questions Concerning Self-Disembodiment,”Kant-Studien 94 (2003), 454–73
Vasilyev, V., Korsgaard, C., and Singer, P.. “International Kant Interview, 2004–2005,” online at www.philos.msu.ru/community/staff/vasiliev/Kant_Interview/Kant_Interview.htm
Vorländer, K. “Einleitung,” in Immanuel Kant, Metaphysik der Sitten, 2nd edn., Leipzig: Verlag der Dürr'schen Buchhandlung, 1907, ix–li
Walch, J.G. “Zulassung,” in Hennings, J.C. (ed.), Philosophisches Lexicon, 4th edn. [1775], Hildesheim: Olms, reprint 1968, vol. ii, col. 1708
Warren, M.A.Moral Status: Obligation to Persons and Other Living Things, Oxford University Press, 1997
Wellman, C.Real Rights, Oxford University Press, 1995
Westphal, K.R.“Do Kant's Principles Justify Property or Usufruct?”Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik 5 (1997), 142–94
Willaschek, M. “Which Imperatives for Right? On the Non-Prescriptive Character of Juridical Law in Kant's Metaphysics of Morals,” in Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays, Oxford University Press, 2002, 65–87
Willaschek, M.“Why the Doctrine of Right Does Not Belong in the Metaphysics of Morals,”Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik 5 (1997), 205–27
Williams, H.Kant's Political Philosophy, London: St. Martin's Press, 1983
Wood, A.W. “The Final Form of Kant's Practical Philosophy,” in Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays, Oxford University Press, 2002, 1–21
Wood, A.W. “General Introduction,” in Gregor, M.J. (ed. and trans.), Immanuel Kant, Practical Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, 1996, xiii–xxxiii
Wood, A.W.Hegel's Ethical Thought, Cambridge University Press, 1990
Wood, A.W.“Kant on Duties Regarding Nonrational Nature I,”Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 72 (1998), 189–210
Wood, A.W.Kantian Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 2008
Wood, A.W.Kant's Ethical Thought, Cambridge University Press, 1999

Metrics

Full text views

Total number of HTML views: 0
Total number of PDF views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

Book summary page views

Total views: 0 *
Loading metrics...

* Views captured on Cambridge Core between #date#. This data will be updated every 24 hours.

Usage data cannot currently be displayed.