Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-xfwgj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-05T23:13:17.691Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Defining Knowledge

Method and Metaphysics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 October 2022

Stephen Hetherington
Affiliation:
University of New South Wales, Sydney

Summary

Post-Gettier epistemology is increasingly modalized epistemology – proposing and debating modally explicable conditionals with suitably epistemic content (an approach initially inspired by Robert Nozick's 1981 account of knowledge), as needing to be added to 'true belief' in order to define or understand knowing's nature. This Element asks whether such modalized attempts – construed as responding to what the author calls Knowing's Further Features question (bequeathed to us by the Meno and the Theaetetus) – can succeed. The answer is that they cannot. Plato's and Aristotle's views on definition reinforce that result. Still, in appreciating this, we might gain insight into knowing's essence. We might find that knowledge is, essentially, nothing more than true belief.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009092203
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 10 November 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, C. (2019). The Gettier problem and fallibilism. In Hetherington, S., ed., The Gettier Problem, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1126.Google Scholar
Ballantyne, N. (2019). Knowing Our Limits, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Becker, K. and Black, T., eds. (2012). The Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beddor, B. and Goldstein, S. (in press). Mighty knowledge. Journal of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Beddor, B. and Pavese, C. (2020). Modal virtue epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 101: 6179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, H. H. (2013). The priority of definition. In Bussanich, J. and Smith, N. D., eds., The Bloomsbury Companion to Socrates, London: Bloomsbury, pp. 136–55, 342–7.Google Scholar
Bjelde, J. (2021). Knowledge is teachable. Mind, 130: 475502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, R. S., ed. (1961). Plato’s Meno, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bogardus, T. and Perrin, W. (2022). Knowledge is believing something because it’s true. Episteme, 19: 178–96.Google Scholar
Bostock, D. (1988). Plato’s Theaetetus, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bradley, B. (2009). Well-Being and Death, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bronstein, D. (2016). Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, J. (2018). Fallibilism: Evidence and Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (1990). Introduction. In Levett, M. J., trans., The Theaetetus of Plato, Indianapolis: Hackett, pp. 1241.Google Scholar
Carter, J. A. (2018). On behalf of controversial view agnosticism. European Journal of Philosophy, 26: 1358–70.Google Scholar
Carter, J. A. and Bondy, P., eds. (2020). Well-Founded Belief: New Essays on the Epistemic Basing Relation, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Cassam, Q. (2009). Can the concept of knowledge be analysed? In Greenough, P. and Pritchard, D., eds., Williamson on Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. (2012). Constructing the World, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Corlett, J. A. (2005). Interpreting Plato’s Dialogues, Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. (1935). Plato’s Theory of Knowledge: The Theaetetus and the Sophist of Plato Translated with a Running Commentary, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., and Murdoch, D., trans. (1985). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the State of Nature: An Essay in Conceptual Synthesis, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. (1985). An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Deslauriers, M. (2007). Aristotle on Definition, Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Dougherty, T. (2011). Fallibilism. In Bernecker, S. and Pritchard, D., eds., The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, New York: Routledge, pp. 131–43.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1970). Epistemic operators. Journal of Philosophy, 67: 1007–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. (1971). Conclusive reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49: 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engel, M. (1992). Is epistemic luck compatible with knowledge? Southern Journal of Philosophy, 30: 5975.Google Scholar
Engel, M. (2011). Epistemic luck. In Fieser, J. and Dowden, B., eds., Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. www.iep.utm.edu/epi-luck.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (1979). Knowledge and logos in the Theaetetus. Philosophical Review, 88: 366–97.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. and Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Foley, R. (2012). When Is True Belief Knowledge? Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility, Journal of Philosophy, 66: 829–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ganeri, J. (2017). Śrīharṣa’s dissident epistemology: Of knowledge as assurance. In Ganeri, J., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Indian Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 522–38.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. P. (2009). Ancient Epistemology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23: 121–3.Google Scholar
Giannopoulou, Z. (2013). Plato’s Theaetetus as a Second Apology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glock, H.-J. (2008). What Is Analytic Philosophy? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1999). Knowledge in a Social World, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, J. (2003). Knowledge as credit for true belief. In DePaul, M. and Zagzebski, L., eds., Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 111–34.Google Scholar
Greco, J. (2010). Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, J. (2012). A (different) virtue epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85: 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grube, G. M. A., trans. (1981). Plato: Five Dialogues, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Gunderson, L. B. (2003). Dispositional Theories of Knowledge: A Defence of Aetiological Foundationalism, Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.Google Scholar
Hales, S. D. (2020). The Myth of Luck: Philosophy, Fate, and Fortune, London: Bloomsbury Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, E. and Cairns, H., eds. (1961). Plato: The Collected Dialogues, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and Lotteries, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (1996). Knowledge Puzzles: An Introduction to Epistemology, Boulder:Westview Press.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (1999). Knowing failably. Journal of Philosophy, 96: 565–87.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2001). Good Knowledge, Bad Knowledge: On Two Dogmas of Epistemology, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2011a). How to Know: A Practicalist Conception of Knowing, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2011b). Knowledge and knowing: Ability and manifestation. In Tolksdorf, S., ed., Conceptions of Knowledge, Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 73100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2011c). The Gettier problem. In Bernecker, S. and Pritchard, D., eds., The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, New York: Routledge, pp. 119–30.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2014). Knowledge can be lucky. In Steup, M., Turri, J., and Sosa, E., eds., Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd ed., Malden: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 164–76.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2016a). Knowledge and the Gettier Problem, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2016b). Understanding fallible warrant and fallible knowledge: Three proposals. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 97: 270–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2017a). Gettier cases: Transworld identity and counterparts. In Borges, R., de Almeida, C., and Klein, P., eds., Explaining Knowledge: New Essays on the Gettier Problem, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 366–83.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2017b). Knowledge as potential for action. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, 9. https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.1070.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2018a). Knowing as simply being correct. In Zhang, B. and Tong, S., eds., A Dialogue between Law and Philosophy: Proceedings of the International Conference on Facts and Evidence, Beijing: Chinese University of Political Science and Law Press, pp. 6882.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2018b). Knowledge and knowledge-claims: Austin and beyond. In Tsohatzidis, S. L., ed., Interpreting Austin: Critical Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 206–22.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2018c). The redundancy problem: From knowledge-infallibilism to knowledge-minimalism. Synthese, 195: 4683–702.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2019a). What Is Epistemology? Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2019b). Conceiving of knowledge in modal terms? In Hetherington, S. and Valaris, M., eds., The Philosophy of Knowledge: A History, vol. 4, Knowledge in Contemporary Philosophy, London: Bloomsbury, pp. 231–48.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2019c). Creating the world: God’s knowledge as power. Suri, 8: 118.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2020a). Knowledge as skill. In Fridland, E. and Pavese, C., eds., The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Skill and Expertise, New York: Routledge, pp. 168–78.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (2020b). Knowledge-minimalism: Reinterpreting Plato’s Meno on knowledge and true belief. In Hetherington, S. and Smith, N. D., eds., What the Ancients Offer to Contemporary Epistemology, New York: Routledge, pp. 2540.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (in press a). Knowing can include luck. In Roeber, B., Sosa, E., Steup, M., and Turri, J., eds. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 3rd ed., Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. (in press b). On whether knowing can include luck: Asking the correct question. In Roeber, B., Sosa, E., Steup, M., and Turri, J., eds. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 3rd ed., Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jowett, B., trans. (1931 [1892]). The Dialogues of Plato, 3rd edn, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kaplan, M. (1985). It’s not what you know that counts. Journal of Philosophy, 82: 350–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelp, C. (2013). Knowledge: The safe-apt view. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91: 265–78.Google Scholar
Kirkham, R. L. (1984). Does the Gettier problem rest on a mistake? Mind, 93: 501–13.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and its Place in Nature, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. (2006). Appeals to intuition and the ambition of epistemology. In Hetherington, S., ed., Epistemology Futures, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 1025.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2007). Why we don’t deserve credit for everything we know. Synthese 158: 345–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G., trans. and comm. (2001). Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983). Introduction. In his Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. ixxi.Google Scholar
Luper-Foy, S., ed. (1987). The Possibility of Knowledge: Nozick and his Critics, Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (2006). On the Gettier problem problem. In Hetherington, S., ed., Epistemology Futures, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 148–68.Google Scholar
Matilal, B. K. (1986). Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J., trans. (1973). Plato: Theaetetus, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McEvilley, T. (2002). The Shape of Ancient Thought: Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies, New York: Allworth Press.Google Scholar
McKeon, R. M., ed. (1941). The Basic Works of Aristotle, New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Morrow, G. R., trans. and comm. (1962). Plato’s Epistles, Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Moss, J. (2021). Plato’s Epistemology: Being and Seeming, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, J. and Schwab, W. (2019). The birth of belief. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 57: 132.Google Scholar
Nails, D. (2006). The life of Plato of Athens. In Benson, H. H., ed., A Companion to Plato, Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 112.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1993a). Warrant: The Current Debate, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1993b). Warrant and Proper Function, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prior, W. J. (2006). The Socratic problem. In Benson, H.H., ed., A Companion to Plato, Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 2535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic Luck, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2007). Anti-luck epistemology. Synthese, 158: 277–97.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2008). Sensitivity, safety, and antiluck epistemology. In Greco, J., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 437–55.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2012). Anti-luck virtue epistemology. Journal of Philosophy, 109: 247–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2014). Knowledge cannot be lucky. In Steup, M., Turri, J., and Sosa, E., eds., Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd ed., Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 152–64.Google Scholar
Pritchard, S. (2020). Anti-risk virtue epistemology. In Kelp, C. and Greco, J., eds., Virtue Theoretic Epistemology: New Methods and Approaches, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 203–24Google Scholar
Reed, B. (2002). How to think about fallibilism. Philosophical Studies, 107: 143–57.Google Scholar
Robinson, R. (1971). Socratic definition. In Vlastos, G., ed., The Philosophy of Socrates: A Collection of Critical Essays, Garden City: Anchor Books, pp. 110–24.Google Scholar
Roush, S. (2005). Tracking Truth: Knowledge, Evidence, and Science, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rowett, C. (2018). Knowledge and Truth in Plato: Stepping Past the Shadow of Socrates, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sartwell, C. (1991). Knowledge is merely true belief. American Philosophical Quarterly, 28: 157–65.Google Scholar
Sartwell, C. (1992). Why knowledge is merely true belief. Journal of Philosophy, 89: 167–80.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. M. (1969). Plato’s Analytic Method, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. M. (1995). Plato’s Literary Garden: How to Read a Platonic Dialogue, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. M. (2005). Plato’s Late Ontology: A Riddle Resolved, 2nd ed., Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.Google Scholar
Schwab, W. (2015). Explanation in the epistemology of the Meno. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 48: 136.Google Scholar
Scott, D. (2006). Plato’s Meno, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shope, R. K. (1983). The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (1999). How must knowledge be modally related to what is known? Philosophical Topics, 26: 373–84.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (2007). A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, vol. 1, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (2011). Knowing Full Well, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and Agency, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2016). Knowledge in action. In Bahr, A. and Seidel, M., eds., Ernest Sosa: Targeting his Philosophy, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 113.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (2017). Epistemology, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R.C. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In Rescher, N., ed., Studies in Logical Theory, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 98112.Google Scholar
Stoltz, J. (2007). Gettier and factivity in Indo-Tibetan epistemology. Philo-sophical Quarterly, 57: 394415.Google Scholar
Tiles, M. and Tiles, J. (1993). An Introduction to Historical Epistemology: The Authority of Knowledge, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Todd, W. (1964). Counterfactual conditionals and the presuppositions of induction. Philosophy of Science, 31: 101–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. (2011). Manifest failure: The Gettier problem solved. Philosophers’ Imprint, 11: 8 (April): 111.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2019 [2012]). In Gettier’s wake. In Hetherington, S., ed., Epistemology: The Key Thinkers, 2nd ed., London: Bloomsbury, pp. 263–80.Google Scholar
Waterfield, R., trans. (2008). Plato: Timaeus and Critias, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., and Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29: 429–60.Google Scholar
White, N.P. (1976). Plato on Knowledge and Reality, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
White, N.P (1992). Plato’s metaphysical epistemology. In Kraut, R., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 277310.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2009). Probability and danger. The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy 4: 135.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2018). Doing Philosophy: From Common Curiosity to Logical Reasoning, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. (1999). What is knowledge? In Greco, J. and Sosa, E., eds., The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 92116.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. (2009). On Epistemology, Belmont: Wadsworth.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Defining Knowledge
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Defining Knowledge
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Defining Knowledge
Available formats
×