Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-08T01:31:10.405Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Can the Prince Really Be Tamed? Executive Prerogative, Popular Apathy, and the Constitutional Frame in Locke's Second Treatise

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 May 2007

BENJAMIN A. KLEINERMAN
Affiliation:
Harvard University and Virginia Military Institute

Abstract

Even as he recommends it as the extra-constitutional solution to the inefficiencies and insufficiencies of legislative constitutionalism, Locke's Second Treatise is far more aware of the dangers of executive prerogative than the more optimistic accounts in the recent scholarship have appreciated, making Locke pessimistic about the permanent sustenance of legislative constitutionalism. This pessimism stems from Locke's recognition that the people are far too constitutionally passive for the vigilance essential to ‘umpire’ well the necessity of executive action outside the laws. In fact, liberalism itself can contribute to such passivity: the people are content to allow an executive to act with a significant degree of discretion outside the laws so long as those actions do not interfere with their short-term interest in security and prosperity. Understanding Locke's pessimism regarding popular vigilance casts into new light his argument for a legislative constitutionalism based on fundamental laws that establish a clear separation of powers. Such fundamental laws provide legislative elites with the constitutional ‘signals’ by which they can alert the otherwise slumbering people about an executive intent on usurpation and tyranny.

Type
ARTICLES
Copyright
© 2007 by the American Political Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agamben Giorgio. 2005. State of Exception. trans. Kevin Attell. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Ashcraft Richard. 1986. Revolutionary Politics and Locke's Two Treatises of Government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Baker Nancy V. 2002. “The Law: The Impact of Antiterrorism Policies on Separation of Powers: Assessing John Ashcroft's Role.” Presidential Studies Quarterly 32 (December): 76578.Google Scholar
Burgess Glenn. 1996. Absolute Monarchy and the Stuart Constitution. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Cooper Phillip J. 2005. “George W. Bush, Edgar Allen Poe, and the Use and Abuse of Presidential Signing Statements.” Presidential Studies Quarterly. 35: (3) 51532.Google Scholar
Dunn John. 1967. “Consent in the Political Theory of John Locke.” Historical Journal 10 (2): 15382.Google Scholar
Farr James, and Clayton Roberts. 1985. “John Locke and the Glorious Revolution: A Rediscovered Document.” Historical Journal 28 (2): 38598.Google Scholar
Fatovic Clement. 2004a. “Constitutionalism and Contingency: Locke's Theory of Prerogative.” History of Political Thought 25 (Summer): 27697.Google Scholar
Fatovic Clement. 2004b. “Constitutionalism and Presidential Prerogative: Jeffersonian and Hamiltonian Perspectives.” American Journal of Political Science 48 (July): 42944.Google Scholar
Faulkner Robert. 2001. “The First Liberal Democrat: Locke's Popular Government.” The Review of Politics 63 (Winter): 539.Google Scholar
Fisher Louis. 1995. Presidential War Power. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
Gauthier David. 1977. “The Social Contract as Ideology.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (Winter): 13064.Google Scholar
Grant Ruth. 1988. “Locke's Political Anthropology and Lockean Individualism.” The Journal of Politics 50 (February): 4263.Google Scholar
Hamilton Alexander, and James Madison. 1976. Letters of Pacificus and Helvidius. New York: Scholars' Facsimiles and Reprints.
Holmes Stephen. 1995. Passions and Constraint: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Hulliung Mark. 1974. “Patriarchalism and Its Early Enemies.” Political Theory 2 (November): 41019.Google Scholar
Jefferson Thomas. 1982. Notes on the State of Virginia. ed. William Peden. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Josephson Peter. 2002. The Great Art of Government: Locke's Use of Consent. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
Kassop Nancy. 2003. “The War Power and its Limits.” Presidential Studies Quarterly 33 (September): 50929.Google Scholar
Kleinerman Benjamin A. 2005. “Lincoln's Example: Executive Power and the Survival of Constitutionalism.” Perspectives on Politics 3 (December): 80116.Google Scholar
Lincoln Abraham. 2001. Abraham Lincoln: His Speeches and Writings. ed. Roy P. Basler. Cambridge, MA: Da Capo Press.
Lobel Jules. 1989. “Emergency Power and the Decline of Liberalism.” Yale Law Journal 98 (May): 13851433.Google Scholar
Locke John. 1988. Two Treatises of Government. ed. Peter Laslett. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Machiavelli Niccolo. 1998. The Prince. trans. Harvey C. Mansfield. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Macpherson C. B. 1962. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Mansfield Harvey. 1989. Taming the Prince: The Ambivalence of Modern Executive Power. New York: The Free Press.
Mattie Sean. 2005. “Prerogative and the Rule of Law in John Locke and the Lincoln Presidency.” The Review of Politics 67 (Winter): 77111.Google Scholar
McClure Kirstie M. 1996. Judging Rights: Lockean Politics and the Limits of Consent. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Mehta Uday Singh. 1992. The Anxiety of Freedom: Imagination and Individuality in Locke's Political Thought. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Myers Peter C. 1998. Our Only Star and Compass: Locke and the Struggle for Political Rationality. New York: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
Pangle Thomas. 1987. “Executive Energy and Popular Spirit in Lockean Constitutionalism.” Presidential Studies Quarterly 17 (Spring): 25365.Google Scholar
Parry Geraint. 1964. “Individuality, Politics and the Critique of Paternalism in John Locke.” Political Studies 12 (June): 16377.Google Scholar
Pasquino Pasquale. 1998. “Locke on King's Prerogative.” Political Theory 26 (April): 198208.Google Scholar
Pateman Carole. 1979. The Problem of Political Obligation: A Critical Analysis of Liberal Theory. New York: Wiley.
Rahe Paul. 1992. Republics Ancient and Modern. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Resnick David. 1984. “Locke and the Rejection of the Ancient Constitution.” Political Theory 12 (February): 97114.Google Scholar
Rosen Gary. 1999. American Compact: James Madison and the Problem of Founding. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
Rossiter Clinton. 1948. Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Ryan Alan. 1971. ‘Locke and the Dictatorship of the Bourgeousie.’ In Life, Liberty, and Property: Essays on Locke's Political Ideas. ed. Gordon J. Schochet. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Schlesinger Arthur M. 1973. The Imperial Presidency. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Company.
Schmitt Gary J. 2000. “Washington's Proclamation of Neutrality: Executive Energy and the Paradox of Executive Power.” The Political Science Reviewer 39: 12159.Google Scholar
Schochet Gordon J. 1969. ‘The family and the origins of the state in Locke's political philosophy.’ In John Locke: Problems and Perspectives. ed. John W. Yolton. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Schumpeter Joseph A. 1952. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. 5th edition. London, UK: Allen and Unwin.
Scigliano Robert. 1981. ‘The War Powers Resolution and the War Powers.’ In The Presidency in the Constitutional Order. ed. Joseph M. Bessette and Jeffrey Tulis. Baton Rouge LA: Louisiana State University Press.
Scott John T. 2000. “The Sovereignless State and Locke's Language of Obligation.” American Political Science Review 94 (September): 54761.Google Scholar
Seliger Martin. 1968. The Liberal Politics of John Locke. London, UK: George Allen and Unwin.
Sidney Algernon. 1990. Discourses Concerning Government. ed. Thomas G. West. Indianapolis: LibertyClassics.
Tarcov Nathan. 1981. “Locke's Second Treatise and ‘The Best Fence Against Rebellion.’The Review of Politics 43 (April): 198217.Google Scholar
Tarcov Nathan. 1984. Locke's Education for Liberty. Chicago University of Chicago Press.
Tarlton Charles D. 2004. ‘Reason and History in Locke's Second Treatise.’ Philosophy. 79 (April): 24779.Google Scholar
Thomas George. 2000. “As Far as Republican Principles Will Admit: Presidential Prerogative and Constitutional Government.” Presidential Studies Quarterly 30 (September): 53452.Google Scholar
Tocqueville Alexis de. 2000. Democracy in America. trans. Harvey C. Mansfield and Delba Winthrop. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Waldron Jeremy. 1989. “John Locke: Social Contract Versus Political Anthropology.” The Review of Politics 51 (Winter): 328.Google Scholar
Walling Karl-Friedrich. 1999. Republican Empire: Alexander Hamilton on War and Free Government. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.
Ward Lee. 2005. “Locke on Executive Power and Liberal Constitutionalism.” Canadian Journal of Political Science 38 (September): 71944.Google Scholar
Zvesper John. 1984. ‘The Utility of Consent in John Locke's Political Philosophy.’ Political Studies. 32 (March): 5567.Google Scholar
Zuckert Michael P. 1994. Natural Rights and the New Republicanism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.