Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T08:28:35.101Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Massively representational minds are not always driven by goals, conscious or otherwise

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 April 2014

Bryce Huebner
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Georgetown University, Washington, DC 20067. lbh24@georgetown.eduhttp://www9.georgetown.edu/faculty/lbh24/
Robert D. Rupert
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy and Institute of Cognitive Science, University of Colorado, Boulder, Boulder, CO 80309-0232. robert.rupert@colorado.eduhttp://www.colorado.edu/philosophy/fac_rupert.shtml

Abstract

The language of conscious and unconscious goals is rooted in a folk-taxonomy that is likely to inhibit progress in cognitive science. Severing the commitment to this taxonomy would allow Huang & Bargh (H&B) to consider a wider variety of representational forms with motivational force and to entertain the intriguing possibility that variations in the number of active-but-redundant representations account for variance in social behavior.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akins, K. (1996) Of sensory systems and the “aboutness” of mental states. Journal of Philosophy 93(7):337–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A. (1997) Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gendler, T. (2008a) Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy 105(10):634–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gendler, T. (2008b) Alief in action (and reaction). Mind and Language 23 (5):552–85.Google Scholar
Grush, R. (2004) The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27(3):377–96.Google Scholar
Huebner, B. (2013) Macrocognition. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. (1995) Pushmi-pullyu representations. Philosophical Perspectives 9:185200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rupert, R. (2011) Embodiment, consciousness, and the massively representational mind. Philosophical Topics 39(1):99120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schröder, T. & Thagard, P. (2013) The affective meanings of automatic social behaviors: Three mechanisms that explain priming. Psychological Review 120(1):255–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shultz, W., Dayan, P. & Monague, R. (1997) A neural substrate of prediction and reward. Science 275:1593–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wexler, M., Kosslyn, S. & Berthoz, A. (1998) Motor processes in mental rotation. Cognition 68:7794.Google Scholar