Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m42fx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-18T15:48:31.688Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Looking for Answers in All the Wrong Places

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 January 2015

Abstract:

In recent years, many business ethicists have raised problems with the “ethics pays” credo. Despite these problems, many continue to hold it. I argue that support for the credo leads business ethicists away from a potentially fruitful approach found in Hume’s moral philosophy. I begin by demonstrating that attempts to support the credo fail because proponents are trying to provide an answer to the “Why be moral?” question that is based on rational self-interest. Then, I show that Hume’s sentiments-based moral theory provides an alternative to the credo that points toward a more fruitful approach to business ethics. Along the way, I examine a recent social contract alternative to the credo that, despite many appealing features, is less effective than is the Humean alternative. Finally, I develop a Humean approach to business ethics and demonstrate why it is a desirable alternative that business ethicists should explore.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Society for Business Ethics 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arjoon, S. 2000. “Virtue Theory as a Dynamic Theory of Business.” Journal of Business Ethics 28: 159178.Google Scholar
Baier, A. 1992. “Artificial Virtues and the Equally Sensible Non-Knaves: A Response to Gauthier.” Hume Studies 18: 429439.Google Scholar
Boatright, J. R. 1995. “Aristotle Meets Wall Street: The Case for Virtue Ethics in Business.” Business Ethics Quarterly 5: 353359.Google Scholar
Boxill, B. R. 1980. “How Injustice Pays.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 9: 359371.Google Scholar
Brady, F. N. and Dunn, C. P.. 1995. “Business Meta-Ethics: An Analysis of Two Theories.” Business Ethics Quarterly 5: 399418.Google Scholar
Cavanagh, G. F., Moberg, D. J., and Velasquez, M.. 1995. “Making Business Ethics Practical.” Business Ethics Quarterly 5: 385398.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 1999. “Good Ethics is Good Business.” Business & Professional Ethics Journal 18: 5768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooke, R. A. 1991. “Danger Signs of Unethical Behavior: How to Determine If Your Firm Is at Ethical Risk.” Journal of Business Ethics 10: 249253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, D. 1997. “The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and the Unity of Reason.” Social Philosophy and Policy 14: 86106.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. L. 1990. “Autonomist Internalism and the Justification of Morals.” Noûs 24: 257267.Google Scholar
Davis, J. J. 1994. “Good Ethics Is Good for Business: Ethical Attributions and Response to Environmental Advertising.” Journal of Business Ethics 13: 873885.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. H. 1991. “Why Be Moral?” Philosophical Inquiry 13: 121.Google Scholar
DesJardins, J. 1985. “Fairness and Employment-At-Will.” Journal of Social Philosophy 16: 3138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donaldson, T., and Dunfee, T. W.. 1994. “Toward a Unified Conception of Business Ethics: Integrative Social Contracts Theory.” Academy of Management Review 19: 252284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donaldson, T., and Dunfee, T. W.. 1999. Ties That Bind: A Social Contracts Approach to Business Ethics. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.Google Scholar
Fairfield, P. 1995. “Overcoming the Theory/Practice Opposition in Business Ethics.” Business & Professional Ethics Journal 14: 2342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1982. “Three against Justice: The Foole, the Sensible Knave, and the Lydian Shepherd.” In Midwest Studies in Philosophy VII: Social and Political Philosophy, ed. French, P. A., Uehlling, T. E., and Wettstein, H. K.. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1129.Google Scholar
Geels, D. E. 1971. “Plato and the Pay-off of Justice.” Personalist 52: 449458.Google Scholar
Goldsmith, M. M. 1995. “Glaucon’s Challenge.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73: 356367.Google Scholar
Harman, E. 2002. “Can We Do Applied Ethics First? Why We Can And Should Do Applied Ethics Before Settling the Questions in Ethical Theory and Meta-Ethics.” A Paper Presented at the Pacific Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association.Google Scholar
Hartman, E. 1996. Organizational Ethics and the Good Life. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hiley, D. 1985. “Employee Rights and the Doctrine of At Will Employment.” Business & Professional Ethics Journal 4: 110.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. 1962. Leviathan. Ed. Oakeshott, M.. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Hodgson, B. J. 2001. “Michalos and the Theory of Ethical Theory.” Journal of Business Ethics 29: 1923.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, W. M. 1991. “Business and Environmental Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 1: 169184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holley, D. M. 2002. “Alternative Approaches to Applied Ethics: A Response to Carson’s Critique.” Business Ethics Quarterly 12: 7382.Google Scholar
Horvath, C. M. 1995. “Excellence v. Effectiveness: MacIntyre’s Critique of Business.” Business Ethics Quarterly 5: 499532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hosmer, L. T. 1994. “Why Be Moral? A Different Rationale for Managers.” Business Ethics Quarterly 4: 191204.Google Scholar
Hosmer, L. T. 1997. “Why Be Moral?: A Reply to Shaw and Corvino.” Business Ethics Quarterly 7: 137143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. 1948. “Of the Original Contract.” In Hume’s Moral and Political Philosophy, ed. Aiken, H. D.. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 356372.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1975. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A., rev. Nidditch, P. H.. 3rd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A., rev. Nidditch, P. H.. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kaler, J. 1999. “What’s the good of ethical theory?” Business Ethics: A European Review 8: 206213.Google Scholar
Kaler, J. 2000. “Putting ethical theory in its place.” Business Ethics: A European Review 9: 211217.Google Scholar
Kavka, G. S. 1983. “Right Reason and Natural Law in Hobbes’s Ethics.” Monist 66: 120133.Google Scholar
Klein, S. 1989. “Platonic Virtue Theory and Business Ethics.” Business & Professional Ethics Journal 8: 5982.Google Scholar
Koehn, D. 1995. “A Role for Virtue Ethics in the Analysis of Business Practice.” Business Ethics Quarterly 5: 533539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koehn, D. 1998. “Virtue Ethics, the Firm, and Moral Psychology.” Business Ethics Quarterly 8: 497513.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 1999. “The General Point of View: Love and Moral Approval in Hume’s Ethics.” Hume Studies 25: 341.Google Scholar
Luthar, H. K., DiBattista, R. A., and Gautschi, T.. 1997. “Perception of What the Ethical Climate Is and What It Should Be: The Role of Gender, Academic Status, and Ethical Education.” Journal of Business Ethics 16: 205217.Google Scholar
Machan, T. 1987. “Human Rights, Workers’ Rights, and the ‘Right’ to Occupational Safety.” In Moral Rights in the Workplace, ed. Ezorsky, G.. Albany: State University of New York Press, 4550.Google Scholar
Maitland, I. 1989. “Rights in the Workplace: A Nozickian Argument.” Journal of Business Ethics 8: 951954.Google Scholar
Maitland, I. 1997. “Virtuous Markets: The Market as School of the Virtues.” Business Ethics Quarterly 7: 1731.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, P. E. 1999. Character and Virtue Ethics in International Marketing: An Agenda for Managers, Researchers and Educators.” Journal of Business Ethics 18: 107124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paine, L. S. 2000. “Does Ethics Pay?” Business Ethics Quarterly 10: 319330.Google Scholar
Plato. 1974. The Republic, trans. Grube, G. M. A.. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 1988. “Hume’s Reply to the Sensible Knave.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 5: 2340.Google Scholar
Rhodes, R. 1992. “Hobbes’s unReasonable Fool.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 30: 93102.Google Scholar
Sass, R. 1985. “Commentary on Hiley’s ‘Employee Rights and the Doctrine of At Will Employment.’” Business & Professional Ethics Journal 4: 1116.Google Scholar
Sayre-McCord, G. 1989. “Deception and Reasons to be Moral.” American Philosophical Quarterly 26: 113122.Google Scholar
Sen, A. 1997. “Economics, Business Principles and Moral Sentiments.” Business Ethics Quarterly 7: 515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaw, B. 1997. “Sources of Virtue: The Market and the Community.” Business Ethics Quarterly 7: 3350.Google Scholar
Shaw, B. and Corvino, J.. 1996. “Hosmer and the ‘Why Be Moral?’ Question.” Business Ethics Quarterly 6: 373383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, A. 1976a. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, ed. Campbell, R. H. and Skinner, A. S.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Smith, A. 1976b. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. Raphael, D. D. and Macfie, A. L.. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. 1992. “Corporate Roles, Personal Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach to Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 2: 317340.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. 1993. Ethics and Excellence: Cooperation and Integrity in Business. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. 1994. The New World of Business. Latham, Md.: Littlefield Adams Quality Paperbacks.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. 1998. “The Moral Psychology of Business: Care and Compassion in the Corporation.” Business Ethics Quarterly 8: 515533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, R. C. 1999. A Better Way to Think About Business. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sorell, T. 2000. “The Good of Ethical Theory: A Reply to Kaler.” Business Ethics: A European Review 9: 5157.Google Scholar
Spurgin, E. W. 2000. “What’s So Special About a Special Ethics for Business?” Journal of Business Ethics 24: 273281.Google Scholar
Stewart, D. 1996. Business Ethics. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Superson, A. 1990. “The Self-Interest Based Contractarian Response to the Why-Be-Moral Skeptic.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 28: 427447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Superson, A. 1998. “Feminist Ethics: Defeating the Why-Be-Moral Skeptic.” Journal of Social Philosophy 29: 5986.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toenjes, R. H. 2002. “Why Be Moral in Business? A Rawlsian Approach to Moral Motivation.” Business Ethics Quarterly 12: 5772.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trianosky, G. W. 1978. “On the Obligation to be Virtuous: Shaftesbury and the Question, Why Be Moral?” Journal of the History of Philosophy 16: 289300.Google Scholar
Vanderschraaf, P. 1998. “The Informal Game Theory in Hume’s Account of Convention.” Economics and Philosophy 14: 251257.Google Scholar
Vanderschraaf, P. 1999. “Hume’s Game-Theoretic Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 9: 4767.Google Scholar
Werhane, P. H. 1983. “Accountability and Employee Rights.” International Journal of Applied Philosophy 1: 1526.Google Scholar
Werhane, P. H. 1988. “Employee and Employer Rights in an Institutional Context.” In Ethical Theory and Business, third edition, edited by Beauchamp, T. L. and Bowie, N. E.. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 267271.Google Scholar
Werhane, P. H. 1991. Adam Smith and His Legacy for Modern Capitalism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Whetstone, J. T. 2001. “How Virtue Fits Within Business Ethics.” Journal of Business Ethics 33: 101114.Google Scholar