Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T09:31:04.306Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Models of the Doctor-Patient Relationship and the Ethics Committee: Part One

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 July 2009

David C. Thomasma
Affiliation:
Director of the Medical Humanities Program, Loyola University of Chicago Medical Center

Extract

Models of the doctor-patient relationship determine which value will predominate in the interaction of the parties. That value then significantly colors and even sometimers alters the nature of the ethical discussion. For example, if an institution predominately prides it-self on its competitive posture, ethical issues arising therein will necessarily be colored by entrepreurial rather than deontological ethics. By contrast, a physician who underlines patient decision making will tend to place autonomy first above all other principles, casting that relationship in a libertarian tone.

Type
From the Annual Congress of Healthcare Ethics Committees
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. Graber, GC, Thomasma, DC.Theory and practice in medical ethics. New York: Continuum; 1989.Google Scholar

2. Ackerman, TA, Strong, C.A casebook of medical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 1989: viixi.Google Scholar

3. Lain, Entralgo P.La medicina hipocratica. Madrid: Revista de Occidente; 1970.Google Scholar

4. Pellegrino, ED.Thomas Percival's ethics: the ethics beneath the etiquette. In: Percival T. Medical ethics; or, a code of institutes and precepts adapted to the professional conduct of physicians and surgeons. Birmingham, Alabama: The Classics of Medicine Library; 1985: 78.Google Scholar

5. Kimsma, G.Frames of reference and the growth of medical knowledge; Fleck, L. and Foucault, M.. In: Ten Have HAMJ, Kimsma GK, Spicker SF, eds. The growth of medical knowledge. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers; 1990: 42.Google Scholar

6. Ellos, WJ.Ethical practice in clinical medicine. London: Routledge; 1990:1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7. Pellegrino, ED, Thomasma, DC.For the patient's good: toward the restoration of beneficence in health care. New York: Oxford University Press; 1988.Google Scholar

8. Thomasma, DC. The comatose patient, the ontology of death and the decision to stop treatment. Theor Med. 1984; 5 181–96.Google Scholar

9. Mees, JM.Filosofie der Geneeskunst: Medicosofie. Assen, The Netherlands: Van Gorcum; 1984.Google Scholar

10. Lo, B, Dornbrand, L.Guiding the hand that feeds: caring for the demented elderly. In: Walter, JJ, Shannon, TA, eds. Quality of life: the new medical dilemma. New York: Paulist Press; 1990; 232–6.Google ScholarPubMed

11. Angell, M.A dual approach to the AIDS epidemic. N Engl J Med. 1991;324 (05 23); 14981500.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

12. Bayer, R.Public health policy and the AIDS epidemic: an end to HIV exceptionalism? N Engl J Med. 1991; 324: 1500–4.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

13. Bayer, R. (with commentaries by Brandt, RB, Litman, RE.). A suicide attempt and emergency room ethics. Hastings Cent Rep. 1989; 9 (08): 12–3.Google Scholar

14. Engelhardt, HT.The foundations of bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 1986.Google Scholar

15. Bergsma, J, Thomasma, DC.Health care: its psychosocial dimensions. Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania: Duquesne University Press; 1982: 173–96.Google Scholar

16. Pellegrino, ED, Thomasma, DC.The conflict between autonomy and beneficence in medical ethics: proposal for a resolution. J Contemp Health Law Policy. 1987; 3 2346.Google ScholarPubMed

17. Childress, J.Priorities in biomedical ethics. Philadelphia: Westminster Press; 1981:14.Google Scholar

18. See note 15. Bergsma, Thomasma. 1982:80.Google Scholar

19. Thomasma, DC, Graber, GC.Euthanasia: toward an ethical social policy. New York: Continuum; 1990.Google Scholar

20. Phillips, DF.Rising tide of euthanasia support turns to ripples of caution. Hosp Ethics. 1991; 7 (05/06): 23.Google Scholar

21. O'Rourke, K.Prolonging life: a traditional interpretation. Linacre Q. 1991; 58: [in press]Google ScholarPubMed

22. Loewy, E. Beneficence in trust: a review of Pellegrino and Thomasma's “For the patient's good: the restoration of beneficence in health care.” Hastings Cent Rep. 1989; 19 (1): 42–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23. Weinstein, M.US Supreme Court to hear first case involving right-to-die. ACP Observer. 1989; 9; (7): 9.Google Scholar

24. Gaylin, W, Kass, L, Pellegrino, ED, Siegler, M.Commentaries: doctors must not kill. J Am Med Assoc. 1988; 259: 2139–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25. Kass, L.Arguments against active euthanasia by doctors found at medicine's core. Kennedy Inst Ethics Newsl. 1989;3(1):13,6. [This article is a shorter version of a paper that will appear in The Public Interest.]Google Scholar

26. Muller, J, Koenig, B. On the boundary of life and death: the definition of dying by medical residents. In: Lock, M, Gordon, D, eds. Biomedicine examined. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers; 1988: 351–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27. Thomasma, DC.Clinical ethics and public policy: reflections on the Linares case. Law Med Health Care. 1989;17:335–8.Google ScholarPubMed

28. [Anonymous]. Euthanasia drive in Washington claims enough signatures for vote. Med Ethics Advisor. 1991 7(1):46.Google Scholar

29. See note 28. [Anonymous]. 1991;7(1):6.Google Scholar

30. Thomasma, DC.Beware overzealous euthanasia. Med Trib. 1990;31(15):8.Google Scholar

31. Thomasma, D.The range of euthanasia. Bull Am Coll Surgeons. 1988;73(8):413.Google Scholar

32. Dr. Stein Husebo explicitly asks himself this question, examines some of the most powerful cases with which he has been associated, and concludes: “I emphasize, however, that in a very few situations, active euthanasia will be a caring thing for doctors to do.”Google ScholarSee his: Is euthanasia a caring thing to do? J Palliative Care. 1988;4(1–2):111–4 (quote from 113–4).Google ScholarBy contrast, MacKinnon, Kenneth considers active euthanasia a cop-out. See his: Active euthanasia: a “cop-out”? J Palliative Care. 1988;4(1–2):110.Google Scholar

33. Wanzer, SH, Federman, DD, Adelstein, SJ, et al. The physician's responsibility toward hopelessly ill patients. N Engl J Med. 1989;320(13):844–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

34. See note 19. Thomasma, Graber. 1990:190201.Google Scholar

35. Kelsey, M.Afterlife: the other side of dying. New York: Crossroad; 1979:115–8.Google Scholar

36. Biallas, L.Von Hügel's contribution to religious studies and to religion. Horizons. 1979 06 1:78ff.Google Scholar

37. Jung, C.Memories, dreams, reflections. Recorded and edited by Jaffé, Aniela. New York: Pantheon; 1963:302.Google Scholar

38. Landers, A.Nurse situation still critical, RNs report. Chicago Tribune. 1989 08 13;sect 5:3.Google Scholar

39. Engelhardt, HT Jr, Rie, M.Morality for the medical-industrial complex. N Engl J Med. 1989; 319:1086–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

40. Relman, A.Practicing medicine in the new business climate. N Engl J Med. 1987;316:1150–1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

41. Reade, JM, Ratzan, RM. Yellow professionalism: advertising by physicians in the yellow pages. N Engl J Med. 1987; 316: 1315–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

42. Loewy, EH.Obligations, community and suffering: problems of community seen in a new light. Bridges. 1990; 2: 116.Google Scholar

43. Drane, J.Becoming a good doctor: the place of character and virtue in medical ethics. Kansas City, Missouri: Sheed & Ward; 1988; 153–63.Google Scholar

44. Churchill, L.Rationing health care in America: perceptions and principles of justice. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press; 1987: 2042.Google Scholar

45. See note 44. Churchill. 1987: 20.Google Scholar

46. Kant, I.Foundations of the metaphysics of morals. Back, LW, tr. New York: Macmillan; 1986.Google Scholar

47. Aristotle. Nichomachean ethics. In: Barnes, J, ed. The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press; 1984: 17291867. (Bollingen Series LXXI.2).Google Scholar

48. Thomasma, D.The possibility of a normative medical ethics. J Med Philos. 1980;5:249–60.Google ScholarPubMed

49. Maclntyre, A.After virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press; 1984.Google Scholar

50. Thomasma, DC. The ethics of caring for vulnerable individuals. In: Reflections on ethics. Washington, D.C.: American Speech-Language-Hearing Association; 1990:3945.Google Scholar

51. Pellegrino, ED, Thomasma, DC.A philosophical basis of medical practice. New York: Oxford University Press; 1981:155–69.Google Scholar

52. Veatch, R.The foundations of justice. New York: Oxford University Press; 1986.Google Scholar

53. Goodin, RE.Protecting the vulnerable. Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1985.Google Scholar

54. See note 53. Goodin. 1985:45.Google Scholar

55. Trivers, RL.The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Q Rev Biol. 1971;46:3557.Google Scholar

56. Ridley, M, Dawkins, R.The natural selection of altruism. In: Rushton, R, Sorrentino, RM, eds. Altruism and helping behavior. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates; 1981:1939.Google Scholar

57. Singer, P.The expanding circle. Oxford: Clarendon Press; 1981.Google Scholar

58. Veatch, R.A theory of medical ethics. New York: Basic; 1981:386.Google Scholar

59. See note 53. Goodin. 1985:xi,42108.Google Scholar

60. Rawls, J.A theory of justice. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press; 1971.Google Scholar

61. Ozar, D.. The social obligations of health professionals. In: Monagle, J, Thomasma, D, eds. Medical ethics: a guide for health professionals. Rockville, Maryland: Aspen; 1988:271–83.Google Scholar