Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-19T15:43:48.823Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nobody’s Perfect: Moral Responsibility in Negligence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 February 2019

Get access

Abstract

Given the unwittingness of negligence, personal responsibility for negligent conduct is puzzling. After all, how is it that one is responsible for what one did not intend to do or was unaware that one was doing? How, therefore, is one’s agency involved with one’s negligence so as to ground one’s responsibility for it? Negligence is an unwitting failure in agency to meet a standard requiring conduct that falls within one’s competency. Accordingly, negligent conduct involves agency in that negligence is a manifestation of agency failure. Now, nobody’s perfect. Human agency is innately fallible, and a measure of agency failure is, therefore, unavoidable. The more one’s negligence manifests failure in one’s agency as an individual, the more one is responsible for it. In contrast, the more one’s negligence involves the shortcomings innate to all human agency the less responsible one becomes, because one’s agency as an individual is less and less involved in one’s failure. Determinative of the measure of individual and of human failings mixed into an instance of negligent phi-ing is the background quality of one’s agency at meeting one’s competency at phi-ing. That is, how able one is at delivering on what one is able to competently do. The more able, the less one’s occasional instances of negligence involve manifestations of failures of one’s agency as an individual—nobody’s perfect—and are more manifestations of one’s agency’s innate human fallibility, making one less and less responsible for one’s negligence.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

For written notes on previous drafts I am grateful to Antony Duff, David Enoch, Anna Finkelstern, Alon Harel, Miguel Herstein, Uri D Leibowitz, Ofer Malcai, Re’em Segev, Sandy Steel, and a reviewer for the CJLJ. I am also grateful for the helpful comments of the participants of the workshop on Negligence, Omissions and Responsibility: Reflecting on Philosophy of Action (University of Birmingham, 2016); UK Analytic Legal and Political Philosophy Conference (University of Manchester, 2016), and the research group on Legitimization of Modern Criminal Law Research Group (Hebrew University Centre for Advanced Studies, 2016).

References

1. For such approaches to responsibility, see Fischer, John M & Ravizza, Mark, Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility (Cambridge University Press, 1998);CrossRefGoogle Scholar Victor Tadros, Criminal Responsibility (Oxford University Press, 2007)

2. Hart, HLA, Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford University Press, 1968) at 154-55, 227-30.Google Scholar A view further developed and extrapolated on by, for example, Tadros, supra note 1 at 227-51 Joseph, Raz, From Normativity to Responsibility (Oxford University Press, 2011) at 55-57, 138.Google Scholar

3. Antony, Duff, “Legal and Moral Responsibility” (2009) 4:6 Philosophy Compass 978.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4. Smith, Holly M, “Non-Tracing Cases of Culpable Ignorance” (2011) 5:2 Crim & Philosophy 115 at 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5. This third category often—although not necessarily—overlaps with one of the previous two.

6. For more on the puzzle of responsibility in negligence, see Herstein, Ori J, “Responsibility in Negligence: Why the Duty of Care is Not a Duty ‘To Try’” (2010) 23:2 Can JL & Jur 403;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Zimmerman, Michael J, “Moral Responsibility and Ignorance” (1997) 107:3 Ethics 410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7. Coleman, Jules L, Risks and Wrongs (Cambridge University Press, 1992) at 217-20;Google Scholar Honoré, Tony, “The Morality of Tort Law—Questions and Answers” in Owen, DG, ed, Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (Clarendon Press, 1995) 73;Google Scholar Rosen, Gideon, “Culpability and Ignorance” (2003) 103 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 61;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Finkelstein, Claire O, “Responsibility for Unintended Consequences” (2005) 2 Ohio State Crim LJ 578;Google Scholar Alexander, Larry & Ferzan, Kimberly, “Against Negligence Liability” in Robinson, P & Ferzan, K, eds, Criminal Law Conversations (Oxford University Press, 2009) 273-80;Google Scholar King, Matt, “The Problem with Negligence” (2009) 35 Soc Theory and Practice 577;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Hurd, Heidi M, “Finding No Fault with Negligence” in Oberdiek, John, ed, Philosophical Foundations of the Law of Torts (Oxford University Press, 2014) 387.Google Scholar

8. Hart, supra note 2 at 147-52 Ayer, AJ, Philosophical Essays (Macmillan, 1954) at 27;Google Scholar Fletcher, George, “The Theory of Criminal Negligence: A Comparative Analysis” (1971) 119:3 U Pa L Rev 401CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Duff, Anthony, Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law (Hart, 2007) at 71;Google Scholar Gardner, John, “The Purity and Priority of Private Law” (1996) 46:3 UTLJ 459CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gardner, John, “Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts” in Cane, Peter & Gardner, John, eds, Relating to Responsibility: Essays for Tony Honoré on His 80th Birthday (Hart, 2001) 111.Google Scholar

9. Legal negligence is typically not conditioned on competency. SeeVaughan v Menlove, [1837] 132 ER 490.

10. Raz, supra note 2 at 243-51; Herstein, Ori J, “Responsibility in Negligence: Discussion of From Normativity to Responsibility” (2013) 8:1 Jerusalem Rev Legal Studies 167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11. A “layup” is considered the easiest shot in the game of basketball.

12. Raz, supra note 2 at 227-50.

13. On the historicity of agency and responsibility, see Fischer & Ravizza, supra note 1 at 194-201; Scanlon, Thomas, What We Owe To Each Other (Harvard University Press, 1998) at 278-79;Google Scholar Tadros, supra note 1 at 140-42; McKenna, Michael, “A Modest Historical Theory of Moral Responsibility” (2016) 20:1 J Ethics 83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14. Williams, Bernard, “Moral Luck” in Statman, D, ed, Moral Luck (State University of New York Press, 1993) 35.Google Scholar

15. On victim resentment, see Heyd, David, “Resentment and Reconciliation: Alternative Responses to Historical Evil” in Gosseries, A & Meyer, LH, eds, Justice in Time (Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar

16. On the “lottery paradox”, see Henry, Kyburg, Probability and the Logic of Rational Belief (Wesleyan University Press, 1961).Google Scholar

17. On the “preface paradox” see Makinson, DC, “The Paradox of the Preface” (1965) 25:6 Analysis 205-07.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18. I say reasonably “foreseeable” because one is obviously not responsible for all the outcomes of one’s conduct.

19. See Dobbs, Dan B, The Law of Torts, vol 1 (Westgroup, 2000) at 493-550;Google Scholar Restatement (second) Torts § 283 (1965). For a case involving an epileptic seizure while driving, see People v Decina, 138 NE (2d) 799 (1956).

20. See, e.g., Fischer, John M & Tognazzini, Neal A, “The Truth About Tracing” (2009) 43:3 Nous 531; Zimmerman, supra note 6.Google Scholar

21. On the distinction between attributionism and volitionism see, e.g., Smith, supra note 4.

22. See, e.g., Scanlon, supra note 13 at 268-69 Smith, Angela M, “Responsibility for Attitudes: Activity and Passivity in Mental Life” (2005) 115:2 Ethics 236;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Sher, George, “Out of Control” (2006) 116:2 Ethics 285;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Tadros, supra note 1; Hieronymi, Pamela, “Responsibility for Believing” (2008) 161:3 Synthese at 357;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Smith, Angela, “Control, Responsibility and Moral Assessment” (2008) 138:3 Philosophical Studies 367;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Smith, ibid.