Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-7drxs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-25T01:03:22.258Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On (Not) Living the Good Life: Reflections on Oppression, Virtue, and Flourishing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Extract

In this article I attempt to untangle the purported connection between moral virtue and flourishing in the context of examining what looks like an unexpected effect of oppression: If moral virtue is necessary for flourishing—as Aristotle assumes that it is when he describes eudaimonia as an “activity of the soul in accordance with virtue” — then members of structurally privileged groups can only flourish if they are morally good. However, it is hard to conceive of the privileged as morally good, since their privileges result from unjust social positionings. Thus it appears that they are prevented from leading good lives. This is an odd claim to add to a theory of oppression, which one would expect to explain how the victims of oppression — rather than its beneficiaries — are denied a shot at the good life.

While the privileged may enjoy especially ample opportunities to develop certain virtues, I will be thinking here about vices associated with practices of domination, including active or passive acceptance of the benefits that come from occupying positionings that depend upon systems of male dominance, white supremacy, class divisions under capitalism, norms of heterosexuality, and so on.

Type
I. Virtue Theory: Challenges and Developments
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Some passages in the first two sections of this article borrow from a short piece entitled “Do the Wicked Flourish? Virtue Ethics and Unjust Social Privilege,” which I published in the American Philosophical Association Newsletter on Feminism and Philosophy 1 (2002): 5963.Google Scholar

2 Aristotle, , Nicomachean Ethics, trans.Google ScholarW. D., Ross, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard, McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 1098a17.Google Scholar

3 Claudia Card (The Unnatural Lottery: Character and Moral Luck [Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1996]) argues that the moral luck arising from conditions of oppression may make certain virtues easier for beneficiaries of oppression - and harder for the oppressed - to develop. For instance, she points out that the virtue of “liberality” is generally not available to those without means to carry it out (4). She also recognizes, though, that privileged people are likely to develop certain vices (seep. 53). (On liberality, notice that Aristotle does permit the poor to be called liberal: “There is … nothing to prevent the man who gives less from being the more liberal man, if he has less to give” [NE 1120b9-10]; however, the larger-scale getting-and-spending virtue, magnificence, is a virtue that is unattainable by the poor: “a poor man cannot be magnificent, since he has not the means with which to spend large sums fittingly; and he who tries is a fool, since he spends beyond what can be expected of him and what is proper, but it is right expenditure that is virtuous” [NE 1122b27-29]).

4 For instance, Rosalind Hursthouse (On Virtue Ethics [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999]), in the context of considering the relevance of the point that it is difficult to convince the “wicked or the moral sceptic that the virtues benefit their possessor,” makes the following remark: “Few of us (by which I mean myself and you, my readers) are likely to be steeped in vice or to be genuine moral sceptics. Thereby we believe many things we know we couldn't convince them of, but we do not reject those beliefs as implausible just because of that” (17 4--75, emphasis added). Within the virtue ethics tradition, an exception to the tendency to portray vice as uncommon is found in John Kekes’ The Reflexivity of Evil,” in Virtue and Vice, ed. E., Frankel Paul, F., Miller Jr., and J., Paul (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)Google Scholar (though he is motivated in his claims by quite different concerns than I am); outside of the neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics tradition, see Judith Shklar's Ordinary Vices (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984) for a discussion of the significance (especially for liberal tolerance) of “ordinary vices.“

5 See Lisa, Tessman, “Moral Luck in the Politics of Personal Transformation,” Social Theory and Practice 26 (2000): 121;Google Scholar and Critical Virtue Ethics: Understanding Oppression as Morally Damaging,” in Feminists Doing Ethics, ed. P., DesAutels and J., Waugh (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2001).Google Scholar

6 For a sustained discussion of moral damage under conditions of oppression, see Card, The Unnatural Lottery (especially the first section of chapter three, for a consideration of how women may be morally damaged); I have relied heavily on Card's work in developing my own analysis of moral damage. For an argument against portraying the oppressed as morally damaged, see Margaret Urban, Walker, Moral Understandings: A Feminist Study in Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1998), 123-25;Google Scholar also see Daryl Michael, Scott, Contempt and Pity: Social Policy and the Image of the Damaged Black Psyche, 18801996 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1997).Google Scholar I extensively consider the question of whether and in what ways it is problematic to associate moral damage with oppression in “Critical Virtue Ethics.“

7 See Aristotle, NE 1099a31-b8 and 1101a14-16, and Aristotle, Rhetoric, trans. W. Rhys Roberts, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. J. Barnes (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), 1360b20--30. Of course, not all virtue theorists agree with Aristotle's position on this; the Stoics, for instance, present virtue as sufficient for flourishing.

8 See Julia Annas, “Virtue and Eudaimonism,” in Virtue and Vice, op. cit., for an interesting discussion of the relation between virtue and eudaimonia and on the differences between the Ancient Greek conception of eudaimonia and the modem conception of happiness.

9 In “Do the Wicked Flourish?” I also discuss Plato's portrayal of Socrates’ disagreement with Thrasymachus in Book I of the Republic, where the dialogue focuses on whether the unjust or the just man is happy.

10 Aristotle, Politics, trans. B., Jowett, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, 1253a2.Google Scholar

11 Aristotle, Eudemian Ethics, trans. J., Solomon, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, 1245b9-ll.Google Scholar

12 There is of course much debate over whether Aristotle believes that the very best life is the contemplative life, which he portrays as a life of solitary contemplation (See NE Book X, ch. 7-8). I will not enter into that debate here.

13 The key text to see for a full discussion of the differences between the Ancient Greek context and the modern context that are relevant for virtue and flourishing is Alasdair, Macintyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981).Google Scholar Macintyre also makes important distinctions within an Ancient Greek context, for instance, between a Homeric and an Aristotelian world. Because I am not developing any detailed account of Ancient Greek flourishing here, I am only noting some differences between Ancient Greek and modern/post-modem understandings of the relationship between virtue and happiness.

14 See Aristotle, NE, Book III, ch. 4, where he notes that some people aim not at the real good, but at an apparent good, usually because they mistakenly confuse the pleasurable and the good.

15 This fact has led some feminists to critique communitarian thinking. See Marilyn, Friedman, “Feminism and Modern Friendship: Dislocating the Community,” Ethics 99 (1989): 275-90.Google Scholar

16 See John Rawls’ concept of political liberalism that attempts to balance an overlapping consensus in the political realm with individuals’ or groups’ privately held comprehensive doctrines. (John, Rawls, Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993/96]Google Scholar, and John, Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. E., Kelly [Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2001].)Google Scholar

17 Very clear examples of this are L. W., Sumner, “Is Virtue its Own Reward?” in Virtue and Vice, op. cit., which I analyze below, and Brad, Hooker, “Does Moral Virtue Constitute a Benefit to the Agent?” in How Should One Live?, ed. R., Crisp (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996).Google Scholar (Hooker distinguishes between asking whether moral virtue is instrumentally beneficial to an agent, and whether it is constitutively beneficial; nevertheless, he is still concerned with benefits to a selfinterested individual.) Also see Julia Driver, “The Virtues and Human Nature,” and Gabriele Taylor, “Deadly Vices,” both in How Should One Live?, and (for somewhat of a contrast) Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (ch. 8). D. z. Phillips, in “Does it Pay to be Good?” (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 65: 45∼0), is critical of the approach of asking whether justice (or any virtue) is beneficial or profitable, given the reliance of this approach on using non-moral justifications of moral claims; his critique focuses on the argument given by Philippa, Foot in “Moral Beliefs” [1959], in Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978).Google Scholar

18 L. W. Sumner, “Is Virtue its Own Reward?”, 21. Italics in the original.

19 Ibid., 30.

20 Ibid., 34.

21 For instance, as Iris Marion Young has pointed out in Inclusion and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), residential racial segregation prevents those who live in predominantly white neighborhoods from perceiving in any detailed way how their quality of life differs from that of the residents of predominantly black or Latino neighborhoods. Young writes: “the very same process that produces … relations of privilege … obscures that privilege from those who have it. In order to see themselves as privileged, the white people who live in more pleasant neighbourhoods must be able to compare their environment with others. But this comparison is rarely forced upon them because those excluded from access to the resources and benefits they themselves have are spatially separated and out of sight” (208).

22 For a critique of the use of the concept of epistemic privilege, see Bat-Ami, Bar On, “Marginality and Epistemic Privilege,” in Feminist Epistemologies, ed. L., Alcoff and E., Potter (New York: Routledge,1993).Google Scholar

23 For a clear statement of the distinction between self-regarding and other-regarding virtues, see Georg Henrik Von, Wright, The Varieties of Goodness (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963)Google Scholar: “One way of marking the distinction between [self-regarding and other-regarding virtues] is to say that self-regarding virtues essentially serve the welfare of the agent himself, who possesses and practices them, whereas other-regarding virtues essentially serve the good of other beings” (153). Also see Philippa Foot, who remarks briefly on the distinction in “Virtues and Vices” (in Virtues and Vices) by noting that, while virtues are beneficial, “we must ask to whom the benefit goes, whether to the one who has the virtue or rather to those who have to do with him?” (3), perhaps picking up on her own consideration of the issue in “Moral Beliefs,” where she addresses the apparent problem that “while prudence, courage and temperance are qualities which benefit the man who has them, justice seems rather to benefit others, and to work to the disadvantage of the just man himself” (125); here she is able to answer that justice is beneficial to the agent precisely because of humans’ equality and interdependence (pointing out that “if a man only needed other men as he needs household objects, and if men could be manipulated like household objects, or beaten into a reliable submission like donkeys, the case would be different” [129]), but she is not led to reject the distinction between self-regarding and other-regarding virtues altogether.

24 Plato, however, does question this connection: otherwise, there would be no Thrasymachus. This makes it clear that the question was quite thinkable within the Ancient Greek context, and that answering the question the way Plato ultimately does -by arguing that a trait such as “justice,” which seems to benefit others actually benefits oneself- required defense. See David, Brink, “Self-Love and Altruism” (Social Philosophy and Policy 14 [1997]: 122-57)Google Scholar, for a unique interpretation of how Plato (and Aristotle) cement the link between other-regarding virtues and an agents’ own well-being.

25 Obviously, ethical egoism is a theory that rejects the belief that self-concern is not moral. However, egoism is seldom seriously defended. As Kelly, Rogers points out in “Beyond Self and Other,” (Social Philosophy and Policy 14 [1997]: 120)Google Scholar, it might be because egoism violates the requirement that morality be about how one treats others that it is so implausible. Rogers argues for a rejection of the distinction between self-regarding and other-regarding virtues, commenting about the “self--other model,” that “on this view, an action has no moral worth unless it benefits others- and not even then, unless it is motivated by altruism rather than selfishness” (1). Her focus is on critiquing the idea that morality is other-based. Jean Hampton has an interesting discussion of egoism in “The Wisdom of the Egoist: The Moral and Political Implications of Valuing the Self” (Social Philosophy and Policy 14 [1997]; 21–51). She rejects the view that self-concern is not moral, after having pointed out that the view that morality is limited to other-regarding concerns is something “that most contemporary moral philosophers take for granted” (21). She writes: “ … moral action and moral regard are taken to be other-regarding …. Self-interest is generally taken to be outside the province of the moral” (21). One of her points about egoism is that it can teach the lesson that “our own selves are valuable” (48). This has not been seen as morally significant to theorists who assume that agents believe in and promote their own self-worth. Hampton rightly remarks that “Probably because most philosophers have, up until now, been males from relatively privileged social positions- a background that encourages people to think well of themselves - there has been virtually no recognition of how difficult it can be for some people to believe in their own worth” (48).

26 B., Hooker, “Does Moral Virtue Constitute a Benefit to the Agent?142.Google Scholar

27 Ibid., 142f.

28 See Lisa Tessman, Critical Virtue Ethics, and D. M. Scott, Contempt and Pity.

29 Helen Leland, Witmer and Ruth, Kotinsky, eds., Personality in the Making: The Fact-finding Report of the Mid-Century White House Conference on Children and Youth (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1951), 4849Google Scholar; quoted in D. M., Scott, Contempt and Pity, 96Google Scholar. See also Kenneth, Clark, Prejudice and Your Child (Boston: Beacon Press, 1955).Google Scholar

30 See D. M., Scott, Contempt and Pity, 133-36.Google Scholar

31 For a classic feminist essay on this phenomenon, see Sandra Lee, Bartky, “On Psychological Oppression,” [1979] in Femininity and Domination (New York: Routledge, 1990)Google Scholar, who draws on Frantz, Fanon, Black Skin, White Masks (New York: Grove Press, 1967 [French, 1952]).Google Scholar

32 Thomas E., Hill Jr., “Servility and Self Respect,” The Monist 57 (1973): 87104, 88-89.Google Scholar

33 Ibid., 97.

34 Ibid., 98.

35 One could describe the beliefs typical of the servile person without using the language of rights. For instance, under an Aristotelian account, if justice entails distributing to each their due amount, then believing one should give oneself less than is appropriate is as problematic as the vice of giving oneself an unfairly large share.

36 For early essays on women's self-sacrifice and altruism, see Judith Farr, Tormey, “Exploitation, Oppression and Self-Sacrifice,” The Philoscrphical Forum 5 (1973-74): 206-21;Google Scholar and Larry, Blum, Marcia, Homiak, Judy, Housman, and Naomi, Scheman, “Altruism and Women's Oppression,” The Philosophical Forum 5 (1973-74): 222-47.Google Scholar

37 Notice that under slavery and to some extent under the pressures of a certain kind of paid labor (labor that while not fulfilling in itself meanwhile takes women away from their families), women are denied the affirmations offered by their potential role as nurturer in their families and are not compensated by being valued elsewhere.

38 See Nel, Noddings, Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984).Google Scholar

39 See, for instance, Sarah Lucia, Hoagland, Lesbian Ethics (Palo, Alto, CA: Institute of Lesbian Studies, 1988), ch. 2.Google Scholar

40 Of course, Aristotle does not consider this as a virtue, but this very fact probably reflects his elitism: it is not a typical virtue of leisured gentlemen.

41 See Elizabeth V., Spelman, “The Virtue of Feeling and the Feeling of VirtueM,” in Feminist Ethics, ed. C., Card (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas. 1991).Google Scholar

42 Wendy, Brown, States of Injury (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995), 70.Google Scholar

43 See Lynne, McFall, “What's Wrong with Bitterness?” (in Feminist Ethics) for a (qualified) defense of bitterness.Google Scholar

44 Hoagland, Lesbian Ethics, 85. Hoagland is drawing on Claudia Card, Virtues and Moral Luck, Series 1, Institute for Legal Studies, Working Papers, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Law School, November 1985.

45 Card, , The Unnatural Lottery, 53.Google Scholar

46 Aristotle does not recognize how one may exercise control or take vengeance from below (what did he think of Medea?) and wrongly asserts that “we feel comparatively little anger, or none at all, with those who are much our superiors in power” since “no one grows angry with a person on whom there is no prospect of taking vengeance” (Rhet. 1370b12-15).

47 See Kathleen, Wilkes, “The Good Man and the Good for Man in Aristotle's Ethics,” in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. A., Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980)Google Scholar: “The essential thing to realize is that Aristotle- and Plato- wrote in a time when the distinction between the moral (other-regarding) and prudential (self-regarding) virtues had not yet been framed, and, perhaps even more importantly, that they would have denied any reality or importance to the distinction had it been explicitly presented to them” (354). Wilkes’ point is partially that Aristotle (and Plato) did not equate moral virtues with otherregarding virtues, but she makes this point without noting and accounting for the fact that Aristotle does specially pick out some traits as other-regarding.

48 These are in addition to his discussions of friendship, which could also be used as Aristotelian sources for thinking about self- and other-regardingness. I am not focusing on friendship in part because concern for a friend is so clearly a limited kind of other-regarding concern, as a friend is very close to one's self (especially for Aristotle). See Julia, Annas’ discussion of Aristotle in her chapter on “Self-Concern and the Sources and Limits of Other-Concern” (ch. 12) in The Morality of Happiness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar, where she does focus on Aristotle's treatment of friendship.

49 A similar point is made by Nancy, Sherman in “The Virtues of Common Pursuit,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (1993): 277-99, 287.Google Scholar

50 I do not mean, here, to refer just to the virtues that are displayed in social intercourse (such as amiability or friendliness, sincerity or truthfulness, and wittiness), though these are social virtues too. See NE Book IV, ch. 6-8. See Sherman (“The Virtues of Common Pursuit” ) for a discussion of what she calls the “virtues of common pursuit”; Sherman also points out that many of Aristotle's virtues mix self-regarding and other-regarding aims, naming even those that appear to be most other-regarding (liberality, magnificence and magnanimity) as having self-regarding elements such as (in reference to liberality) “being a good steward of one's acquisitions and expenditures” and “not being negligent about what one materially requires for a non-depraved existence” (286).

51 One might argue for a different connection between other-regarding virtues and one's own eudaimonia under Aristotle's version of eudaimonism, a connection that does not emphasize (though is compatible with) Aristotle's assumptions of human sociality. William, Prior argues (in “Eudaimonism and Virtue,” The Journal of Value Inquiry 35 [2001]: 325-42)Google Scholar that “Reason is the crucial link between virtue and eudaimonia in Aristotle's theory … since a good life is essentially characterized by excellence in rational activity, every act that makes excellent use of reason, every virtuous act, contributes essentially to the good life of an agent” (330﹜. With respect to an other-regarding virtue such as justice, Prior observes that “in order to act justly, we must first determine rationally what justice requires. This use of our rational ability contributes intrinsically to our eudaimonia, and so benefits us. The phronimos, in reasoning out the demands of justice in a particular situation, contributes to his own eudaimonia” (331).

52 Pol., Book I, ch. 4--7, 12, 13; Book ill, ch. 5; 1280a32-34.

53 They can also be fairly indifferent towards far-away strangers in general, regardless of privilege. Notice that Aristotle's conception of interdependent community is based on a small polis, which is not only exclusive, but is also simply limited in size or population.

54 See Julia, Annas, “The Good Life and the Good Lives of Others,” Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (1992): 133-48Google Scholar, for a consideration of which of the ancient eudaimonistic theories might accommodate a wider-reaching other-concern than Aristotle's theory does.

55 I find Iris Young, Inclusion and Democracy, promising for addressing these questions.

56 Brink disagrees and contends in “Self-Love and Altruism” that “there are good eudaimonist reasons for recognizing a more inclusive common good than Aristotle does” (150). His argument rests on claims about “interpersonal self-extension” that he conceives as parallel to the continued personal identity of a single self through time; that is, one extends oneself by investing oneself in or contributing to the projects of others, no matter how distant those others may be. I do not find his argument to be convincing but will not argue the point here. See also David, Brink, “Rational Egoism, Self, and Others,” in Identity, Character, and Morality, ed. O., Flanagan and A., Rorty (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990).Google Scholar

57 I do not know the source of this slogan; I think of it as a bumper sticker.