Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-vt8vv Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-08-11T09:16:04.855Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Indexical Color Predicates: Truth Conditional Semantics vs. Truth Conditional Pragmatics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Lenny Clapp*
Affiliation:
Northern Illinois University, Zulauf Hall 918, Dekalb, IL60115, USA

Extract

Truth conditional semantics is the project of ‘determining a way of assigning truth conditions to sentences based on A) the extension of their constituents and B) their syntactic mode of combination’ (Rothschild and Segal, 2009). This research program has been subject to objections that take the form of underdetermination arguments, an influential instance of which is presented by Travis:

… consider the words ‘The leaf is green,’ speaking of a given leaf, and its condition at a given time, used so as to mean what they do mean in English. How many distinct things might be said in words with all that true of them? Many.… Suppose a Japanese maple leaf, turned brown, was painted green for a decoration. In sorting leaves by colour, one might truly call this one green. In describing leaves to help identify their species, it might, for all the paint, be false to call it that.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, J.L. (1952-3). ‘How to Talk.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.Google Scholar
Barker, C. (2002). ‘The Dynamics of Vagueness.Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 1-36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezuidenhout, A. (2002). ‘Truth Conditional Pragmatics.’ Philosophical Perspectives 16: 105-34.Google Scholar
Borg, E. (2004). Minimal Semantics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D.. (2003). ‘Color Realism and Color Science.Behavioral an Brain Sciences 26: 3-64.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cappelen, H. and Lepore, E.. (2005). Insensitive Semantics. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, J. (2004). ‘Color Properties and Color Ascriptions: A Relationalist Manifesto.The Philosophical Review 113: 451-506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1967). ‘Truth and Meaning.Synthese 17: 304-23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Egan, A. Hawthorne, J. and Weatherson, B.. (2005). ‘Epistemic Modals in Context.’ In Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning, and Truth, Preyer, G. and Peter, G. eds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Glanzberg, M. (2007). ‘Context, Content and Relativism.Philosophical Studies 136: 1-29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansen, N. (2011). ‘Color Adjectives and Radical Contextualism.Linguistics and Philosophy 34: 201-21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, C.L. (1988). Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1989). ‘Demonstratives.’ In Themes from Kaplan, Almog, J. Perry, J. and Wettstein, H. eds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kennedy, C. (2007). ‘Vagueness and Grammar: The Semantics of Relative and Absolute Gradable Adjectives.Linguistics and Philosophy 30: 1-45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, C. and McNally, L.. (2005). ‘Scale Structure and the Semantic Typology of Gradable Predicates. Language 81: 345-81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, C. and McNally, L. (2010). ‘Color, Context, and Compositionality.Synthese 174: 79-98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kölbel, M. (2002). Truth Without Objectivity. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larson, R. and Segal, G.. (1995). Knowledge of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1979). ‘Scorekeeping in the Language Game.Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 339-59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacFarlane, J. (2007). ‘Relativism and Disagreement.Philosophical Studies 132: 17-31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Predelli, S. (2005). ‘Painted Leaves, Context, and Semantic Analysis.Linguistics and Philosophy 28: 351-74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. (2004). Literal Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rothschild, D. and Segal, G.. (2009). ‘Indexical Predicates.Mind and Language 24: 467-93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, D. and Wilson, M.. (1986). Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. (2000). ‘Context and Logical Form.Linguistics and Philosophy 23: 391-434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sundell, T. (2011). ‘Disagreements About Taste.Philosophical Studies 155: 267-88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Syrett, K. Kennedy, C. and Lidz, J.. (2010). ‘Meaning and Context in Children's Understanding of Gradable Adjectives.Journal of Semantics 27: 1-35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szabó, Z. (2001). ‘Adjectives in Context.’ In Perspectives on Semantics, Pragmatics and Discourse: A Festschrift for Ferenc Kiefer, Kenesei, I. and Harnish, R.M. eds. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Travis, C. (1994). ‘On Constraints of Generality.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94: 165-88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Travis, C. (1997). ‘Pragmatics.’ In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Hale, B. and Wright, C. eds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar