Hostname: page-component-68945f75b7-gkscv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-05T11:15:27.872Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Natural History of Philosophy in Canada

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 April 2010

Thomas Mathien
Affiliation:
University of Toronto

Extract

Some writers about the history of philosophy in Canada have wondered why it should be studied. That is a worthy question, but it is not the one I want to discuss here. I am going to assume there are good reasons for doing so because I want to consider some general features of the subject of such studies and to determine what has to be done to establish certain descriptive claims about it. I will also point out some concerns I have about the proper explanation of certain interesting features of Canadian philosophic activity, and I will present a brief evaluation of one major study. I will do this with the aid of a contention that the study of the history of an intellectual discipline is a little like an evolutionary study of a biological species, but I will close by pointing out one reason for doing history which goes beyond description, and even explanation, of the past.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See, for example, the contributions of Fernand Duraont, “Le project d'une histoire de a l pensée québécoise”, and Brodeur, Jean-Paul, “A propos d'une question de Fernand Dumont”, in Panaccio, Claude and Quintin, Paul-André, eds., Philosophie an Québec (Montreal: Bellarmin, 1976)Google Scholar. The sharp distinction between Dumont's concern with the general question—Why study the history of any thought, particularly Quebec thought?—and Brodeur's rejection of the general question in favour of a more restricted concern—What reasons are there for studying the history of thought in Quebec? (49-53)—is worth noting. Another discussion of the reasons for studying the history of philosophy can be found in J. T. Stevenson's unpublished “On the Philosophy of the History of National Philosophy”.

2 There are people, however, who would deny that textual analysis is part of an historical discipline. See Graham, Gordon, “Can there be a History of Philosophy?”, History and Theory 21/1 (1982), 3752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 White, Morton, Foundations of Historical Knowledge (New York, NY: Harper & Row, 1965), chap. 6, 219270.Google Scholar

4 Cf. White on “Chronicles”, in ibid., 222-223. Being a feature of a central subject is here a necessary but, by no means, sufficient condition for relevance to the chronicle on which a narrative is built. The evaluation of one narrative as better history than another introduces other considerations as well. Cf. 225-227, and White's survey of evaluative principles applicable to the basic statements in the narrative, 238-266. Other different treatments of narrative less dependent on a principle of causal integration than White's may be found in Fain, Haskell, Between Philosophy and History (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), 256276Google Scholar, and in Gallie, W. B., Philosophy and the Historical Understanding (London: Chatto & Windus, 1964), 2271Google Scholar. For a discussion of forms of historical writing other than narratives, in the strict sense of that term, see White, Hayden, “The Question of Narrative in Contemporary Historical Theory”, History and Theory 23/1 (1984), 133, and especially 1-21CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Hull, David, “Central Subjects and Historical Narratives”, History and Theory 14/3 (1975), 253274CrossRefGoogle Scholar. I intend to exploit in this paper only the suggestion that intellectual history can be studied in a manner analogous to evolutionary studies in biology. I offer no opinions as to whether this is the only appropriate approach. Neither do I suggest here that biological species must be regarded as individuals. I am quite content that the approach upon which I am relying be one scientifically respectable one. Fora discussion on the treatment of species as individuals see Hull, David, “Are Species Really Individuals?”, Systematic Zoology 25 (1976), 174191CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hull, David, “A Matter of Individuality”, Philosophy of Science 45 (1978), 335360CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Ghiselin, Michael T., “A Radical Solution to the Species ProblemSystematic Zoology 23 (1975), 536544CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Hull, , “Central Subjects”, 259.Google Scholar

7 Ibid., 266.

8 Cf. Hull, David, Philosophy of Biological Science (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1974), pp. 6263Google Scholar, for his discussion of the founder principle.

9 Sparshott, Francis, “National Philosophy”, Dialogue 16/1 (1977), 321CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See 16-17forhis report of the response to his question of his colleagues about what “Canadian philosophy” was.

10 Some of Lucien Levy-Bruhl's works, especially on primitive mentality, are good examples of this.

11 On this see French, Stanley, “Considerations sur l'histoire et l'esprit de la philosophic au Québec”, Cité Libre 15/68 (1964), 2026Google Scholar. Reprinted in Lamonde, Yvan, ed., Historiographie de la philosophie au Quebec 1953-1970 (Montreal: Hurtubise, 1972), 147163Google Scholar. This feature of philosophy in Quebec has been well noted since at least Louis-Adolphe Pâquet's time. See his “Coup d'oeil sur l'histoire de l'enseignement philosophique canadien”, which first appeared in 1971 and is reprinted, 51-92, in Lamonde, Historiographie, and also Lamonde, Yvan, Philosophie et son enseigne-ment au Québec, 1965-1920 (Ville La Salle: Hurtubise, 1980)Google Scholar.

12 It did. A good example is the development of interest in social issues before the First World War. This is discussed in Lamonde, , Philosophie et son enseignement, 207Google Scholar, 227–234, in reference to the work of S.-A. Lortie.

13 On this see Racette, Jean, “La philosophie au Canada-francais”, Dialogue 3/3 (12 1964), 288298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 See Houde, Roland, Histoire et philosophie an Québec (Trois Rivieres: Editions du Bien Public, 1979), and “Biblio-Tableau”Google Scholar, in Quintin and Panaccio, eds., Philosophie au Québec.

15 Braybrooke, David, “The Philosophical Scene in Canada”, The Canadian Forum 53/636 (01 1974), 2934.Google Scholar

16 Armour, Leslie and Trott, Elizabeth, The Faces of Reason (Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1981), 26.Google Scholar

17 For Beaven, see The Faces of Reason, chap. 2. Forcommon sense, see the discussions of Lyall and Murray both of whom were influenced by the works of thinkers like Reid and Hamilton. Forthe idealists, the treatments of John Clark Murray (chap. 5), of John Watson (chaps. 7 and 8), and of George John Blewett (321-353) are especially worth consulting. Brett is discussed on 430-448 and Lodge on 405-422.

18 Armour, Leslie, The Idea of Canada (Ottawa: Steel Rail Press, 1981)Google Scholar. Lachance and John Watson are compared on issues of social philosophy in chap. 6 (77-91). De Koninck is discussed in chap. 8. See also 115f.

19 See Harris, Robin, A History of Higher Education in Canada 1663-1970 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1976)Google Scholar, for this. The relevant discussions are in the chapters on humanities teaching.

20 One might recall the excerpt from a letter of O. D. Skelton to Adam Shortt, cited in Berger, Carl R., The Writing of Canadian History (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1976), 49Google Scholar, to get an idea of one sort of response on the part of the educated public to philosophic concerns: “Strikes, trusts, taxes, socialism, tariffs (and) banking bulk a good deal larger in the public mind than the authenticity of John's Gospel or the wherefore of the shyness [sic] of Hegel.”

21 Mills, Judy and Dombra, Irene, University of Toronto Doctoral Theses (1897-1967) (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1968), 98108.Google Scholar

22 Cf. Sparshott, “National Philosophy”. This “school” has, it is worth noting, figured in a novel. See Hood, Hugh, Reservoir Ravine (Toronto: Oberon, 1974), and especially 31.Google Scholar

23 What is proposed here is an application of network analysis to the philosophic community. The informal use of it ca n be seen in Boissevain, Jeremy, Friends of Friends (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1974)Google Scholar. A more formal discussion of it can be had in Berkowitz, Steven, Structural Analysis (Toronto: Butterworth's, 1982). It ca n involve exploring links among philosophers as diverse a s those provided by. letter-writing, by shared institutional identifications, by responses to papers delivered, by shared use of common texts. It can also regard individuals as the means by which institutions are linkedCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Vogt, W. Paul, “Identifying Scholarly and Intellectual Communities: A Note on French Philosophy, 1900-1939”, History and Theory 21/2 (05 1982), 267276CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The reviews surveyed are the Revue philosopliiqne and the Revue de la métapliysique et de morale.

25 Cf. his “Biblio-tableau”, in Quintin and Panaccio, eds., Philosophic an Québec, and his Histoire et philosophic an Québec.

26 “Introduction anecdotique”, à une “Table-ronde sur le positivisme”, Bulletin de la Société de philosophic du Québec 6/1 (mars 1980), 74-81.

27 See White, Morton, Foundations, chap. 1 and 237f.Google Scholar

28 Brodeur, , “A propos d'une question”, 60.Google Scholar

29 Berger, , The Writing of Canadian History, 1317.Google Scholar

30 Armour, , The Idea oj Canada, 107108.Google Scholar