Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-11T11:15:20.664Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Weakening the Law of Excluded Middle

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 September 1966

Douglas Odegard
Affiliation:
Lakehead University, Port Arthur

Extract

Let us use ‘false’ and ‘not true’ (and cognates) in such a way that the latter expression covers the broader territory of the two; in other words, a statement's falsity implies its non-truth but not vice versa. For example, ‘John is ill’ cannot be false without being nontrue; but it can be non-true without being false, since it may not be true when ‘John is not ill’ is also not true, a situation we could describe by saying ‘It is neither the case that John is ill nor the case that John is not ill.’

Type
Discussions/Notes
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1966

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 This is consistent with allowing that for some statements falsity does mutually entail non-truth: e.g., molecular statements, the A-proposition of syllogistic logic under a Boolean interpretation.

2 Strictly, this should read ‘Any statement of the form “p v ∼ p” is true’, or ‘Any substitution-instance of “p v ∼ p” is true’, or ‘The statement-form “p v ∼ p” is a tautology.’

3 Since ∼ C (p v ∼ p), i.e., ∼ Cp · ∼ Cp.

4 Since ∼ C (Cp v ∼ Cp), i.e., ∼ CCp · ∼ C ∼ Cp.

5 I.e., ∼ p, or ∼ Cp, or ∼ CCp, or ∼ CCCp, and so on.

6 Since ∼ Cp.