Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-08T06:37:47.426Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Definitions of Man

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 July 2024

Extract

The interpretation of man which I have defended in my book, Theory of Man, agrees with the Linnaean designation of homo sapiens, which is more exact, in my opinion, than the classical one of “rational animal.” In that work I maintain that what is peculiar to man is that he is conscious of a reality outside of himself and of his own intimate being, or, in other words, that he recognizes the independent existence of the world and is an ego. Both matters can be reduced to a unique primary function: the objectifying activity, which in normal, continuous, and accumulative operation belongs only to man, and from which all essentially human traits are derived. The peculiar characteristic of perception properly so called, that is, human perception, is the observation of things that are present, the recognition that a given thing exists. To perceive, then, is to attribute presence or existence to what is perceived, to admit it as an object existing by itself, certainly in different ways according to whether it is a question of external things, of the subjective entity, or of the processes and “states” inherent in it; let it be noted that when perceptive attention fastens upon the “states,” that is to say, on subjective, unintentional processes like those of coenesthesia which ordinarily are not perceived but are lived, enjoyed, or suffered, these become objectified without losing in themselves their condition of states. The capacity to objectify is the bedrock of human nature; animal conscience (if it deserves this name) must be imagined, save for rare exceptions, to be a succession of “states” to which objectifying attention is not applied because such attention can only come from an ego.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1955 Fédération Internationale des Sociétés de Philosophie / International Federation of Philosophical Societies (FISP)

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Buber, Martin. Between Man and Man. Chap. V, “What Is Man?London: Kegan Paul, 1947.Google Scholar
Cassirer, E. An Essay on Man. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1944.Google Scholar
Groethuysen, B. Mensch und Charakter. Part I, Philosophische Anthropologie. Munich & Berlin: Oldenbourg, 1931.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huizinga, J. Homo ludens. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1949.Google Scholar
Korn, A. Obras completas. “La libertad creadora” and “Axiología.” Buenos Aires: Editorial Losada, 1949.Google Scholar
Lévy-Bruhl, L. Primitive Mentality. New York: Macmillan, 1923.Google Scholar
Marías, J. El tema del hombre. Madrid: Revista de Occidente, 1943.Google Scholar
Maybr, C. Man, Mind or Matter? Boston: Beacon Press, 1951.Google Scholar
Nicol, E. La idea del hombre. 1946.Google Scholar
Ortega, Y. Gasset, J. El Espectador de José Ortega y Gasset, “Vitalidad, alma, espíritu.” Madrid: V, 1926.Google Scholar
Gasset, J., Toward a Philosophy of History. New York: Norton, 1941.Google Scholar
Romero, F. Teoría del hombre. Buenos Aires: Losada, 1952.Google Scholar
Romero, F., Ubicación del hombre. Buenos Aires: Columbia, 1954. Brief account of the most important theses in philosophical anthropology.Google Scholar
Scheler, M. Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos. Munich: Nymphenburger Verlag, 1949.Google Scholar
Sombart, W. Vom Menschen. 1938.Google Scholar
Spranger, E. Lebensformen. Halle: Niemeyer, 1924.Google Scholar