Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-pfhbr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-14T04:31:35.992Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why ‘Law and Economics’ Is Not the Frankenstein Monster

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Samson Vermont
Affiliation:
The author is an attorney in Washington D.C.

Extract

In a published debate between Law and Economics avatar Judge Richard Posner and Professor Robin Malloy entitled ‘Is Law and Economics Moral?’, Malloy argued that the dominant methodology of Law and Economics (Posner's Chicago-style wealth maximization) is immoral. Malloy likened it to the Frankenstein Monster – an unholy, undead abomination that can go berserk despite its ostensibly benign provenience. Malloy claimed that wealth maximization applied to social discourse ‘reduces people to an human existence to imaginary variables for calculation’.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Bentham, Jeremy, Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, in Chapter One of ‘On the Principle of Utility’, p. 4 (Macmillan, 1879)Google Scholar.

2 Usher, Dan, ‘The Value of Life for Decision Making in the Public Sector’, Ethics and Economics, p. 189, Paul, Ellen Frankel, Paul, Jeffrey and Miller, Fred D. Jr (eds.). (Basil Blackwell, 1985)Google Scholar.

3 ‘Law and Economics can be defined as the application of economic theory (primarily microeconomics and the basic concepts of welfare economics) to examine the formation, structure, processes, and economic impact of law and legal institutions. Mercuro, Nicholas and Medema, Steven, ‘Schools of Thought in Law and Economics: A Kuhnian Competition’, in Law and Economics: New and Critical Perspectives, p. 65 (1995), Malloy, Robin Paul and Braun, Christopher K. (eds.)Google Scholar. Law and Economics encompasses a series of topics ranging from microeconomics to game theory, sociology and jurisprudence. Harrison, Jeffrey L., Law and Economics in a Nut Shell, p. 5 (1995)Google Scholar. There are several styles of Law and Economics, but the original and defining approach is Chicago's neo-classical approach, which emphasizes price theory and is sometimes distinguished from all other components of law and economics by the rubric ‘the economic analysis of law’. See Malloy, Robin P., Law and Economics: A Comparative Approach to Theory and Practice, pp. 23 (1990)Google Scholar.

4 Debate: is Law and Economics moral?’ 24 Valparaiso L. Rev., 147 (1990)Google Scholar.

5 Schumacher, E. F., Small is Beautiful – Economics as if People Mattered, pp. 45–6 (1973)Google Scholar.

6 See, Frank, Robert H., Gilovich, Thomas, and Regan, Dennis T., ‘Does studying economics inhibit cooperation?7 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 159–71, no. 2 (Spring, 1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Carter, John and Irons, Michael, ‘Are economists different and if so why?5 Journal of Economic Perspectives 171–77, no. 2 (Spring, 1991)Google Scholar; Kahneman, Daniel, Knetsch, Jack, and Thaler, Richard, ‘Fairness and the assumptions of economies’, 59 Journal of Business, Part 2 (10 1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Marwell, Gerald and Ames, Ruth, ‘Economists free ride, does anyone else?: experiments on the provision of public goods, IV’, 15 Journal of Public Economics, 295310, no. 3 (06 1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Gazzaniga, Michael, Nature's Mind, p. 175 (Penguin, 1992)Google Scholar.

8 See Nozick, Robert, The Nature of Rationality, p. 62 (Princeton University Press, 1993)Google Scholar.

9 Avery Katz, ‘Positivism and the separation of Law and Economies’, page 6 of a working paper posted on the Web at file://ftp://ftp.ll.georgetown.edu/pub/papers/katz2.html (August 10,1995).

10 See Slovic, P. et al. , ‘Facts and Fears: Understanding Perceived Risk’, Societal Risk Assessment: How Safe is Safe Enough?, p. 181 (Plenum Press, 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Howard, Phillip K., The Death of Common Sense, pp. 47–8 (Random House, 1994)Google Scholar.

12 Such as cognitive dissonance, lack of self-control and the disproportionate aversion to loss as compared to attraction to equivalent gain. See generally Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel, ‘Rational choice and the framing of decisions’, 59, J. Bus.S., p. 251 (1986)Google Scholar; Ward Edwards and Detlof von Winterfeldt, ‘Cognitive Illusions and Their Implications for the Law’, – Scott, Robert E., ‘Error and rationality in individual decisionmaking’, 59, S. Cat. L. Rev., pp. 225 and 329 (1986)Google Scholar; Ellickson, Robert C., ‘Bringing culture and human frailty to rational actors: a critique of Law and Economies’, 65, Chi.-Kent L. Rev., p. 23 (1989)Google Scholar; Leff, Arthur, ‘Economic analysis of law: some realism about nominalism’, 60, Va. L.Rev., p. 451 (1974)Google Scholar; Sunstein, , ‘Legal interference with private preferences’, 53, U. Chi. L Rev., p. 1129 (1986)Google Scholar; Schelling, Thomas, ‘Self-command in practice, in policy, and in the theory of rational choice’, 74, Am. Econ. Rev. Papers & Proc, p. 1 (1984)Google Scholar; Thaler, R. & Shefrin, , ‘An economic theory of self-control’, 89, J. Pol. Econ., p. 392 (1981)Google Scholar; Piatelli-Palmarini, Massimo, Inevitable Illusions: How Mistakes of Reason Rule Our Minds (Wiley & Sons, 1994)Google Scholar; Sutherland, Stuart, Irrationality: Why We Don't Think Straight (Rutgers University Press, 1992)Google Scholar; Allman, William F., The Stone Age Present (Simon & Schuster, 1994)Google Scholar; Schumaker, John F., Wings of Illusion: The Origin, Nature and Future of Paranormal Belief (Prometheus Books, 1990)Google Scholar; Klein, Daniel B., ‘If government is so villainous, how come government officials don't seem like villains?10, Economics and Philosophy, pp. 91106 (1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hardin, Russell, Morality Within the Limits of Reason (University of Chicago Press, 1988)Google Scholar.

13 Siskin, Bernard and Staller, Jerome, What are the Chances?: Risks, Odds and Likelihood in Everyday Life, p. 13 (Crown, 1989)Google Scholar.

14 Brown, Frederick Z., ‘Vietnam since the war’, The Wilson Quarterly, 66 (Winter, 1995)Google Scholar.

15 Cohen, Bernard L., ‘King Coal and the melt-down myth’, 12, National Review, p. 667 (06, 1981)Google Scholar. See also Raloff, J., ‘Study: reactor risks have been exaggerated’, Science News, p. 230 (04 3, 1982)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hellman, Caroline and Hellman, Richard, The competitive Economics of Nuclear and Coal Power (D.C. Heath and Company, 1983)Google Scholar; Imai, Ryukichi and Rowen, Henry S., Nuclear Energy and Nuclear Proliferation (Westview Press, 1980)Google Scholar; Rothman, Stanley, ‘Rothman's authority principle’, Society, 11 (03/04, 1984)Google Scholar.

16 Risk Versus Risk: Tradeoffs in Protecting Health and the Environment, Graham, John D. and Wiener, Jonathan B. (eds.). (Harvard University Press, 1995)Google Scholar.

17 A line from Bernadette Peters's character in Steve Martin's movie The Jerk, just after she finds out she is about to go from riches to rags.

18 See generally Mercuro, Nicholas and Medema, Steven, ‘Schools of Thought in Law and Economics: A Kuhnian Competition’. In Law and Economics: New and Critical Perspectives, Malloy, Robin Paul and Braun, Christopher K. (eds.). pp. 65123 (1995)Google Scholar.

19 Law and Economics: New and Critical Perspectives, pp. 14, Malloy, Robin Paul and Braun, Christopher K. (eds.). (Lang, 1995)Google Scholar.

20 Ibid, at pp. 2–3.

21 Ibid, at p. 3.

22 Hazlitt, Henry, Economics in One Lesson, p. 17 (Crown Trade, 1979)Google Scholar.

23 Ibid, at p. 191.

24 Landsburg, Steven E., The Armchair Economist, p. 4 (Free Press, 1993)Google Scholar. See also Friedman, David, Hidden Order: The Economics of Everyday Life (Harper Business, 1996)Google Scholar.