Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-t6hkb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T06:26:59.176Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Moral Critique of the Cosmopolitan Institutional Proposal

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2012

Extract

Preventive intervention, though an old practice, has recently come under widespread discussion due to concerns about international terrorism and the potential availability to rogue states or terrorists of weapons of mass destruction (WMD). With the 2003 war in Iraq, the Bush administration made preventive intervention part of United States military policy. In a recent issue of Ethics & International Affairs, Allen Buchanan and Robert Keohane argued that the preventive use of military force may be justified in some circumstances. In this essay I take issue with their argument.

Type
Debate: The Preventive Use of Force
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 This policy was set forth in 2002 in “The National Security Strategy of the United States of America” (September 2002); available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/nsc/nss.pdf. The Bush administration has referred to the policy as one of preemptive use of force, but, as many commentators have pointed out, it is instead preventive, since a use of force is preemptive only when the aggression to which it is a response is imminent. The preemptive/preventive distinction is discussed further belowGoogle Scholar.

2 Allen, Buchanan and Keohane, Robert O., “The Preventive Use of Force: A Cosmopolitan Institutional Proposal,” Ethics & International Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004), pp. 122 . All in-text citation references are to this article.Google Scholar

3 Another kind of intervention is humanitarian intervention, where the purpose is not to avoid an attack on the intervener, but rather to avoid massive human rights violations against the citizens of the target of the intervention. I argue later that it is a mistake to treat these two forms of intervention as morally akin.Google Scholar

4 Humanitarian intervention would be an exception to this.Google Scholar

5 See last note.Google Scholar

6 On this point, see Luban, David, “Preventive War,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 32, no. 3 (2004), p. 227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Again, excepting cases of humanitarian intervention.Google Scholar

8 These two conditions are related. If the expected aggression has yet to be initiated, defensive force is generally not a last resort.Google Scholar

9 This also explains why someone engaging in self-defense is not permitted to harm an innocent third party. Though the third party is, like the attacker, not culpable for the attack, neither is she causally responsible for the harm inflicted by the attack. The claim that a defender is justified in defending against a nonculpable attacker is disputed, however. Jeff McMahan has argued that justified self-defense requires the moral responsibility of the attacker for the attack. See, e.g., his “Preventive War,” in Rodin, David and Sorabji, Richard, eds., The Ethics of War: Shared Problems in Different Traditions (Aldershot,, U.K. : Ashgate, forthcoming 2005).Google Scholar

10 The body the authors have in mind for the ex ante review of the intervention might, of course, over time evolve into a genuine judicial institution, but, given the length of time this would take, its prospect provides no legal cover for states now desiring to intervene.Google Scholar

11 McMahan, in “Preventive War,” makes this point, though on different grounds.Google Scholar

12 The authors might seek to justify preventive intervention in WMD cases by introducing into their account a feature like Michael Walzer's supreme emergency that permits an overriding of just war rules in cases where extreme harm is threatened. But Walzer's notion of supreme emergency applies at the jus in bello level, not at the jus ad bellum level where the authors need it, and the level of threatened harm constituting a supreme emergency for Walzer is much higher than the level of threatened harm in WMD cases. In addition, the adequacy of a moral theory of war that includes the notion of supreme emergency is a matter of controversy. For Walzer's discussion of supreme emergency, see Just and Unjust Wars (New York,: Basic Books, 1977), chs. 16 and 17.Google Scholar

13 See note 8 above.Google Scholar

14 See Luban, “Preventive War,” p. 214.Google Scholar