Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-jwnkl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-15T03:28:25.209Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Deconstructing the Conflict in Ukraine: The Relevance of International Law to Hybrid States and Wars

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

In Ukraine, spheres of political, military, and economic control are contested, non-transparent, and shifting. As the Ukrainian government lost control over the rebellious Eastern oblasts (regions) of the country, Russia denies its authority over various pro-Russian separatists and vigorously rejects any responsibility for the abuses by the unidentified “green men,” both before and after the annexation of Crimea. Even during the decades before this conflict, the rule of law in Ukraine was “thin” at best. Meaningful political control was sporadic and dispersed, often wielded by the mix of public, private, and other shady actors occupying the grey area between a functional and a dysfunctional state. If state actors never effectively took control over the events at the state-level during peaceful times, it is not surprising that it is more difficult once a “hot” conflict breaks out. It is not unreasonable to assume that Minsk agreements—signed in an effort to stop the hemorrhaging of the conflict—will not hold if the signatories do not effectively control the diverse public and private actors who possess the actual capacity to influence the dynamic on the ground. Before rendering any kind of juridical judgment, the complicated political and socioeconomic configuration of the conflict in Ukraine forces us to first confront a factual puzzle: Who and what influence the current situation? Which concrete actors really drive the conflict and what interests animate them?

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2015 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 See generally, Umut Özsu, Ukraine, International Law, and the Political Economy of Self-Determination, 16 German L.J. 434 (2015) (examining these in an exemplary manner). I thank Anne Orford for the methodological discussion that made this explicit in Turku April 27, 2015. See also Anne Orford, In Praise of Description, 25 Leiden J. Int'l L. 609-25 (2012).Google Scholar

2 Donna Haraway, Situated Knowledges; The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective, 14 Feminist Studs. 575, 592-93 (1988).Google Scholar

3 See, e.g., Korostelina, Karina, Constructing the Narratives of Identity and Power, Self-Imagination in a Young Ukrainian Nation 81 (2013).Google Scholar

4 See Oxford Pub. Int'l L., Debate Map: Ukraine Use of Force (2014), http://opil.ouplaw.com/page/ukraine-use-of-force-debate-map (last visited Aug. 3, 2014).Google Scholar

5 See Tierney, Steven, Sovereignty and Crimea: How Referendum Democracy Complicates Constituent Power in Multinational Societies, 16 German L.J. 523, 527–28, 536 (2015).Google Scholar

6 See OSCE (HCNM), Human Rights Assessment Mission in Ukraine 9 (May 12, 2014), http://www.osce.org/odihr/118476?download=true (“No increase in the manifestation of intolerance or escalation of violence against the Russian-speaking population was observed in the [visited] regions. …”); see also Brad R. Roth, The Virtues of Bright Lines: Self-Determination, Secession, and External Intervention, 16 German L.J. 384 (2015).Google Scholar

7 See Kellman, Barry, MH17 and the Missile Threat to Aviation, 18 ASIL Insights (2014), http://www.asil.org/insights/volume/18/issue/19/mh17-and-missile-threat-aviation (last visited June 15, 2015) (stating that the make/country of origin of the arms is not sufficient to prove state responsibility in the circumstances of the international arms trade and smuggling today).Google Scholar

8 See Posner, Eric, Russia's Military Intervention in Ukraine: International Law Implications, http://ericposner.com/russias-military-intervention-in-ukraine-international-law-implications/ (last visited Jan. 15, 2015) (associating irrelevance based on enforcement deficit critique on international law in Ukraine crisis).Google Scholar

9 Austin has been discussed by many as the progenitor of the idea that without efficient enforcement a system cannot be properly called legal. According to the command theory of law, international law could not be regarded as law at all. Austin was criticized by H.L.A. Hart, who also had reservations about the legal quality of international law. See, e.g., Mehrdad Payandeh, The Concept of International Law in the Jurisprudence of H.L.A. Hart, 21 Eur. J. Int'l L. 967 § B (2010).Google Scholar

10 See Mamlyuk, Boris M., The Ukraine Crisis, Cold War II, and International Law, 16 German L.J. 479, 515 (2015) (unraveling the concept of Cold War and what its meaning structures entail in a precise and highly insightful discussion).Google Scholar

11 See Oxford Pub. Int'l L., supra note 4 (stating defenses of international law's significance).Google Scholar

12 See Kennedy, David, Of War and Law (2006) (noting that David Kennedy has thus been right to characterize modern war as lawfare).Google Scholar

13 See Mamlyuk, supra note 10 (demonstrating that one needs an analytical description on a larger scale, probing the deeper layers of the conflict, and, in more detail).Google Scholar

14 Kaldor, Mary, New and Old Wars: Organized Violence in Global Era (1999).Google Scholar

15 Korhonen, Outi & Gras, Jutta, International Governance in Post-Conflict Situations (2001).Google Scholar

16 Kennedy, supra note 12, at 5.Google Scholar

19 VPK News No. 8, Feb. 5, 2013, http://vpk-news.ru/sites/default/files/pdf/VPK_08_476.pdf (last visited June 15, 2015); Sam Jones, Ukraine: Russia's New Art of War, Financial Times, Aug. 28, 2014, http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/2/ea5ES2fa-2E0c-11e4-b760-00144feabdc0.html#axzz3QDUHEgwh (last visited June 15, 2015).Google Scholar

20 Hoffman, Frank, Hybrid Warfare and Challenges, 52 Joint Force Q., 34, 37 (2009). Western military strategists had also discussed new wars, asymmetry, compound strategies, and hybrid wars, particularly in reference to the Middle East.Google Scholar

21 The billiard-ball-theory of states as units is associated with the neo-Realism of Kenneth Waltz, in particular, in Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics 99 (1979); although the structural causes of conflict in the international system are part of Waltz's theory, the analysis here opposes the neo-realist take and posits that states should be understood as non-unitary actors with diffused rather than tightly shut borders and cultural spaces.Google Scholar

22 In the Western media, the hybridity was suppressed by making ominous references to the Franco-British appeasement policies and the traumas of the 1930s. Owen Wilson, David Cameron Warns of “Appeasing Putin Like Hitler,” Guardian, http://www.theguardian.com/politics/2014/sep/02/david-cameron-warns-appeasing-putin-ukraine-hitler (last visited Jan. 28, 2015) (criticizing the cynicisms of the comparison and refers to reports of off-record discussions both between EU Commission President Barroso and President Putin, and those among the Western leaders in the Nato summit in September 2014).Google Scholar

23 See, e.g., Georg Sarensen, States Are Not “Like Units”: Types of State and Forms of Anarchy in the Present International System, 6 J. Pol. Phil. 79, 79–81 (1998).Google Scholar

24 Id.; see also, Hoffman, supra note 20, at 37.Google Scholar

25 Id. Still, hybrid wars are not reducible to anarchy. While methods of such wars constantly transform through the reciprocal exploitation and fueling of the development of cutting edge technologies for war, Gerasimov traced the hybrid war mindset back to U.S. tactics in Desert Storm but also to partisans in World War II, and Soviet methods in Northern Caucasus and Afghanistan; whereas, Hoffman made comparisons even with certain battles in the American Civil War.Google Scholar

26 See, e.g., Gray, Colin, Strategy and History, Essays on Theory and Practice 185 (2006) (citing Clausewitz and Bull) (“War, its threat and actuality, is an instrument of policy.”).Google Scholar

27 Contrast Paulus, Andreas & Vashakmadze, Mindia, Asymmetrical War and the Notion of Armed Conflict—A Tentative Conceptualization, 91 Rev. Red Cross 95 (2009), with David Kilcullen, Out of the Mountains: The Coming Age of the Urban Guerrilla (2013), and Saskia Sassen, When the City Itself Becomes a Technology of War, 27 Theory, Culture & Soc'y 33 (2010).Google Scholar

28 Paulus & Vashakmadze, supra note 27, at 99–100.Google Scholar

29 For example, the actions of Palestinian suicide bombers are often juxtaposed to the vast technological superiority of the Israeli army; the conflicting units are different and, therefore, the tactics are also available.Google Scholar

30 See generally, Roth, Brad, The Virtues of Bright Lines: Self-Determination, Secession, and External Intervention, 16 German L.J. 384 (2015).Google Scholar

31 See Oklopcic, Zoran, The idea of Early-Conflict Constitution-Making: The Conflict in Ukraine Beyond Territorial Rights and Constitutional Paradoxes, 16 German L.J. 658, 670 (2015).Google Scholar

32 From that perspective, nations indeed present themselves as “imagined communities.” Anderson, Benedict, Imagined Communities; Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism (1982).Google Scholar

33 Wedel, Janine, Corruption and Organized Crime in Post-Communist States: New Ways of Manifesting Old Patterns, 7 Trends in Organized Crime 3, 4–5, 18 (2001).Google Scholar

34 Avioutskii, Viatcheslav, The Consolidation of Ukrainian Business Clans, 1 Revue Internationale Economique 119, 141 (2011).Google Scholar

36 Koskenniemi, Martti, International Law: Between Fragmentation and Constitutionalism, pt. 10 (2006), http://www.helsinki.fi/eci/Publications/Koskenniemi/MCanberra-06c.pdf.Google Scholar

36 See generally, Korhonen, Outi & Gras, Jutta, International Governance in Post-Conflict Situations (2001).Google Scholar

37 See Kaldor, Mary, Terry Lynn Karl & Yahia Said, Oil Wars (2007) (describing a theory of coincidence of a new war in the so-called petro-states, including Russia).Google Scholar

38 The territorial structure of Ukraine as prescribed in the Constitution of 1996 was influenced by the peculiarities of history and the constant contestation by Russia over Crimea and Sevastopol. Thus, article 133 provided that Ukraine is composed of 25 oblasts (provinces), one Autonomous Republic (Crimea), and two cities with special status (Sevastopol and Kiev). Despite Khrushchev's grant of Crimea to Ukraine, during Soviet times and beyond, Crimea and Sevastopol were also mentioned in the various Constitutions of the Soviet Union and, later, the Russian Federation.Google Scholar

39 Wedel, supra note 33, at 33.Google Scholar

40 Ironically, its clan structure made it appear more pluralist than, for example, Russia and Belarus. See Matuszak, Slawomir, The Oligarchic Democracy: The Influence of Business Groups on Ukrainian Politics 74, 78 (2012).Google Scholar

41 Wedel, supra note 33, at 33 (referring to Oleksandr Turchynov (1996)). On the exploits of the criminal networks, see references also in Helene Lavoix, Ukraine Crisis: State of Play—The Oligarchs, The Red (Team) Analysis Society (June 13, 2014), https://www.redanalysis.org/2014/06/13/ukraine-state-play-oligarchs/ (last visited Jan. 31, 2015). See also Matuszak, supra note 40.Google Scholar

42 See the arrow-pierced images of Ukraine business and political relations in, for example, Lavoix, supra note 41, and Avioutskii, supra note 34, at 119–41.Google Scholar

43 Avioutskii, supra note 34, at 120–21, 140–41.Google Scholar

44 Caveat: By taking these two oblasts (provinces/regions) and their groupings as examples I risk implying that they are the decisive forces of the conflict. Such implication is not intended. On the contrary, the choosing of these examples is not based on any sociological or political evidence of their superior significance vis-á-vis the various other regions and influence groupings around Ukraine.Google Scholar

45 Avioutskii, supra note 34.Google Scholar

46 Id. at 125-29; see also Lavoix, supra note 41.Google Scholar

47 Lavoix, supra note 41.Google Scholar

48 Avioutskii, supra note 34, at 118–19.Google Scholar

49 See Management, System Capital, http://www.scmholding.com/en/business/list/ (last visited June 1, 2015).Google Scholar

50 Id. at 126–29.Google Scholar

52 Press Release, System Capital Management, SCM's Profit-Maker (Oct. 28, 2011) (on file with the author). According to SCM it pays twice as high salaries as other companies. See id., Interview with CEO Oleg Popov, http://www.scmholding.com/en/media-centre/coverage/view/300/ (last visited Jan. 31, 2015).Google Scholar

53 See Avioutskii, supra note 34, at 127–29.Google Scholar

54 Id. at 139.Google Scholar

55 Id. at 138–39.Google Scholar

56 Matuszak, supra note 40, at 57.Google Scholar

57 Id. at 16.Google Scholar

58 Avioutskii, supra note 34, at 119–41.Google Scholar

59 Matuszak, supra note 40, at 16.Google Scholar

60 Id. at 19–20.Google Scholar

61 Id. at 21–22.Google Scholar

62 See Evraz: Making the World Stronger, http://www.evraz.com (last visited June 11, 2015).Google Scholar

63 Matusiak, supra note 40.Google Scholar

64 Lavoix, supra note 41.Google Scholar

65 See Olearchyk, Roman, Battle Rages in East Ukraine as Peace Talks Stall, Financial Times, Jan. 31, 2015, http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/966d0adc-a967-11e4-a28e-00144feab7de.htmlftaxzz3QWt0dpZw (last visited Feb. 1, 2015).Google Scholar

66 See Lavoix, supra note 41.Google Scholar

67 Id.; see also paragraphs on DF group and RosUkrEnergo, the Russian-Ukrainian joint venture in natural gas.Google Scholar

68 Donetsk, J.Y. & Enakievo, T.J., Rinat Akhmetov's Choice, Economist, (May 20, 2014), http://www.economist.com/blogs/easternapproaches/2014/05/ukraine.Google Scholar

69 Matuszak, supra note 40, at 30, 53, 78.Google Scholar

70 Lavoix, supra note 41.Google Scholar

71 Dunnet, Chris, Ukraine's ‘Battalions’ Army, Explained, Hromadske Int'l, (Sept. 17, 2014), https://medium.com/@Hromadske/ukraines-shadow-army-b04d7a683493 (last visited June. 15, 2015).Google Scholar

72 Arato, Andrew, International Role in State-Making in Ukraine: The Promise of a Two-State Constituent Process, 16 German L.J. 691 (2015).Google Scholar

73 Wedel, supra note 33, at 18.Google Scholar

74 Kennedy, David, The Dark Sides of Virtue: Reassessing International Humanitarianism 349 (2005).Google Scholar

75 Cf. Anghie, Antony, Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law (2004).Google Scholar

76 1 Lorimer, James, The Institutes of the Law of Nations: a Treatise of the Jural Relations of Separate Political Communities 103 (1883).Google Scholar

77 The Ukrainian Weekly, Dec. 22, 1996, No. 51. Vol. LXIV http://www.ukrweekly.com/old/archive/1996/519604.shtml (last visited Jan. 15, 2015).Google Scholar

81 Lorimer, James, The Institutes of the Law of Nations: a Treatise of the Jural Relations of Separate Political Communities 27–28 (1884).Google Scholar

82 Id. at 23.Google Scholar

81 For a cautious defense of transformative occupations and/or humanitarian interventions in failed states, (i.e. relativization of the non-intervention and non-interference rules) see Roberts, Adam, Transformative Military Occupation: Applying the Laws of War and Human Rights, 100 Am. J. Int'l L. 580 (2006).Google Scholar

84 Anghie, supra note 75.Google Scholar

85 Kennedy, supra note 74.Google Scholar

86 Danielsen, Dan, How Corporations Govern: Taking Corporate Power Seriously in Transnational Regulation and Governance, 42 Harv. Int'l L. J. 411, 412 (2005),Google Scholar

87 Lavoix, supra note 41.Google Scholar

88 Koskenniemi, supra note 35, pts. 5, 16.Google Scholar

89 Korhonen, Outi, International Law Situated: The Lawyer's Stance towards Culture, History and Community (2000).Google Scholar

90 In that regard, floating analysis echoes Kennedy's call for combining the principled commitment and the participation in the process of governance with pragmatism about consequences. See Kennedy, supra note 74, at 327–58.Google Scholar

91 Koskenniemi, supra note 35, pt. 18.Google Scholar

92 Id., pt. 26.Google Scholar

93 Id., pt. 29.Google Scholar

94 Such logic can, of course, be criticized as the re-introduction of the hermeneutic Horizontenverschmelzung ideal.Google Scholar

95 Kennedy, supra note 74, at xxvi.Google Scholar

96 Matuszak, supra note 40, at 59.Google Scholar

97 Id. at 15, 23–24, 43.Google Scholar

98 Id. at 19.Google Scholar

99 Interestingly, the Family is the relatively belated start to build a new oligarchic clan with a model that is actually based on blood relations in addition to the reliance of security police links.Google Scholar

100 See Introduction to Sakwa, Richard, Frontline Ukraine: Crisis in the Borderlands (2015).Google Scholar

101 Wedel, supra note 33.Google Scholar

102 Haraway, supra note 2, at 593.Google Scholar

103 Orford, Anne, Scientific Reason and the Discipline of international Law, 25 Eur. J. Int'l L. 369, 385 (2014).Google Scholar