Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m42fx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T13:40:38.418Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

European Exceptionalism? — A Response to Alexander Somek's The Cosmopolitan Constitution

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

A major contemporary shift in constitutionalism is manifest in that domestic constitutions, to an unprecedented degree, submit themselves to legal regimes and agencies beyond the state. This is epitomized in national courts taking into account foreign precedent within the system of the European Convention on Human Rights and the government of the Eurozone crisis by the executive apparatus of the European Union (EU). Alexander Somek's The Cosmopolitan Constitution is one of the most important monographs that endeavors to conceptualize this contemporary shift in constitutionalism. This response, however, highlights that the EU plays an uneasy role in the tale of The Cosmopolitan Constitution. The argument presented is that there are reasons to question the Eurocentrism that posits European post-WWII constitutional developments as the epitome of contemporary global constitutional developments. These reasons relate to the particularity of the European post-WWII political and constitutional experiences and developments. In contrast to what is maintained by Somek, this response argues that contemporary European trends in constitutionalism do not point in the direction of a universal cosmopolitanism but express a distinct European particularity.

Type
Book Review
Copyright
Copyright © 2018 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 See Somek, Alexander, The Cosmopolitan Constitution 179 (2014).Google Scholar

2 See id. at 17–18, 23, 179–80.Google Scholar

3 See id. at 1–2.Google Scholar

4 See id. at 1, 65–66, 79–80.Google Scholar

5 See id. at 92, 95, 109–10.Google Scholar

6 See id. at 16.Google Scholar

7 See id . at 16–17, 82–84.Google Scholar

8 See id. at 7–8, 16–17, 81–84, 106–07.Google Scholar

9 See id. at 1, 282.Google Scholar

10 See id. at vii.Google Scholar

11 See id. at 86.Google Scholar

12 Dani, Marco, Una traiettoria teorica del costituzionalismo modern, 4 Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 887, 890–91 (2017) (raising a similar critique).Google Scholar

13 Somek, supra note 1, at 9.Google Scholar

14 Ackerman, Bruce, We the People Ii: Transformations 279–311, 383–422 (1998).Google Scholar

15 See, e.g., Rossiter, Clinton, constitutional dictatorship: crisis government in the modern democracies 255–314 (1948).Google Scholar

16 Somek, supra note 1, at 17, 94–97; Carl Schmitt, Legality and Legitimacy 4–5, 8, 53 (Jeffrey Seitzer trans., 2004).Google Scholar

17 Somek, supra note 1, at 87.Google Scholar

18 Ackerman, Bruce, We The People I: Foundations 67, 75, 80, 83–85, 105 et seq. (1991); Ackerman, supra note 14, at 18, 25, 279–311, 383–422; see also Rossiter, supra note 15, at 211–314.Google Scholar

19 Somek, supra note 1, at 271.Google Scholar

20 Somek, Alexander, Replica, 4 Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 927, 927 (2017).Google Scholar

22 Kant, Immanuel, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795).Google Scholar

23 Habermas, Jürgen, The Crisis Of The European Union: A Response (Ciaran Cronin trans., 2012).Google Scholar

24 Itzcovich, Giulio, Libertà sociale e stato nazione: una relazione problematica, 4 Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 919, 923 (2017).Google Scholar

25 Bickerton, Christopher, European Integration: From Nation-States to Member States 12 (2012).Google Scholar

26 Id. at 13, 74–112.Google Scholar

27 Somek, supra note 1, at vii.Google Scholar

28 See Wilkinson, Michael A., Constitutional Pluralism: Chronicle of a Death Foretold? 23 Eur. L.J. 213 (2017); Michael A. Wilkinson, The Reconstitution of Postwar Europe, in Constitutionalism Beyond Liberalism 38 (Michael W. Dowdle & Michael A. Wilkinson eds., 2017).Google Scholar

29 Milward, Alan, The European Rescue Of The Nation-State 4 (1992).Google Scholar

30 Id. at 3.Google Scholar

31 Somek, supra note 1, at 84.Google Scholar

32 Id. at 1.Google Scholar

33 Id. at 78, 96. Somek stresses the passive nature of the constituent power in this shift. While this arguably is the case for Germany, it is not the case for many other states belonging to the ideal type of 2.0. On the contrary, many of the states belonging of the ideal type of 2.0 have been the most active and inclusive constitution making process. See Andrew Arato, Post Sovereign Constitution Making: Learning and Legitimacy (2016).Google Scholar

34 Grundgesetz [GG] [Basic Law] pmbl.Google Scholar

35 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], June 30, 2009, 2 BvE 2/08, para. 222 [hereinafter Judgement of June 30, 2009]. Google Scholar

36 Id. at para. 225.Google Scholar

37 Id. at paras. 219–25. With reference to the Italian Constitution, Andrea Gauzzarotti has raised a similar critique, see Andrea Guazzarotti, Rafforzare il costituzionalismo al di là della geopolitica, 4 RiVIsta Trimestrale di Diritto PubbLIco 907, 909 (2017).Google Scholar

38 Somek, supra note 1, at 10, 155–57.Google Scholar

39 Müller, Jan-Werner, Contesting Democracy: Political Ideas in Twentieth-Century Europe 148 (2013).Google Scholar

40 Müller, Jan-Werner, Beyond Militant Democracy?, 73 New Left Rev. 39, 43 (2012).Google Scholar

41 The main exceptions are arguably the Scandinavian countries and the United Kingdom, neither of which seem to fall within Somek's 2.0 ideal type.Google Scholar

42 Fursdon, Edward, The European Defence Community: A History 41–47, 64–5, 81–99 (1980).Google Scholar

43 See Syntagama [Syn.] [Constitution] art. 2(1) (Greece) (“Respect and protection of the value of the human being constitute the primary obligations of the State.”); Constitution of the Republic of Portugal, art. 1 (“Portugal is a sovereign Republic, based on the dignity of the human person and the will of the people, and committed to building a free and fair society that unites in solidarity.”); C.E., B.O.E. n. 1, Dec. 29, 1978 (Spain) (“The dignity of the person, the inviolable rights which are inherent, the free development of the personality, the respect for the law and for the rights of others are the foundation of political order and social peace.”).Google Scholar

44 Royo, Sebastián, Lessons from Spain and Portugal in the European Union After 20 Years, 26 Pôle Sud 1 (2007); Laurence Whitehead, Democracy by Convergence and Southern Europe: A Comparative Politics Perspective, in Encouraging Democracy: The International Context Of Regime Transition In Southern Europe 45–61 (Geoffrey Pridham ed., 1991); Dusan Sidjanski, Transition to Democracy and European Integration: The Role of Interest Groups in Southern Europe, in Encouraging Democracy: The International Context Of Regime Transition In Southern Europe 195–211 (Geoffrey Pridham ed., 1991); Geoffrey Pridham, The Politics of the European Community, Transnational Networks and Democratic Transition in Southern Europe, in Encouraging Democracy: The International Context Of Regime Transition In Southern Europe 212–245 (Geoffrey Pridham ed., 1991); Eirini Karamouzi, A Strategy for Greece: Democratization and European Integration, 1974-1975, in 90 Cahiers De la Méditerranée: Democratic Transition/Ardengo Soffici 1, 4–6, 8–9 (2015).Google Scholar

45 Sío-López, Cristina Blanco, Reconditioning the “Return to Europe”: The Influence of Spanish Accession in Shaping the EU's Eastern Enlargement Process, in The Crisis of EU Enlargement: Special Report 26 (2013).Google Scholar

46 Přibáň, Jiří, Legal Symbolism: On law, Time And European Identity 94 (2007); Marise Cremona, Introduction to The Enlargements Of The European Union 2 (Marise Cremona ed., 2003); Milada Anna Vachudova, Europe Undivided: Democracy, Leverage, and Integration After Communism (2005).Google Scholar

47 Přibáň, supra note 46, at 94.Google Scholar

48 Habermas, Jürgen, What Does Socialism Mean Today? The Rectifying Revolution and the Need for New Thinking on the Left, I/183 New Left Rev. 3 (1990).Google Scholar

49 Whether this was actually the case is irrelevant. The point is that the emergence of 2.0 was intrinsically linked to 3.0 in the constitutional imagination of these states.Google Scholar

50 With the notable exception of the UK and Scandinavia.Google Scholar

51 Somek, supra note 1, at 202.Google Scholar

52 Consolidated Version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union art. 21, May 9, 2008 O.J. (C 115) 47 [hereinafter TFEU].Google Scholar

53 Id. art. 18.Google Scholar

54 Somek, supra note 1, at 202.Google Scholar

55 Id. at 203–05, 260–61.Google Scholar

56 Id. at 205–10.Google Scholar

57 Schönberger, Christoph, Unionsbürger: Europas Föderales Bürgerrecht in Vergleichender Sicht (2005).Google Scholar

58 Schönberger, Christoph, Die Europäische Union als Bund, 129(1) Archiv des Offentlichen Rechts 113, 113–17 (2004); Christoph Schönberger, European Citizenship as Federal Citizenship, Some Citizenship Lessons of Comparative Federalism, 19(1) Eur. Rev. of Pub. L. 63, 68–69 (2007).Google Scholar

59 Schönberger, supra note 58, at 74–75.Google Scholar

60 Id. at 72.Google Scholar

61 Id. at 71, 74.Google Scholar

62 Edwards v. California, 314 U.S. 160 (1941).Google Scholar

63 Schönberger, supra note 58, at 71. See also Arthur E. Sutherland, Commerce, Transportation and Customs, in Studies in Federalism 297 (Carl J. Friedrich & Robert R. Bowie eds., 1954).Google Scholar

64 Schönberger, supra note 58, at 71.Google Scholar