Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-l4ctd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-18T02:24:36.720Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Sliding Towards Supranationalism? The Constitutional Status of EU Framework Decisions after Pupino

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The constitutional structure of the EU comprises two different components, one supranational (the European Community - EC) and one intergovernmental (the European Union). The EC is referred to as the first pillar, while the European Union in turn consists of two parts referred to as the second and third pillars respectively: the Common Foreign and Security Policy is the second, and the Police & Judicial Cooperation in Criminal Matters (the so called “area of Freedom, Security and Justice” - PJCC). The role of the common European institutions was from the outset more limited not just when it - which is logical - comes to legislation, but also when it comes to consultation and preparation of legislation. However, the ECJ retained jurisdiction to interpret the meaning of so called framework decisions in order to create a basis for uniform implementation in national law of such decisions. This was particularly true in relation to the Police and Judicial Cooperation in Criminal Matters. Whereas the European Court of Justice (ECJ) was granted jurisdiction in PJCC, the other community institutions, notably the European Commission, were given roles to supervise the implementation of framework decisions - but their role in enforcing uniformity was limited compared to the role of the community institutions in EC-law.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2007 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 Ulrich Everling, The Structure of the European Union, 29 Common Market Law Review 1074 (1992)Google Scholar

2 C-105/03 PupinoGoogle Scholar

3 Deirdre Curtin, A Europe of Bits and Pieces, 30 Common Market Law Review 17-63 (1993) Deirdre Curtin & Ige F Dekker, EU – a Layered International Organisation, in The Evolution of EU Law, 112-126 (Paul Craig & Gráinne de Búrca eds., 1999). Armin von Bogdandy, Gubernatives Rechtssetzung, (2000) 39-42, 488-496, Armin von Bogdandy, Supranationaler Föderalismus - Eine Neue Herrschaftsform (1999) 17-21, 44-50. Trevor C Hartley, International Law and the Law of the European Union, 72 British Yearbook of International Law 1, 3-10 (2001), Stefan Griller, EU – Ein staatsrechtliches Monstrum? in Europawissenschaften 201, 203-209 (Gunnar Folke Schuppert, Ingolf Pernice & Ulrich R Haltern eds. 2006)Google Scholar

4 Bruno de Witte, The Pillar Structure and the Nature of the European Union: Greek Temple or French Gothic Cathedral, in The European Union after Amsterdam – A Legal Analysis 51, 54 (Tom Heuekels et al eds., 1998)Google Scholar

5 Steve Peers, Who's Judging the Watchmen? The Judicial System of the “Area of Freedom Security and Justice 18 Yearbook of European Law 337, 343-348, 376-380 (1998). Eileen Denze, Intergovernmental Pillars of the European Union 265-267 (2001). Peter-Christian Müller-Graf, Die Europäische Zusammenarbeit in den Bereichen Justiz und Inneres (JIZ), in Festschrift für Ulrich Everling, vol. II 925, 932-934 (Gil Carlos Rodriguez Iglesias et al. eds., 2000). Pieter Jan Kuijper, The Evolution of the Third Pillar from Maastricht to the European Constitution: Institutional Aspects. 41 Common Market Law Review 609, 611-613 (2004).Google Scholar

6 Philipp Dann, Parlamente im Exekutivföderalismus (2004)Google Scholar

7 de Witte, supra note 4, 52-53Google Scholar

8 Mitchell Lasser, Judicial Deliberations 347-360 (2004)Google Scholar

9 Alan Dashwood, States in the European Union, 23 European Law Review 201, 206-209 (1998)Google Scholar

10 de Witte, supra note 4, 6263.Google Scholar

11 In the context of European integration this has been described as “functionalism,” which is a technically correct description of that European integration is based on delegation of national powers concerning particular governmental functions. However, the normative idea that underlies functionalism is the liberal view of public power, where law is thought of as separate from political will, both by its forms of institutionalisation and by its decision-making method. In that sense however, functionalism and more traditional understandings of separation of powers share basic pre-suppositions concerning the relation between political decision-making and corresponding political control of public powers on one hand, and legal control of public powers on the other. The difference between functionalist approaches and approaches based on separation of powers lies in the understanding of which kinds of institutions are necessary to accomplish such controls.Google Scholar

12 Bogdandy, Armin von, Bast, Jürgen & Arndt, Felix, Legal Instruments in European Union Law and their Reform: A Systematic Approach on an Empirical Basis 24 Yearbook of European Law 91, 108-111 (2005)Google Scholar

13 Id., 112-114Google Scholar

14 Id., 114-115Google Scholar

15 Elspeth Guild, The Constitutional Consequences of Lawmaking in the Third Pillar of the European Union, in Lawmaking in the European Union 65, 74-75 (Paul Craig & Carol Harlow eds., 1999)Google Scholar

16 However, that tension is far from always present; there are moments when it is in the institutional interest of the Council to adopt legislation that is directly effective rather than to adopt indirectly effective framework legislation since that can make the implementation of the legislation more expedient.Google Scholar

17 Marc Bungenberg, Art. 235 EGV Nach Maastricht (1999).Google Scholar

18 Panos Koutrakos, Is Article 297 EC a ‘reserve of sovereignty’?, 37 Common Market Law Review 1339-1362 (2000)Google Scholar

19 Lenaerts, Koen & Nuffel, Piet van, Constitutional Law of the European Union 53-54, 428-430 (2nd ed. 2005).Google Scholar

20 While that might be theoretically contestable in the sense that it is hard to point to any clear explanatory factor for a particular common “institutional interest” of the various national executives, it nevertheless is the assumption that such a common institutional interest of the national executives still make a lot of sense to the adopted policies, e.g. the tendency to use art. 308 of the EC-treaty and (to a lesser extent) framework decisions in an expansive way in order to avoid parliamentary oversight at both the national and the European level.Google Scholar

21 Maudro, Miguel Poiares, We The Court (1997). Rasmussen, Hjalte, On Law and Policy in the European Court of Justice (1986). Id., The European Court of Justice (1999)Google Scholar

22 The most obvious case of this is when the ECJ has applied principles of state-liability for nonimplementation of directives and regulations of states. Although the ECJ has enabled citizens of the member states of the EU to vindicate their rights against the states, it has not created legal protection in the form of injunctions, but has instead chosen to develop principles of compensation for damages. However, since EC-law has mainly concerned economic damages, it is also clear that the difference between allocating costs in that way and by way of more general injunctions is relatively limited. However, the ECJ does, in cases where it finds a member state to be in violation of its obligations under the treaties, apply a mix between enforcement through principles of damages and injunctions applied to states, which seems to parallel state-liability in public international law. C-26/62 van Gend en Loos E.C.R. [1963] 3, C-6/90 Francovich and Bonifaci E.C.R. [1992] I-5357, C-224/01 Köbler E.C.R. [2003] I-10239 and C-173/03 Traghetti del Mediterraneo (not yet reported) are all examples of how the ECJ has applied the principle of state-responsibility in relation to state action within the framework of EC-law in a way which treats judicial powers as a part of a dependent part, analogous to the treatment of domestic judicial power on state-liability under public international law. C-105/03 Maria Pupino can be seen as an example how the ECJ has used the same principle in the context of EU-law.Google Scholar

23 Acceto & Zleptnig argue that the principle of effectiveness is a central structural principle of EC-law, which has been illustrated in some recent cases where the court has extended the effects of legislation under the third pillars in the national legal orders. The normative reasons are based on a combination of that citizens are to be treated equally regardless of their nationality in relation to EC-law, and that the benefits from cooperation that arise from coordination will not come about if effectiveness is an overarching legal principle in deciding which forms implementation of the community decisions should take. The problem, from a normative perspective however, is that this presupposes that all forms of cooperation within the framework of the EU should be given equal effectiveness. The problem that Accetto & Zleptnig point to is that this presupposes that effectiveness is to be an overarching concern for some kind of normative reason, while disregarding reasons against regarding effectiveness as an overarching value. In relation to national law, that seems to be related to protection of fundamental rights and legal certainty and to some extent to the protection of political accountability within the national political system. The alternative approach that some authors argue is that the ECJ has embraced an element of proportionality review as opposed to an across the board principle of supremacy. However, in relation to recent case-law, it seems as if the ECJ has instead chosen to adopt a far more extensive understanding of effectiveness as an overarching constitutional principle. See Accetto, Matej & Zleptnig, Stefan, The Principle of Effectiveness: Rethinking Its Role in Community Law, 11 European Public Law 375, 379-383 (2005). Ross, Malcolm, Effectiveness in the European legal order(s): beyond supremacy to constitutional proportionality, 31 European Law Review 476, 483-488 (2006)Google Scholar

24 Wasielewski, Lukas, Differentiation in the System of Judicial Review in EU Law – the ECJ in a Differentiated Legal Order, in The Emerging Constitutional Law of the European Union 158 ff, 164-169 (Adam Bodnar et al. eds., 2003)Google Scholar

25 Tomuschat, Christian, Das Francovich-Urteil des EuGH – Ein Lehrstück zum Europarecht, in Festschrift für Ulrich Everling, vol. II 1585 (Gil Carlos Rodriguez Iglesias et al. eds., 2000)Google Scholar

26 Eeckhout, Piet, The European Court of Justice and the “Area of Freedom, Security and Justice”: Challenges and Problems, in Judicial Review in EU – Liber Amicorum Lord Slynn of Hadley vol. I 153-166, 159-161 (David O'Keeffe et al. eds. 2000). TEU Art. 35(6)Google Scholar

27 TEU Art. 35(2), 35(3)a-b, 35(4)Google Scholar

28 The argument of Levinson & Pildes is essentially that why political safeguards work rather through political parties than through institutions is that political parties represent people with different and sometimes changing preferences for how power is to be allocated among institutions. Levinson & Pildes assume that institutional choices are ultimately dependent on political preferences on substantive issues. That seems to be true when such preferences are channelled through a long-lasting organisational system such as parties that represent certain interests. In the context of legislative institutions without parties, it is clear that the argument depends on whether and to what extent such contingent preferences will influence the process of political decision-making. In certain contexts, such as the EU, it is obvious that the kind of influence based on representation of popular political opinion is mediated through a number of political institutions, nationally and internationally, with limited direct control of parties. On the other hand, the powers of the member states are still regarded as the source and as the final constraint on EU-law in the sense that the member states are the ultimate sources of authority of EC-law, and it is the states that ultimately decide on whether to retain EC-law as a part of their legal system. See Levinson, Daryl & Pildes, Richard H, Separation of parties, not of powers, 119 Harvard Law Review 2311 (2006). Kramer, Larry, Putting Politics Back in the Political Safeguards of Federalism, 100 Columbia Law Review 215-293 (2000)Google Scholar

29 Guild, , supra note 15, 83-84Google Scholar

30 Lysén, Göran, EU Framework Decisions (2005) 13-15Google Scholar

31 Hatje, Armin, Loyalität als Rechtsprinzip (2001) 36-38, 38-41Google Scholar

32 Lysén supra note 30, 38-49Google Scholar

33 C-8/81 Becker v Finanzamt Muenster-Innenstadt, E.C.R. [1982] 53Google Scholar

34 C-105/03 Maria Pupino, para. 22-26, 38-41, 45-46 (opinion of AG Kokott)Google Scholar

35 C-105/03 Maria Pupino, para. 37-48Google Scholar

36 Per Hallström, European Union Law – From reciprocity to loyalty, 39 Scandinavian Studies in Law 79 (1999)Google Scholar

37 C-105/03, Maria Pupino, para. 58-61Google Scholar

38 C-105/03 Maria Pupino, paras. 45-48Google Scholar

39 Tomuschat, supra note 25, 1608-1609Google Scholar

40 C-105/03 Maria Pupino, para. 41-43 and paras. 68-69 (opinion of AG Kokott)Google Scholar

41 Maria Fletcher, Extending “indirect effect” to the third pillar: the significance of Pupino? 30 European Law Review 862 (2005)Google Scholar

42 Case C-14/83 von Colson and Kamann, E.C.R. [1984] 26Google Scholar

43 Fletcher supra note 41, 871-872Google Scholar

44 Vassilios Skouris, “Rechtswirkungen von nicht umgesetzten EG-Richtlinien und EU-Rahmenbeschlüssen gegenüber Privaten – neuere Entwicklungen in der Rechtsprechung des EuGH“, Zeitschritft für Europarechtliche Studien 4-2005, 474-476Google Scholar

45 For a more traditional understanding of the role of precedents, see Schauer, Fredrick, Precedent, 39 Stanford Law Review, 571 (1986-1987), In the context of EC/EU-law, see Albors-Llorens, Albertina, Changes in the Jurisdiction of the European Court of Justice under the Treaty of Amsterdam, 35 Common Market Law Review, 1273 (1998), Arnull, Anthony, Owning up to Fallibility: Precedent and the Court of Justice, 30 Common Market Law Review, 247 (1993)Google Scholar

46 The ECJ notes in its decision that there is a duty to interpret national law to be in harmony with framework decisions. It is not obvious how far such an obligation goes and the ECJ does not define any general principle on that matter. However, it is notable that the ECJ did not reject the view that their interpretation would be contra legem in relation to Italian domestic law.Google Scholar

Constantinesco, Vlad, The ECJ as a Law-Maker: Praeter Aut Contra Legem, in Judicial Review in EU – Liber Amicorum Lord Slynn of Hadley, vol. I, 73 (David O'Keeffe ed., 2000)Google Scholar

47 von Bogdandy supra note 3, 39-55Google Scholar

48 One aspect that seems to be important in relation to unanimity requirements is that it provides for a certain minimal transparency to the decision-making process, namely that an unanimity requirement makes it clear that all changes were supported by all governments, unlike various forms of QMV-procedures that make it impossible for the citizens to know which government that took which position. In that respect, unanimity requirements enhances transparency and accountability, on the other hand, it only works to provide information in cases where there actually was a decision to change law, i.e. there is no possibility to account for non-decisions through the unanimity requirement.Google Scholar

49 C-6/64 Costa v. ENEL. E.C.R. [1964] 1251Google Scholar

50 Kumm, Mattias, Who is the final arbiter of constitutionality in Europe?, 36 Common Market Law Review 351 (1999)Google Scholar

51 Mayer, Franz C., Wer soll der Hüter der Europäische Verfassung Sein in Die Zukunft der Europäischen Union: Eine kritische Bilanz des Konvents, 429 (Olivier Beaud & Ingolf Pernice, eds., 2004)Google Scholar

52 One should however be clear about that the constitutionalization of EC/EU-law has mainly concerned the constitutionalization of certain competencies of the institutions, the remedies under EC-law and the jurisdiction of the ECJ. As has often been pointed out, it has been a development focused on functions, rather than attempting to make a claim of the powers of EC/EU stemming from a particular European “demos” or in any other way making a claim to some kind of inherent political legitimacy. However, in a similar way, domestic courts have often avoided according any final authority to EC/EU-decisions. Therefore, what has often been described as a constitutionalization of the EU seems to be a matter of cooperation and routinization of decision-making through customary practices and not of the creation of institutional hierarchies associated with the more traditional approach of constitutionsalization at the level of the nation-state.Google Scholar

53 In relation to the issue of the character of the EC/EU, it seems notable that there are two concurrent trends within the case law of the ECJ with regard to the relation between the member states and the EC/EU. One trend concern the increasing malleability of competencies of the EC, which is related to expansionist understandings of implied powers granted under art. 308 EC-treaty which concerns the extent of EC-powers, whereas in relation to the third pillar, it seems mainly to be a matter of effects of powers granted. However, these currents have in common that they both serve to amplify the institutional role of the Council at the expense of the national parliaments. In these both respects, it seems as if the effect has been enhancement of the role of national executives through the Council. In practice it seems to lead to that the role of the Council as legislator and the ECJ as arbiter of claims of constitutional validity are enhanced. For developments in EC-law, e.g. Carl Lebeck Article 308 EC-treaty: From a Democratic Deficit to a Constitutional Deficit? Europarättslig Tidskrift 231 (2007)Google Scholar

54 Nergelius, Joakim, “De-legalize it” - On Current Tendencies in EC Constitutional Law, 21 Ybk Euro. L. 443 (2002)Google Scholar

55 Stein, Eric A, International Integration and Democracy – No Love at First Sight, 95 Am. J. Int’ L. 489, 515-520 (2001)Google Scholar

56 Peters, Anne, The Constitutionalist Reconstruction of International Law: Pros and Cons, NCCR Trade Working Paper 11/2006, 10-11Google Scholar

57 Graínne de Búrca & Witte, Bruno de, The Delimitation of Powers Between the EU and its Member States, in Accountability and Legitimacy in the European Union, 201, 205-209 (Anthony Arnull & Daniel Wincott eds., 2002)Google Scholar

58 Coppel, Jason & O'Neill, Aidan, The European Court of Justice: Taking Rights Seriously?, 29 Common Market Law Review 669 (1992), and for a contrary opinion, see Weiler, Joseph H.H., Eurocracy and Distrust: Some Questions Concerning the Role of the European Court of Justice in the Protection of Fundamental Human Rights in the European Community, 61 Washington Law Review 1103 (1986), Weiler, Joseph H.H. & Lockhart, Nicolas, ‘Taking Rights Seriously’ Seriously: The European Court of Justice and its Fundamental Rights Jurisprudence - Part I, 32 Common Market Law Review 51 (1995)Google Scholar