Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-jwnkl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T21:32:16.708Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Subject in Hegel’s Absolute Idea

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 December 2018

Clinton Tolley*
Affiliation:
University of California, San Diego, USActolley@ucsd.edu
Get access

Abstract

There has been a tendency in some of the most influential recent interpretations of Hegel to downplay (or simply ignore) the theological characterizations that Hegel gives to the subject-matter of logic, and to emphasize, instead, certain continuities taken to exist between Hegel’s conception of logic and that of Kant. In the work of Robert Pippin and others, this has led to an ‘apperception’-oriented interpretation of Hegel’s logic, according to which Hegel follows Kant in taking logic to be primarily concerned with the nature of human self-conscious subjectivity. Here I put pressure on this interpretation—first, by foregrounding textual and systematic evidence for taking the theological characterizations to accurately convey Hegel’s considered position on logic, as the science of the ‘absolute idea’, and then, secondly, by showing how Hegel’s arguments for the absolute formality and universality of logic point instead to a more fully-fledged rejection of Kant’s conception as too specifically psychological.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© The Hegel Society of Great Britain, 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ameriks, K. (1985), ‘Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46:1: 135.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (1999), ‘Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel’s Idealism’, European Journal of Philosophy 7: 164189.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (2009), Reason in Philosophy. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bristow, W. (2007), Hegel and the Transformation of Philosophical Critique. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
de Boer, K. (2004), ‘The Dissolving Force of the Concept: Hegel’s Ontological Logic’, Review of Metaphysics 57: 787822.Google Scholar
Forster, M. (1998), Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Förster, E. (2000), ‘The Significance of §§76 and 77 of the Critique of Judgment for the Development of Post-Kantian Philosophy (Part 1)’, Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 30:2: 197217.Google Scholar
Förster, E. (2012), The Twenty-Five Years of Philosophy, trans. B. Bowman. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hardimon, M. (1994), Hegel’s Social Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jaeschke, W. (1986), Die Vernunft in der Religion. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.Google Scholar
Kreines, J. (2006), ‘Hegel’s Metaphysics: Changing the Debate’, Philosophy Compass 1:5: 466480.Google Scholar
Kreines, J. (2015), Reason in the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Longuenesse, B. (2000), ‘Point of View of Man or Knowledge of God: Kant and Hegel on Concept, Judgment and Reason’, in S. Sedgwick (ed.), The Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lumsden, S. (2008), ‘The Rise of the Non-Metaphysical Hegel’, Philosophy Compass, 3:1: 5165.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (2009), Having the World in View. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nuzzo, A. (2009), ‘Kritik der Urteilskraft §§76–7’, Kant Yearbook 1: 143172.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. (1994), Hegel’s Phenomenology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. (2000), Hegel: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. (2002), German Philosophy 1760–1860. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. (2012), Hegel’s Naturalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (1989), Hegel’s Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2008), Hegel’s Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2014a), ‘The Significance of Self-Consciousness in Idealist Theories of Logic’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114: 145–66.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2014b), After the Beautiful. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2017), ‘Hegel on Logic as Metaphysics’, in D. Moyar (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Hegel. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Plevrakis, E. (2017), Das Absolute und der Begriff. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Redding, P. (2007), ‘Hegel, Idealism, and God’, Cosmos and History 3.2–3: 1631.Google Scholar
Rosenkranz, K. (1858), Wissenschaft der logischen Idee: Erster Teil: Metaphysik. Königsberg: Bornträger.Google Scholar
Sedgwick, S. (2012), Hegel’s Critique of Kant. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. (1975), Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tolley, C. (2017a), ‘Hegel and Kant on Reason and the Unconditioned’, Hegel-Studien, 50: 131141.Google Scholar
Tolley, C. (2017b), ‘The Relation between Logic and Ontology in Kant’, International Yearbook for German Idealism 12: 7598.Google Scholar
Tolley, C. (2017c), ‘The Place of Cognition in the Progression of Representations’. Synthèse online: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1625-3.Google Scholar
Williams, R. (2017), Hegel on the Proofs and the Personhood of God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yeomans, C. (2012), Freedom and Reflection: Hegel and the Logic of Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zambrana, R. (2015), Hegel’s Theory of Intelligibility. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar