Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-vt8vv Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-08-13T17:07:33.688Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Contra Teleology: Hegel on Subjective and Objective Purpose

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 December 2022

Kevin Thompson*
Affiliation:
DePaul University, Chicago, USA
Get access

Abstract

Hegel's system is not teleological. For a philosophy to be teleological, as I shall use the term, means that it takes the basic nature of the world itself or any foundational account of that world to be defined ultimately by final causality. Such a view has, of course, long stood as the dominant model for interpreting Hegel's system. This essay argues, to the contrary, that the accounts of Teleology and Life in the Science of Logic, and more precisely their analyses of what Hegel calls there subjective purpose and objective purpose, actually demonstrate this conception of teleology to be profoundly mistaken.

The conventional reading of these sections is that they argue for two related claims: (1) that the means-ends relationship of extrinsic purposiveness—subjective purpose—is made possible by the intrinsic self-organizing process of intrinsic purposiveness; and (2) that intrinsic purposiveness—objective purpose—takes the basic structure of an organism, a natural purpose (Naturzweck), as its model, a model defined by final causality. I show this to be a deeply flawed interpretation. Hegel certainly shows that extrinsic purposiveness entails intrinsic purposiveness, but he does not conceive of intrinsic purposiveness, objective purpose, in terms of the final causality inherent in the model of a natural purpose. Rather, the systematic account of logical life argues that the activity of life must be understood as genus and this as a process of self-differentiation where the immanent and necessary unfolding of determinate negation itself, and itself alone, engenders the development without possessing or relating itself to any antecedent content. Hence, this austere thesis, rather than any form of final causality, is, as Hegel puts it, the truth of teleology, the nature of the absolute idea, and, as a result, Hegel's system is shown, at its very core, not to be teleological.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Hegel Society of Great Britain

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Biard, J., Buvat, D., Kervegan, J.-F., Kling, J.-F., Lacroix, A. and Lécrivain, A. (1987), Introduction à la lecture de la Science de la logique de Hegel: La Doctrine du concept. Paris: Aubier.Google Scholar
Bowman, B. (2013), Hegel and the Metaphysics of Absolute Negativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burbidge, J. (2002), ‘Objektivität’, in Koch, A. F. and Schick, F. (eds.), G. W. F. Hegel. Wissenschaft der Logik. Berlin: Akademie.Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (1976), Das Problem der Subjektivität in Hegels Logik. Bonn: Bouvier.Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (1986), ‘Die Idee des Lebens in Hegels Logik’, in Horstmann, R.-P. and Petry, M. J. (eds.), Hegels Philosophie der Natur. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.Google Scholar
Englert, A. T. (2017), ‘Life, Logic, and the Pursuit of Purity’, Hegel-Studien 50: 6395.Google Scholar
Ferrarin, A. (2001), Hegel and Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleischmann, E. (1968), La science universelle ou la logique de Hegel. Paris: Plon.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1971), ‘Hegels Logik der Reflexion’, in his Hegel im Kontext. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1974), ‘Formen der Negation in Hegels Logik’, Hegel-Jahrbuch: 245–56.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1976), ‘Hegels Grundoperation’, in Guzzoni, U., Rang, B. and Siep, L. (eds.), Der Idealismus und seine Gegenwart. Festschrift für Werner Marx. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1978), ‘Hegels Logik der Reflexion’, Hegel-Studien Beiheft 18: 204324.Google Scholar
Knappik, F. (2016), ‘Hegel's Essentialism. Natural Kinds and the Metaphysics of Explanation in Hegel's Theory of “the Concept”’, European Journal of Philosophy 24: 760–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreines, J. (2008), ‘The Logic of Life: Hegel's Philosophical Defense of Teleological Explanation Living Beings’, in Beiser, F. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth Century Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kreines, J. (2015), Reason in the World: The Philosophical Appeal of Hegel's Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindquist, D. (2020), ‘On Origins and Species: Hegel on the Genus-Process’, Hegel Bulletin 41:3: 426–45.Google Scholar
Mure, G. R. G. (1950), A Study of Hegel's Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Karen, Ng (2020), Hegel's Concept of Life: Self-Consciousness, Freedom, Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. B. (2019), Hegel's Realm of Shadows: Logic as Metaphysics in The Science of Logic. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sell, A. (2013), Der lebendige Begriff: Leben und Logik bei G. W. F. Hegel. Freiburg: Karl Alber Verlag.Google Scholar
Spahn, C. (2007) Lebendiger Begriff, begriffenes Leben: Zur Grundlegung der Philosophie des Organischen bei G.W.F. Hegel. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.Google Scholar
Stekeler-Weithofer, P. (2004), ‘Gehört das Leben in die Logik?’, in Schneider, H. (ed.), Sich in Freiheit entlassen: Natur und Idee bei Hegel. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (2006), From Concept to Objectivity: Thinking Through Hegel's Subjective Logic. Burlington: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (2012), Hegel's Science of Logic: A Critical Rethinking in Thirty Lectures. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar