Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-g5fl4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-27T12:03:09.980Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Opportunity and impasse: social change and the limits of international legal strategy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 August 2020

Lee McConnell*
Affiliation:
University of Bristol, Office 3.21, 8-10 Berkeley Square, Bristol, UK
*
Corresponding author. E-mail: Lee.mcconnell@bristol.ac.uk
Get access
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

A diverse range of actors, from practitioners and academics to civil society groups and activists, appear to see hope in international law for the advancement of their causes. This paper examines whether this optimism is well-founded. It explores whether international law can serve as an agent of social change, and whether it can accommodate radical changes in social order. It begins by exposing a formalist stance that is immanent to much ‘legal activist’ discourse. It then explores links between this mode of jurisprudential thought and idealist epistemology. Drawing from the philosophy of Theodor Adorno, and in particular his notion of ‘identity-thinking’, it uncovers structural connections between formalism, idealism, law, and economy that call into question international law's socially-transformative potential. The perspective advanced in this paper falls somewhere between the polarities of opportunity and impasse, seeking to acknowledge the importance of legal strategies in safeguarding the disenfranchised, while remaining alive to their potential dangers and limitations.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

International law is often portrayed as an institutional and normative framework that, while imperfect, is capable of facilitating the realization of ambitious global objectives.Footnote 1 It has been characterized as ‘a discipline, discourse, and practice of reform [that] tells a story of its own progressive development, and of its prominent role in the betterment of others’.Footnote 2 For David Kennedy, ‘whether in practice or the academy, whether working on particular legal issues or generating broad new proposals for the field as a whole, the work international lawyers do is in large part the generation of arguments for reforms’.Footnote 3 Today, international law is a site of intersection between practitioners, civil society groups, activists, and scholars seeking to advance a range of agendas.Footnote 4 Implicit in many of their activities is a degree of faith in the socially-transformative or even emancipatory potential of international law – the idea that the establishment of new legal regimes or reform to existing standards may ultimately serve ‘progressive’ ends. Whether such a belief is well-founded is the central concern of this paper. It explores whether international law can serve as an agent of social change, and whether it is capable of accommodating radical changes in social order.

The paper proceeds in three sections. The first section sketches what might be termed an ‘activist-reformer’ stance in international law, drawing from developments in the field of business and human rights by way of illustration. Its purpose is to expose a ‘formalist’ tendency lying behind much activist discourse. It then explores parallels between formalist jurisprudence and Kantian idealism. This connection is most pronounced in Hans Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law, which is used as an exemplar throughout.Footnote 5

The second section examines the theoretical implications of this idealist orientation via the work of the social theorist, Theodor Adorno. It uncovers structural connections between idealist epistemology and political economy that call into question its suitability as a theoretical framework for those seeking provoke social change through international law. The third section advances this analysis, drawing from a materialist theory of law developed by the Soviet theorist, Evgeny Pashukanis.Footnote 6 While contemporary Pashukanite scholars have not explicitly engaged with Adorno's work, this paper reveals significant harmony in their methods, such that the phenomenon of law may be conceived as an emanation of what Adorno termed ‘identity-thinking’. Viewed from this perspective, legal activism – and the severe separation between ‘form’ and ‘content’ that it often entails – betrays a fundamental subservience to prevailing forms of socio-economic organization.

This paper argues that structural affinities between law, economy, and idealist epistemology serve to limit international law's socially-transformative potential. These insights are particularly apparent when situated in the business and human rights context, where the limits of legalism in the face of economic power are plainly exposed. Yet, while Adorno's insights paint a rather bleak picture of both formalist argument and legalism generally, they do not necessitate the wholesale abandonment of either. Rather, Adorno offers a perspective that acknowledges and encourages reflection on their dangers and limitations, while remaining alive to the opportunities they present for real-world benefits. The main contributions offered by this paper, then, are threefold. First, it offers a robust and novel critique of formalist jurisprudence. Second, it exploits underexplored connections between Adorno's scholarship and wider Marxist jurisprudence. Third, in subjecting the theoretical issues raised by movements such as business and human rights to detailed critique, it provides an opportunity to reflect on the strategies pursued by those seeking to effect social change through international law.

Before proceeding, a word on the positionality of this work is necessary. While terms such as ‘emancipatory’, ‘transformative’, and ‘progressive’ are used interchangeably throughout this paper, they are left intentionally without positive definition. This approach is integral to the theoretical perspective adopted. As will become clearer below, Adorno's work relies on the notion that ‘[o]ur ideas of freedom emerge in the negation of what is negative, of the unfree conditions in which we live’.Footnote 7 As such, for Adorno, a ‘utopian future could not be affirmatively defined’.Footnote 8 It is only through critique – through the constant negation of the falsity that taints our thought – that emancipatory potential can be glimpsed. This is to say very little about what ‘a better life’ is to look like, or whether this can be achieved via legal strategy. All that is implied is that things can be different – an underlying refusal to accept as given the existing state of affairs. This core theme is returned to and significantly expanded in what follows.

Opportunity and international law: the ‘empty formalism’ of the legal activist

International law is depicted as an agent of progress in at least two senses. In the first, progress is integral to the project itself. International law possesses ‘an immanent progressive value for the world, for civilization, for humanity’.Footnote 9 Indeed, the UN Charter commits to the promotion of ‘social progress and better standards of life in larger freedom’.Footnote 10 Perhaps as a consequence of these professed values, the discipline is said to engender a particular professional milieu. International lawyers ‘almost invariably see themselves as “progressives” whose political objectives appear not merely as normative hopes, but as necessary insights into the laws of historical or social development’.Footnote 11 Although ‘to work in a bank is not to be for banking’, this cannot be said for many international lawyers.Footnote 12 Yet, a more detached stance is also conceivable. It is clearly possible to acknowledge the utility of international law in advancing particular objectives while eschewing any firm commitment to the wider project. In this second sense, international law is merely a vehicle for ‘external’ projects. The primary commitment of the activist is to their cause rather than the discipline.Footnote 13

These positions are neither mutually-exclusive nor exhaustive of the professional attitudes permeating the field. They do, however, provide a useful contextual backdrop. Either or both can be said to be at play in recent business and human rights discourse. This diverse movement seeks to respond to the growing public influence wielded by corporate actors, and the adverse consequences their operations produce for much of the world's population.Footnote 14 Many advocate the establishment of new international regulatory standards, absent the will and capability of States to provide appropriate domestic safeguards. Proposals include a business and human rights treaty,Footnote 15 reform to investment treaty regimes providing asymmetrical rights to the corporations of investment-exporting States,Footnote 16 and the adoption of soft law instruments that may gradually crystallize into hard law.Footnote 17 These initiatives may lead to ‘advancements’ in the field itself: expanding and reconfiguring conceptions of legal personality,Footnote 18 extraterritorial jurisdiction,Footnote 19 and shared responsibility between (and beyond) States.Footnote 20 Progress for the field may be seen as progress for the world at large. Alternatively, the field may simply act as a vehicle for particular causes by facilitating gradual improvements to global labour conditions, environmental protection, and wealth distribution, or even serving as a stepping stone towards radical social transformation.

An implicit ‘formalist’ stance lies behind much activist-reformer discourse of this type. This term is employed to describe a range of characteristics in legal thought,Footnote 21 two of which are relevant to this paper.Footnote 22 First, the term is associated with a theory of adjudication premised on the logical derivation of legal decisions from abstract principles.Footnote 23 While this deductive formalism is dealt with in the penultimate section of the paper, the primary concern lies with a second characterization. Empty formalism represents a theoretical approach that prioritizes the ‘form’ or ‘vessel’ in appraising legal validity.Footnote 24 So long as a norm meets certain formal requirements, its content will not affect this validity. Thus construed, formalism aims at an objective description of law,Footnote 25 conceived as an autonomous branch of knowledge.Footnote 26 To treat law ‘as a self-contained system of norms that is “there”, identifiable without reference to the content, aim, and development of the rules that compose it, is the very essence of formalism’.Footnote 27

Empty formalism is seemingly immanent to many activist-reformer projects, including the business and human rights movement. International law is conceived as a mere servant to a larger cause. Its content is a site of struggle unrestrained by the essential properties of its form. Such a stance is arguably a necessary minimum in order to see hope in international law for the advancement of one's agenda. While this may be supplemented by a belief in international law's inherently progressive character, ‘from the activist's perspective, a commitment to law only is a commitment to empty formalism’.Footnote 28 Yet, rarely is it suggested that international law may be blind to (or part of) the problem.Footnote 29 To do so ‘would put the activist in a strategically difficult position, running the risk of marginalization… The activist therefore needs to dress his or her objectives in international law claims’.Footnote 30

While ‘formalism’ has arguably become ‘little more than a loosely employed term of abuse’,Footnote 31 this paper seeks to explore the relationship between activist discourse and formalist argument in international law. It aims to discover whether formalism may be employed opportunistically, ‘as a counter-hegemonic strategy’,Footnote 32 by those seeking to effect social-transformation. Below, it sketches connections between formalist jurisprudence and Kantian idealism, before drawing on the work of Theodor Adorno to explore various theoretical implications for the pursuit of social change via legal strategy. Ultimately, it is argued that structural connections between formalism, idealism, law, and economy diminish the socially-transformative capacity of international law. Given the confrontation between law and economy that characterizes the field of business and human rights, this movement serves as a useful practical reference point throughout. While rooted in this context, this paper does not engage in a detailed doctrinal appraisal of the diverse range of proposals advanced by the movement. Such matters have been dealt with elsewhere.Footnote 33 Rather, it focuses on wider theoretical questions concerning the adequacy of law as a vehicle through which adverse corporate conduct might be combatted, and meaningful social change might be achieved.

The idealist roots of empty formalism

Empty formalism shares significant parallels with certain philosophies of natural science. This is evident in the idealist epistemology of Immanuel Kant, which posits a separation between the human subject and the object of knowledge. For Kant, it was not possible to acquire direct knowledge of an object as a ‘thing-in-itself’ – that is, in a form unconditioned by the subject's conceptual apparatus.Footnote 34 As such, Kant identified a number of invariant a priori conditions necessary for empirical knowledge of the natural world. There are two core components to this. First, in the transcendental aesthetic, Kant posits that the natural world appears to the human senses via the a priori conditions of ‘time’ and ‘space’.Footnote 35 Second, in the transcendental analytic, Kant posits a range of a priori intellectual ‘categories’ or ‘concepts’.Footnote 36 The subject applies these concepts to intuitions perceived by the senses, synthesizing them into an intelligible format. For example, sensory perceptions of a bat hitting a ball may be known via the category of ‘causation’.Footnote 37 Here, causality is the form of knowledge. The content is derived from ‘raw’ data as they appear by the senses. Put together, the subject can be taken to know the object.

The question of how ‘causality’ as a discrete form of knowledge is validated requires further consideration. Clearly, it isn't possible to point empirically to the first cause that set the universe in motion. We might presuppose a ‘big bang’, but inability to prove this point would not cause us to doubt the validity of scientific observations. In effect, we ‘assume a first cause as a limiting idea, knowing that no such entity exists or even could exist’.Footnote 38 Thus, natural science must presume an unknowable first cause, or simply accept the transcendental validity of causal knowledge.

The structure of Kantian idealism is mirrored in empty formalist jurisprudence. It is replicated most explicitly in Hans Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law, and for this reason, it is adopted as the archetypal empty formalist position throughout this paper. Kelsen's jurisprudence is premised on the is/ought dichotomy. Legal rules are normative prescriptions as to what ought to occur, as entirely separate from descriptions of fact (is).Footnote 39 Thus, the validity of the norm ‘all murderers ought to receive life sentences’ cannot depend on whether all murderers are, in reality, caught and punished. This logic pierces contractarian explanations of legal validity common to international law, whereby the State, as an entity comparable to a natural person, validates the law by expressing its ‘consent to be bound’.Footnote 40 The sociological characterization of the State implicit in contractarian theories – with its empirical features such as territory and population – belongs to the realm of is.Footnote 41 It cannot serve as validation for legal prescriptions (ought).

Kelsen conceived of the legal order as a hierarchy encompassing both international and domestic spheres. The validity of lower norms is derived from their compatibility with higher norms. At the apex sits the Grundnorm or basic norm – the only ‘non-positive’ norm in the system.Footnote 42 Accordingly, some have noted its proximity to a natural law source of validation.Footnote 43 For Kelsen, this was a mischaracterization:

the basic norm may be considered a natural law doctrine in keeping with Kant's transcendental logic. There still remains the enormous difference which separates… the transcendental conditions of all empirical knowledge and consequently the laws prevailing in nature on the one side from the transcendent metaphysics beyond all experience on the other. There is a similar difference between the basic norm which merely makes possible the cognition of positive law as a meaningful order, and a natural law doctrine which proposes to establish a just order beyond, and independent of, all positive law.Footnote 44

Accordingly, Kelsen retains the ‘normativity’ inherent to natural law framings, while rejecting appeals to an ultimate moral foundation. Simultaneously, he retains the positive determination of the content of legal norms, while rejecting the inseparability of validity and fact maintained by dominant positivism.Footnote 45 Thus, Kelsen's theory of law is rooted neither in empirical facts nor moral absolutes. While the Grundnorm validates the legal form in a manner comparable to a natural law principle, it is empty of substantive content.Footnote 46

In justification, Kelsen often appealed to Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.Footnote 47 Comparable to the transcendental validity of causal knowledge, the Grundnorm serves as an a priori concept that makes knowledge of law as a unified normative order possible:Footnote 48

natural science becomes metaphysics when it attempts to discuss the creation of the natural universe… Just as self-contained natural science can say nothing of its own nature but must presuppose it as a hypothesis, self-contained legal science has its hypothesis in the basic norm.Footnote 49

As such, the Grundnorm ‘makes evident the limits of human knowledge generally, and the limits of positive, normative legal knowledge in particular’.Footnote 50 For Kelsen, it was necessarily presupposed in any depiction of law as a normative order.

Nonetheless, Kant's logic cannot be applied wholesale to the legal sphere. For Kant, it was impossible for the subject to know the empirical world in a form unconditioned by a priori categories. This is because empirical reality is a ‘given’ source of data that affects the subject's senses; it is then necessarily rendered intelligible by the subject's intellectual processes. Yet, ‘law’ is not an immediate ‘given’ in the same way as sensory data.Footnote 51 Instead, the Grundnorm constitutes a formal category that is not directed towards a ‘given’ object of study.Footnote 52 Rather, the object itself is constituted by the subject. Kammerhofer captures this perfectly:

What [the natural sciences] attempt to do is impossible with respect to normative [legal] theory, because here the theory through the creation of the intellectual superstructure determines its object: the ought. A purported ‘given’ that does not satisfy the criteria of normative theory is not a ‘given’ of normative scholarship… The choice is existential, because everyone cognising norms has already made the choice, even if they are not aware that they have done it. It is an expression of our existential freedom to choose our own dogmas and is thus most profound.Footnote 53

That legal theories offer a choice of dogmas is indeed profound, particularly in light of what follows. For now, it suffices to note the implications of the empty formalist stance for the activist-reformer. Kantian idealism posits a form/content divide comparable to the empty formalism of the legal activist. International law is an empty vessel. Its form does not necessitate any particular content, permitting the activist to see hope in law for the advancement of their cause.

From the business and human rights perspective, an empty formalism such as Kelsen's may even merit explicit adoption.Footnote 54 While it is difficult to speak of a uniform movement employing complementary strategies in this field, a resurgent interest in the extension of international obligations to business actors has emerged. This is visible in the recent debates surrounding the inclusion of investor obligations within bilateral investment treaties,Footnote 55 and in strategic domestic litigation seeking to employ standards derived from customary international law against multinational corporations.Footnote 56 Such approaches entail the extension of international obligations to corporate actors in a manner that offends against State-centric, contractarian conceptions of legal validity. Kelsen's empty formalism is capable of accommodating this business and human rights agenda, given the radical restructuring of legal personality it permits. On this view, legal validity is no longer derived from the consent of the addressee of a norm during the law-making process.Footnote 57 Law-making competence is a power ascribed by international law's content, rather than being tied to the validity of its form. Consequently, scholarly concerns regarding the legitimacy of the extension of international obligations to corporate actors unable to directly consent to the norms are alleviated,Footnote 58 and the possibility of the direct regulation of business actors in international law emerges.Footnote 59 On the formalist view, legal personality is simply a bundle of rights and obligations imputed to an actor. The terms ‘subject’, ‘validator’, and ‘law-maker’ are not synonyms as presented by contractarian theory, but discrete and contingent statuses determined by the content of the international legal order. Thus, while the claim to necessity of an empty formalist conception of law such as Kelsen's is likely untenable, the approach deserves to be taken seriously. This is particularly so given its immanence to legal activist discourse, and its potential to respond to contemporary challenges within and beyond the field of business and human rights.

Empty formalism as ‘identity-thinking’

This section introduces Adorno's notion of ‘identity-thinking’ before employing it to expose structural affinities between idealist epistemology and economy. Such connections call into question the progressive potential of the activist's empty formalist stance. This analysis is extended in the third section, which supplements Adorno's insights with a materialist theory of law derived from Evgeny Pashukanis. In combination, this discussion allows a deeper examination of the problems particular to formalism than has been permitted in the existing literature, while also addressing universal concerns surrounding international law's socially-transformative potential.

Above, it was established that Kelsen's formalism hinges on what might be termed ‘constitutive-subjectivity’. Simply put, the jurist (subject) perceives law (object) as a normative order via the Grundnorm (concept) in a fashion comparable to a natural scientist (subject) characterizing empirical events (object) via causation (concept). Adorno was deeply critical of humanity's willingness to passively accept the world in a conceptually-mediated form. For Adorno, this approach was prone to overlook that which falls outside of the concepts or categories applied by the subject. In his view, such a tendency was demonstrable of the social problems that pervade in modernity. Writing with Max Horkheimer, Adorno characterized these problems via two theses: ‘myth is already enlightenment and enlightenment reverts to myth’.Footnote 60 While these statements can seem frustratingly cryptic, they concisely express a number of insights concerning the techniques employed by humankind to know and control their world.Footnote 61

For Horkheimer and Adorno, seemingly ‘primitive’ modes of thinking (e.g. appeals to magic, ritual, and so on) are forms of rationality; they are ways of ordering and understanding the world, despite the mythic status with which they are branded in modernity.Footnote 62 Thus, myth is already enlightenment. Conversely, and despite Kant's motivation to banish the dogmatic metaphysics of previous eras,Footnote 63 the idealist project itself reverts to myth when it treats objects in their conceptually-mediated form as complete, thereby discarding all appreciation of that which is not captured by the concept.Footnote 64 Adorno termed this tendency ‘identity-thinking’, a process that does not say what something is in its rich, manifold particularity, but ‘what it comes under, what it exemplifies or represents, and what, accordingly, it is not itself’.Footnote 65 Thus, while Kant posits the existence of a ‘noumenal realm’ of ‘things-in-themselves’, subjects are denied direct access to it. This ‘confines the subject to examining its perceptions because these are allegedly all it can know’.Footnote 66 The remainder or surplus of the object falling outside of the concept is what Adorno termed the non-identical.Footnote 67 As such, in Dialectic of Enlightenment, Horkheimer and Adorno were not merely standing in opposition to Kant's Enlightenment rationality; their intention was not to hark back to some ‘golden age’, or to condemn all thought as equally mythic. Instead, they suggested that reason, as employed in idealism, is not enlightened enough.Footnote 68 It fails to appreciate the significance of the non-identical – the surplus that idealism's conceptual apparatus cannot capture.

Rather than seeing modes of thought as invariant and universal, Adorno saw them as the products of objective socio-historical conditions. He offered a materialist response that echoed Marx's aphorism: ‘life is not determined by consciousness, but consciousness by life’.Footnote 69 Yet, Adorno also recognized that ‘it is much more difficult to really think as a materialist than it is to lay claim to the label’.Footnote 70 While emphasizing that the subject's perception is coloured by the material conditions in which they are situated, Adorno did not claim immediate access to those objective conditions in thought.Footnote 71 To this extent, Adorno was in line with Kant in denying subjects direct knowledge of ‘things-in-themselves’. To posit such access would be to lapse into the same illusory thinking as idealism – to become another mythology masquerading as enlightenment.Footnote 72 Rather, Adorno encouraged a reflexive practice of critical thinking that aimed to highlight the partial and impoverished character of the subject's conceptual apparatus. He sought to respect the object, ‘even where the object does not heed to the rules of thinking’.Footnote 73

Among the techniques employed in this pursuit was immanent critique, by which Adorno sought to ‘uncover the contradictions and tensions within a given position…rather than judge it against some external or transcendent standard’.Footnote 74 Accordingly, Adorno rejected the possibility of a ‘fresh start’ in philosophy resting on an immediate materialist grounding. Instead, he used reasoning characteristic of prevailing idealist philosophy against itself. In doing so, he sought to expose the social antagonisms in material reality of which idealism is a product, and which it attempts to conceal.Footnote 75 A demonstration of this technique is evident in Adorno's ‘metacritique’ of Kantian epistemology. Given Kelsen's proximity to this branch of philosophy, this is of direct relevance to the argumentative thread of this paper. As Chimni acknowledges, ‘a materialist critique of Kelsen must begin with a critique of Kant's transcendental method’.Footnote 76

Adorno's critique begins by addressing the transcendental analytic, in which Kant sets out the intellectual conditions necessary for knowledge. Through this set of a priori categories or concepts, the subject is said to render ‘raw’ sensory data intelligible. Against Kant, Adorno claims that ‘[w]ithout “Something” there is no thinkable formal logic’.Footnote 77 Put another way, without being oriented towards a material object, our concepts would not simply be empty a priori forms. Rather, they would be unthinkable entirely.Footnote 78 For Adorno, concepts are always coloured by materiality or objectivity; they are ‘entwined with a non-conceptual whole’.Footnote 79

To refer to non-conceptualities… is characteristic of the concept, and so is the contrary: that as the abstract unit of the noumena subsumed thereunder it will depart from the noumenal. To change the direction of conceptuality, to give it a turn toward non-identity, is the hinge of negative dialectics.Footnote 80

Moreover, Kant presupposes that the subject's senses are able to apprehend ‘given’ objects in a pure or unmediated form prior to this intellectual process taking place.Footnote 81 Thus, Adorno turns to Kant's transcendental aesthetic – the sensible conditions underlying this process. Characteristically for Kant, unmediated material objects comprise: (i) the matter and (ii) the form. The form is said to make the matter's unmediated representation to the human senses possible. This form cannot be abstracted from sensory experience of the matter, since it must be presupposed in order for the subject's senses to be affected in the first place. Rather, this form is brought to the matter by the perceiving subject as a necessary condition for sensory experience. But at the same time, the form cannot be a concept in the intellectual sense discussed above. If this were so, it would be impossible for objects to appear to the senses in a pure fashion, unmediated by the subject's conceptual apparatus.Footnote 82 Thus, Kant was forced to posit ‘an a priori form of sensibility pertaining to the very structure of sensibility and constituting a necessary condition for all sense intuition’.Footnote 83 The two forms identified by Kant are time and space, and these supposedly ‘pure’ forms permit unmediated objects to be apprehended by the senses.Footnote 84

Perhaps understandably, Adorno found Kant's explanation that time and space are neither products of objective experience nor subjective concepts deeply problematic. Instead, Adorno contended that ‘time’ and ‘space’ were merely subjective concepts. Consequently, they were coloured or mediated by material objects to some degree.Footnote 85 The so-called pure ‘forms’ by which matter appears to the senses

are not intuitive, but rather the highest universals under which the ‘given’ may be grasped. The fact, however, that a given independent of these concepts is not possible, turns givenness itself into something mediated… Such a contradiction expresses a comprehension of the non-identity and the impossibility of capturing subjective concepts without surplus… It expresses ultimately the break down of epistemology itself.Footnote 86

To simplify, the radical separations erected by Kant between form/content, concept/intuition, knowledge/sensibility, and subject/object, are the source of its undoing. The polarities ‘cannot be made intelligible without destroying the methodological separation in which they are supposedly held apart for epistemological analysis’.Footnote 87 Subjective concepts, including Kant's ‘pure’ forms of intuition, are unthinkable and unintelligible without any relation, however minimal, to the object.

This means that the object – the material circumstances in which the subject finds itself – must assume priority. In Adorno's words, there is

a difference of weighting… The forms are in fact essentially mediated by contents and cannot be conceived in their absence. The contents, however, always contain a reference to something that is not fully coextensive with form and cannot be fully reduced to it… [T]here is a priority [of matter] over form that amounts to the statement that our knowledge does not exhaust itself in pure mediation, in its purely formal aspect, but that it remains attached to something to which it refers.Footnote 88

Simply put, while there is a dialectical relationship between subject and object, the object (or matter) ultimately takes priority over the subject's conceptual apparatus. Forms are not entirely constituted by the subject, but are coloured by ‘the subject's own corporally mediated apprehension of objects’.Footnote 89 In other words, subjects cannot be reduced to pure, transcendental consciousness. Rather, subjects are also human; they are socially-situated, material objects:

if subjects have an objective core, if the subject is thus something other than a geometrical location in space, then this will be due to just those qualities which it shares with objects that have traditionally been designated as merely subjective.Footnote 90

Given that all human subjects and the concepts they employ are infused with objectivity in this way, Kant's project of radically separating the two fails.

If the object has priority as Adorno claims, then the intellectual conditions presented by Kant as universal and invariant are in fact variable. Kant's conditions of knowledge actually reflect a particular socio-historical mode of understanding. By transforming something variable into an invariant to which all thought must correspond, Kant engaged in the very dogmatism he sought to overcome. His presentation of contradiction as coherence results in an unworkable epistemology that nonetheless expresses a certain ‘truth-content’.Footnote 91 In other words, much like a Freudian slip, the false coherence presented by Kantian idealism unintentionally reveals a ‘truth’ concerning the material/social conditions under which this mode of thought gained prominence.Footnote 92 References to these truths are ‘part and parcel of even apparently “purely” logical or epistemological concepts themselves… Immanent critique seeks to make explicit the reference to social experience already sedimented within philosophical concepts’.Footnote 93 Thus, the novelty of Adorno's materialism is that it is accessed negatively. Adorno did not posit access to objects in their unmediated form.Footnote 94 Nor did he posit as immutable the material world that conditions our modes of perception. Rather, he sought to uncover references to the material conditions in which we are situated within our prevailing modes of thought. He encouraged reflection ‘at every historical and cognitive stage, both upon what at the time is presented as subject and object as well as upon their mediation’.Footnote 95

The dependence of subjective concepts on material conditions points to an emancipatory potential. It speaks to the capacity to alter the objective conditions on which our conceptuality is founded, rather than dogmatically forcing thought to yield to ‘invariant’ conditions.Footnote 96 Yet, Adorno did not romanticize previous socio-historical arrangements.Footnote 97 All modes of thinking to date have engaged in ‘identity-thinking’, subsuming objects under concepts that cannot capture their particularity. ‘It is not that capitalism invents mystification but that in capitalism mystification presents itself, to an unprecedented extent, as demystification’.Footnote 98 Thus, the most problematic characteristic of idealism (including Kelsen's brand) is that it claims its concepts, and the historically-specific conditions that colour them, are necessary presuppositions of human experience. To treat the object as it appears in thought as all that is relevant, all that is possible, is to equate the subjectively-constituted object with a thing-in-itself. Such a claim conceals the possibility for change in both thought and society.

This tendency in Kant and Kelsen's work expresses a reference to material, socio-economic conditions.Footnote 99 Indeed, Adorno's epistemological analysis shares many parallels with Marx's critique of commodity fetishism.Footnote 100 Marx highlighted the way in which particular products of labour assume an ‘equivalence’ via the universal category of ‘exchange-value’.Footnote 101 The same occurs when ‘labour-power’ is treated as identical to all other commodities, overlooking its ‘peculiar’ capacity to produce ‘surplus-value’.Footnote 102 Similar too is the equivalence expressed in the labour contract between bourgeois buyers and proletarian sellers of labour-power, despite the power disparity in their relationship.Footnote 103 For Adorno, ‘when consciousness reflects upon itself, it necessarily arrives at a concept of rationality that corresponds to the rationality of the labour process’.Footnote 104 Thus, the identity-thinking inherent within idealism points to the socio-economic relations in capitalist exchange societies, which characterize as equivalent (identical) that which is non-equivalent (non-identical).Footnote 105 Such societies obscure, rather than respect, the priority of the non-identical. This logic, which underlies empty formalist jurisprudence, is plainly in tension with the stated goals of the business and human rights movement.

Kelsen's formalism is a prime example of identity-thinking. His work is premised on a set of binaries: is/ought, fact/norm, and validity/efficacy. Legal knowledge is that which falls under his conception of ‘legal normativity’. All that is relevant to legal study pertains to the normative realm (ought). The empirical reality (is) that gives rise to law and provides it with its content is presupposed, but is written off as irrelevant, much like Kant's thing-in-itself.Footnote 106 In constraining legal knowledge to the normative realm as constituted by the jurist/subject, Kelsen overlooks important, non-identical features that are in fact vital conditions of possibility for normative legal knowledge.Footnote 107 Thus, Kelsen is able to remark that the practical effectiveness of the legal order is a condition, but not the reason for its validity.Footnote 108

Yet, it is precisely this position that may prove comforting to the activist-reformer. From the business and human rights perspective, it permits law to accommodate any content. This provides scope for the extension of direct obligations to corporate non-State actors. This might occur via the creation of new multilateral human rights treaties, reform to bilateral investment treaties, or via customary human rights standards invoked in domestic litigation.Footnote 109 In the alternative, it also permits international law to facilitate greater access to domestic remedies for victims of adverse corporate activity.Footnote 110 Such is the strategy employed in the current draft business and human rights treaty, which seeks to remove jurisdictional barriers to domestic litigation in the ‘home States’ of parent corporations. The hope is that this will work in tandem with soft law efforts to embed human rights due diligence into corporate supply chains, thereby improving compliance with human rights, and establishing tortious duties of care on behalf of parent companies where abuses take place at the hands of their foreign subsidiaries.Footnote 111 Again, nothing in the form of law precludes these ‘advances’ in content, so the activist-reformer argument goes. To the empty formalist, obstacles to ‘progress’ are largely externalized.Footnote 112 An assessment of the likelihood of these measures coming to pass is simply resigned to ‘separate’ theories of political or social obligation on States and corporate actors to realize such initiatives in practice.

To his credit, Kelsen was not blind to this tendency, but like Kant, wrote off these ‘external’ considerations no sooner than they were posited:

Nor let it be said that the jurist may not also undertake sociological, psychological, or historical studies… These are necessary; except that the jurist… must never incorporate the results of his explanatory examination into his construction of normative concepts.Footnote 113

An expanded reflection on the material conditions underlying Kelsen's normativity follows below. For now, it suffices to highlight the structural proximity of empty formalist logic to material conditions in capitalist economies. The abuses facilitated under such conditions are precisely what the business and human rights movement seeks to mitigate. Moreover, the neo-Kantian basis of Kelsen's theory makes it all the more problematic. Kammerhofer's notion of a ‘choice of dogmas’ underscores this perfectly.Footnote 114 So-called ‘normative science’ cannot even claim access to the immediate ‘givens’ of empirical reality. It is thus premised on an acutely arbitrary, variable concept to which its object of knowledge is simply forced to conform. In Adorno's words:

Neo-Kantianism… which laboured strenuously to gain the content of reality from logical categories, has indeed preserved its self-contained form as a system, but has thereby renounced every right over reality and has withdrawn into a formal region in which every determination of content is condemned to virtually the farthest point of an unending process.Footnote 115

This insight points to a structural affinity between empty formalism and a particular economic mode. Framed dialectically, Kelsen's definitive definition of what law is ultimately implies that the social relations that underlie it ought to persist. It presents as identical that which is non-identical, treating variable conceptual forms, and the material conditions that colour them, as invariable.Footnote 116 Yet, these considerations alone may not entirely undermine the empty formalist stance behind much business and human rights discourse. After all, this jurisprudence still admits of the possibility of accommodating legal developments that push against the socio-economic status quo, despite its inability to address realist factors concerning the political will to realize such agendas in practice.Footnote 117 Accordingly, the foregoing merely cautions that empty formalism, taken to its extreme, may provide only an illusion of emancipation. Acknowledgment of this position underlines the importance of a degree of interdisciplinarity and realism already in vogue in international legal scholarship. Yet, it does not dispute the utility of legal strategies in effecting social transformation. Law remains a component and potential agent of emancipation. Whether this residual faith in legal strategy is well-founded is explored below.

Legal strategy at an impasse: law as ‘identity-thinking’

It has been established that empty formalist accounts of law do not consider directly the social processes that give content to legal norms and represent the real operation of legal systems. It is to those material conditions, and their relationship with the form and content of international law, that this section turns. It begins with a discussion of the place of ‘the material’ in Kelsen's work, before elaborating a materialist theory of legal form. These insights are then extrapolated to the field of international law. The section concludes with a reflection on whether these material conditions, and the materially-situated character of international lawyers and legal activists, fundamentally impede the pursuit of social transformation through international law.

Materialism and the legal form

Material reality occupies a curious position in Kelsen's work. As mentioned above, his formalism presupposes a ‘minimally efficacious’ legal order. This provides the material conditions under which legal normativity may arise, without providing the reason for legal validity:Footnote 118

efficacy is a condition of validity; a condition, not a reason of validity. A norm is not valid because it is efficacious; it is valid if the order to which it belongs is, on the whole, efficacious.Footnote 119

This characterization is peculiar on first reading. Ebenstein suggests that some minimal degree of ‘tension’ between normative prescription and social reality is necessary to sustain Kelsen's jurisprudence. If reality were to correspond in all aspects with a legal norm, the ought would collapse into the is. The ‘norm’ would not be prescriptive, but descriptive.Footnote 120 The reverse poses similar problems; it would be problematic to speak of a legal order if its norms were entirely unobserved.Footnote 121

This curious aspect of Kelsen's formalism results from the radical separations on which it is premised. Yet, it is also the reason for its potential utility to the legal activist. Just as the validity of norms is not grounded by their social efficacy, nor is it affected by the content prescribed by law-makers in social reality.Footnote 122 Legal norms can accommodate any content, so long as the prescribed procedures are followed and there is an absence of blatantly contradictory norms.Footnote 123 Thus, Kelsen elaborates a theory of legal form. Nothing in the ‘form’ of law (law qua norms) precludes the achievement of the stated goals of the business and human rights movement.Footnote 124 But with the opportunities provided by this framing come its inability to account for socio-economic conditions impeding their realization. The Pure Theory of Law can ambivalently accommodate such agendas, but no more. There is, however, a deeper question prompted by Adorno's critique of Kantian epistemology. It concerns whether empty formalist theories can legitimately claim a radical separation between form and content in a manner that at least maintains the possibility of effecting radical change through law.

A branch of Marxist scholarship has expressed a ‘scepticism that international law can be used to systematically improve the world’.Footnote 125 In an analysis that often echoes Adorno's critique of idealism, China Miéville claims that rule-based formalist theories of law are thin, self-recursive and fail to provide a robust account of the specificity of the legal form.Footnote 126

The rules of international behaviour are taken as given… Inasmuch as they are law… this is simply because we say they are law, rather than because of their form or essence. Rules, here, are deemed central: their ‘law-ness’ is epiphenomenal.Footnote 127

Here, Miéville exposes a problem addressed indirectly among Kelsen scholars.Footnote 128 Kelsen arguably violates his own validity/efficacy divide by adhering to the ‘coercive order paradigm’ associated with John Austin.Footnote 129 Some development on this point is necessary.

For Austin, law consisted of a system of sovereign commands enforced by sanctions. Consequently, he famously denied international law status as law ‘properly so called’.Footnote 130 Kelsen agreed with Austin as regards the uniquely coercive character of legal norms, but concluded that the international community fulfilled this criterion in a decentralized manner via war and reprisals.Footnote 131 The international legal order is said to hold a monopoly on force, which is only permitted as a sanction in response to a breach.Footnote 132 For Kelsen, denial of the monopoly of force held by the legal order would ‘den[y] international law in toto as a legal order’.Footnote 133 Kelsen must adopt this position owing to a problem of his own making. His conception of law as a normative sphere disconnected from social reality makes it difficult to distinguish legal norms from norms belonging to other spheres (e.g. morality). In order to differentiate legal norms, Kelsen must point to coercion as a distinguishing characteristic.Footnote 134 Yet, this poses a problem:

To make law's existence dependent on coercive elements – which are designed to guarantee its effectiveness – in effect means… making the validity of a legal system dependent on (not equivalent to!) its continued effectiveness.Footnote 135

Thus, in making coercion and efficacy integral to his theory, Kelsen seemingly violates his self-imposed is/ought divide by suggesting that there is an irreducible materialist component to the legal form. If this coercive element were removed, only the notion of pure normativity would remain.Footnote 136 Kelsen would fail to account for the particularity, the ‘law-ness’, of law.

Kammerhofer provides a compelling defence of Kelsen's methodology, such that the coercive order paradigm may be discarded without destroying the possibility of cognizing law as a discrete system. For Kammerhofer, the primary problem is one invented by traditional positivism, which seeks to identify one ‘true’ body of law as elevated above all other normative orders.Footnote 137 By removing the coercive element, law simply lies in a continuum with all other normative orders. What gives law or any other normative system its specific sphere of validity is not coercion, but a choice undertaken by the subject:

there is no objective criterion to cognize the coherence of a normative order. This is a problem of Kelsenian theory, a problem merely hidden behind the veil of the coercive order paradigm…We must realize what Kelsen had taken on from Kant, namely that one's epistemological position influences the world we perceive, that the world is only what we perceive.Footnote 138

The quality of Kammerhofer's work in lending greater consistency to Kelsen is not disputed. Yet, in the present context, Kammerhofer proves Miéville's point. Without coercion, all that remains is pure normativity and a subjective choice. Kelsen discovers nothing uniquely legal.Footnote 139

This insight can be pushed further in light of Adorno's work. Kammerhofer's attempt to separate more radically the spheres of is and ought magnifies the social antagonisms Kelsen sought to conceal. The products of arbitrary conceptual choices originating in the subject are treated as equivalent to the object of knowledge. This mode of thinking fails to capture the object in its particularity; it fails to acknowledge and respect the object's non-identity. By treating law qua norms, Kelsen claims to subsume the object of knowledge under an abstract concept without remainder. Yet, there obviously is a surplus that falls outside the concept of normativity: the material conditions that make possible the conception of law as a body of norms in the first place. All Kelsen's theory can perceive is a by-product; the result of presupposed and apparently invariant social relations. While his ‘science’ defines law's essence in its normativity and aims to provide a neutral account of the object of knowledge, it actually presents a partial picture by simply defining the non-identical out of view. His theory ‘explains nothing, and turns its back from the outset on the facts of reality’.Footnote 140 In failing to acknowledge the particular social relations that fall outside and colour his concept, he treats these material conditions as immutable. He conceals the dependence of his theory on social reality, denying its direct relevance to the jurist.

Analogously, Adorno argued that sociology was unable to claim full disciplinary autonomy,Footnote 141 given that the conceptual apparatus by which the discipline makes this claim is pre-formed, self-constituting, and mediated by material conditions.Footnote 142

‘[I]ndividual intellectual disciplines such as jurisprudence or sociology… follow their own delusively self-grounding methodologies rather than the historically varying material itself… The illusory autonomy of individual disciplines… is inseparable from the fate of consciousness in a society universally structured by the commodity form’.Footnote 143

This proximity between Adorno's identity-thinking and Marx's critique of commodity fetishism is particularly pertinent.

For Miéville, empty formalism fails to capture the uniquely legal aspect of law.Footnote 144 He finds a resolution to this problem in the work of the Soviet theorist, Evgeny Pashukanis. In an analysis close to that of Adorno, Pashukanis characterized branches of legal theory as being

at pains to transfer the object of analysis into the realm of subjective areas of consciousness… and fail[ing] to see that the ordering of the corresponding abstract categories expresses the logical structure of social relations which are concealed behind individuals and which transcend the bounds of human consciousness.Footnote 145

Pashukanis saw the conceptual jurisprudence employed by legal theorists, including Kelsen, as capable of expressing oblique references to the material conditions in which such theories arose.Footnote 146 He sought to discover whether ‘the categories of law are objective forms of thought (objective for the historically given society) corresponding to objective social relations’.Footnote 147 In other words, he sought a materialist theory of legal form that respected ‘non-identity’.

For Pashukanis, law represented ‘the mystified form of a specific social relation’.Footnote 148 The social relations that give rise to law are revealed in Marx's analysis of the commodity, an analysis that Adorno ‘ranked with the finest analyses of classical German Philosophy’.Footnote 149 Accordingly, Pashukanis took the view that ‘the existence of the legal form is contingent upon the integration of the different products of labour according to the principle of equivalent exchange’.Footnote 150 Miéville offers a concise distillation:

[I]n commodity exchange, each commodity must be the private property of its owner, freely given in return for the other. In their fundamental form, commodities exchange at a rate determined by their exchange value, not because of some external reason or because one party demands it. Therefore, each agent in exchange must be (i) an owner of property, and (ii) formally equal to the other agent(s). Without these conditions, what occurred would not be commodity exchange. The legal form is the necessary form taken by the relation between these formally equal owners of exchange value.Footnote 151

Thus, law serves as a particular conceptual lens through which exchange relations can be perceived and preserved. Law is a deceptive device through which the subject is able to perceive as formally equivalent that which is not equivalent.Footnote 152 The formal equality established by the legal contract misrepresents the relationship between parties, concealing their non-identity.Footnote 153 Law is a form of identity-thinking; a mode of thought that reaches its peak in capitalist exchange economies. Empty formalism concentrates this position by denying the direct relevance of these insights to jurists.Footnote 154 Adorno captures this perfectly:

In law the formal principle of equivalence becomes the norm… An equality in which differences perish secretly serves to promote inequality… For the sake of an unbroken systematic, the legal norms cut short what is not covered, every specific experience that has not been shaped in advance, and then they raise the instrumental rationality to the rank of a second legality sui generis. The total legal realm is one of definitions.Footnote 155

Moreover, Adorno's work is capable of supplementing and strengthening the Pashukanite view against several significant critiques. First, Pashukanis has been accused of basing his theory on the circulation of commodities rather than their historically specific mode of production.Footnote 156 If, as Marx acknowledged, commodity exchange is not peculiar to capitalism, then surely neither is the legal form.Footnote 157 Yet, this does not necessarily undermine Pashukanis's central analysis.Footnote 158 Rather, it suggests that law existed in an ‘embryonic’ form prior to the emergence of capitalist class relations and the universalization of capitalist commodity production and exchange.Footnote 159 The term ‘embryonic’ is somewhat problematic, in that it suggests a certain primitiveness or imperfection – that law will inevitably assume its ‘final form’ under capitalism. From Adorno's perspective, it is perhaps better to speak of historicizing the form assumed and role performed by law in particular socio-historical circumstances. Nonetheless, there is a parallel in Adorno's claim that identity-thinking is not a product of capitalism, but simply becomes entrenched, obscured, and universalized therein. Where all production is geared towards exchange, exchange-value entirely eclipses use-value; identity eclipses non-identity.Footnote 160 In a similar way, the universalization of commodity exchange under capitalism results in the universalization of the legal form, itself a mode of identity-thinking.Footnote 161

Second, Kelsen dedicates a chapter in The Communist Theory of Law to Pashukanis.Footnote 162 There is a certain irony in Kelsen's claim that ‘[b]y pretending to be morally indifferent, objective science, Marxian socialism tries to veil the highly subjective character of the value judgement which is at its basis’.Footnote 163 Exchange ‘Marxian socialism’ for ‘the Pure Theory of Law’ and the reader is presented with a distillation of the conclusions drawn from Adorno above. To his credit, Kelsen disputes the capability of the Marxist method to present a more objective account of law, since ‘the very statement that the social existence determines the consciousness of men must claim to be… [an] objective theory of human consciousness, not determined by the social existence of the one who makes this statement’.Footnote 164 Again, this critique can be dismissed via Adorno's work.Footnote 165 Contrary to Kelsen, ‘there is no unequivocally true consciousness… Instead truth is glimpsed in the determinate negation of what is false’.Footnote 166 Adorno exposes the partiality of the subject's conceptual apparatus, rather than claiming unmediated access to the object of knowledge.Footnote 167 The compatibility of Adorno's reading of Marxist methodology with Pashukanis is evident in their common emphasis on Marx's critique of commodity fetishism.

Consequences for the ‘activist’ international lawyer

It is necessary to briefly sketch the operation of the commodity-form theory at the international level before spelling out the implications of this analysis for activist movements. Miéville argues that the emergence of the legal form among private individuals cannot be radically separated from the emergence of the centralized State's public order.Footnote 168 To maintain the façade of formal equality/impartiality, dispute resolution cannot be left to individual contracting parties. If this were so, the legal system would manifest its arbitrariness – its fundamental relation to violent coercion. Instead, dispute resolution ‘has to appear… as coercion emanating from an abstract collective person, exercised… in the interests of all parties to legal transactions’.Footnote 169 As such, the universalization of exchange has led

to the abstraction of the State as a ‘third force’ to stabilize relations. Thus politics and economics have been separated. In the same moment, the flipside of that separation and the creation of a public political body was the investiture of that body – the State – as subject of those legal relations which had long inhered between political entities, and has now become international law.Footnote 170

The operation of the commodity-form theory in international law is essentially simpler than the domestic context. In the place of individual contracting parties are States: the ‘High Contracting Parties’.Footnote 171 Each is characterized in its claim to territory, with concomitant rights and duties attaching to it.Footnote 172 States are presented as formally equal in law,Footnote 173 despite obvious disparities in their economic and political power.Footnote 174 In this decentralized system, ‘self-help’ prevails.Footnote 175 This factor prompts the ‘collapse of the distinction between politics and economics’ that emerged in the domestic context.Footnote 176 From this, Miéville derives his central thesis, modelled on Marx's aphorism: ‘between equal rights, force decides’.Footnote 177 Material inequalities in power between States are concealed by empty formalism, but are likely to produce real effects in terms of the interpretation of extant international law and the formulation of new instruments. For Miéville, this is a decisive factor in the struggle for interpretive dominance in the international legal order, one that undermines international law's progressive potential.

The malleability of international law at the hands of the powerful speaks to the indeterminacy thesis adopted by much New Stream and Critical Legal Studies (CLS) scholarship.Footnote 178 It is interesting that contemporary Pashukanite scholars embrace this view, it having previously been used to critique the commodity-form theory of law. In the 1980s, Duncan Kennedy derided its potential reliance on a deductive formalist trope; the widely-discredited, deterministic view that the rich content of law can be deduced logically from abstract principles derived from the economic base.Footnote 179 Such principles are seemingly integral to Pashukanis's theory. For Kennedy,

the problem is that the legacy of legal realism… is loss of faith that either the idea of property… or that of free contract, is enough to generate a unique legal regime. Most theorists believe that there are many possible specifications of a commodity (private property) regime and many possible specifications of a contract regime based on the idea of freedom.Footnote 180

Here, Kennedy highlights the complex, contradictory, and often indeterminate content of law. This indeterminacy suggests that law may be used as a tool of the right or left; its content is a site of struggle. Again, we see a certain empty formalism common to the activist-reformer stance. Adorno's work potentially supplement's Kennedy's view, highlighting that legal concepts are not necessarily static and unchangeable, but dynamic and responsive to material forces. While extant law may privilege particular conceptions of property and contract and in doing so facilitate the identity-thinking integral to capitalist exchange, this is not to say that these are immutable properties of law in general. On this reading, Miéville's pessimism regarding the socially-transformative potential of law is arguably misplaced, vindicating the resistance to powerful economic actors through law championed by the business and human rights movement.

Yet, advocates of the commodity-form theory now expressly adopt a comparable indeterminacy thesis drawn from Martti Koskenniemi. For Koskenniemi, the contradictions between individual liberty and social order inherent within liberal political doctrine manifest in international law, rendering it structurally indeterminate.Footnote 181 Virtually any course of action can be defended ‘by professionally impeccable legal arguments’ on a utopian basis, prioritizing world order, or an apologetic basis, prioritizing sovereign will.Footnote 182 Interestingly, Koskenniemi also advances a ‘culture of formalism’ through which he seeks to make use of ‘international law's professional vocabulary for critical or emancipatory causes’.Footnote 183 For Koskenniemi, ‘nothing has undermined formalism as a culture of resistance to power, a social practice of accountability, openness, and equality whose status cannot be reduced to the political positions of any one of the parties whose claims are treated within it’.Footnote 184

Consequently, Koskenniemi embraces a version of empty formalism, albeit via novel reasoning. In exposing international law's structural indeterminacy, he calls for international lawyers to move ‘beyond objectivism’; to abandon the view that a definitive interpretive decision can be reached via a process internal to legal argumentation itself, or by reference to some stable external ground.Footnote 185 Instead, he calls on the profession to acknowledge the inescapable moment of politics in any interpretation or application of legal doctrine.Footnote 186 This technique frees the content of international law, while retaining some semblance of form that separates it from pure politics.Footnote 187 Koskenniemi is incredibly close to Kelsen in separating form and content in this way.Footnote 188 As established above, such a position enables movements such as business and human rights to see hope in international law for progressive projects that seek to restrain the harmful practices of powerful economic actors.

Adorno's theoretical orientation permits us to navigate the connections and tensions between all three stances on law and emancipation: Koskenniemi's cautious optimism, Miéville's pessimism, and Kelsen's purported indifference. Indeed, the philosophical foundations of Koskenniemi's argument align substantially with those of Adorno. Citing the work of Ernesto Laclau, Koskenniemi treats international law as a language: a form of signification or identification.Footnote 189 Much like Adorno, Laclau saw all such systems as contingent and incapable of representing objects of knowledge without remainder. For Laclau, any attempt to delimit a system of signification implies that something lies beyond the boundaries of signification.Footnote 190 This ‘beyond’ is excluded by the system, but must be presupposed, otherwise it would be unnecessary to establish formal limits in the first place. Thus, the very possibility of constituting an identity is necessarily dependent on the exclusion of the non-identical. This is very close to Adorno's critique of identity-thinking.Footnote 191 This ‘non-identical space’ functions as a quasi-transcendental condition of possibility for any system of signification, but has no positively defined content.Footnote 192 It is an undefinable negative; an absence of identification. It is an expression of an underlying contingency; a horizon of possibility in which particular systems of signification are necessarily situated.Footnote 193

Through Laclau, Koskenniemi seeks to provoke a reflexive stance that enables legal professionals to use international law as a system of signification, while acknowledging its partiality and thus respecting non-identity. This stance is made possible by the system's indeterminacy. As Laclau suggests:

…if undecidability lies in the structure as such, then any decision developing one of its possibilities will be contingent, that is external to the structure, in the sense that it is not determined by that particular structure, even though it may be made possible by it.Footnote 194

In bringing this indeterminacy to light and stressing the essential political moment in any legal act or decision, Koskenniemi alerts legal professionals to the non-identical, negative ‘space’ that both makes possible the discipline's autonomy as a system of signification, and undermines its claim to totality.

Yet, any claim regarding international law's uniquely emancipatory character is surely undermined once it is situated alongside other systems of signification which might seek (but necessarily fail) to give comprehensive expression to their object of study. Indeed, it implicitly concedes that international law ‘may not be the most emancipatory, or democratic, or transgressive’ of all possible mediums.Footnote 195 Moreover, Koskenniemi acknowledges that a culture of formalism ‘cannot be permanently associated with any of the substantive outcomes’ it facilitates, and that it ‘may occasionally have supported good, occasionally evil policies’.Footnote 196 He recognizes that ‘out of a number of “possible” choices, some choices – typically conservative or status quo oriented choices are methodologically privileged in the relevant institutions’.Footnote 197 These admissions speak to Miéville's pessimism. While international law may be indeterminate, particular interpretive decisions must be made within particular institutional settings in order for the system to function.Footnote 198 While these may be open to revision or ‘dislocation’, Laclau suggested that any decision will rely on the hegemonic exclusion of other interpretive claims, however temporarily.Footnote 199 Similarly for Derrida, even ‘in the most reassuring and disarming discussion and persuasion, force and violence are present’.Footnote 200 But, Derrida continues, ‘[n]onetheless I think that there is, in the opening of a context of argumentation and discussion, a reference – unknown and indeterminate but nonetheless thinkable – to disarmament’.Footnote 201 Thus, while the necessary presence of coercion in reaching any interpretive decision or the fixing of any legal position is recognized, a shred of emancipatory potential lies behind any attempt to mount a claim through the language of international law. While Koskenniemi seems to share Derrida's position, for Miéville, the prospects for positive social transformation through international law are incredibly limited. Although doctrinal indeterminacy does not of necessity hand free-reign to powerful elites,Footnote 202 it is the power to fix a particular hegemonic interpretation that will prove decisive.Footnote 203 Thus, he claims that ‘[t]he international legal form assumes juridical inequality and unequal violence’.Footnote 204

While in broad agreement with Miéville, Knox notes the ‘complex interrelation of, inter alia, violence, ideology and economics… In widening and complicating the types of “coercion” that resolve legal disputes, it becomes much more difficult to argue that these will almost always be won by imperialist States’.Footnote 205 This contribution retains some cautious optimism by acknowledging the rise of progressive non-State actors.Footnote 206 Nonetheless, for Knox

the transformative power of this struggle is limited by the legal form… pursuing a legal strategy can break up collective solidarity, and render progressive forces unable to address the systemic causes of social problems. Indeed to mount a legal strategy is to risk legitimating the structures of global capitalism.Footnote 207

These insights undermine the radical separation between the legal form and its content posited by most empty formalist accounts. It is this element of ‘identity-thinking’, a mode of thought entrenched in societies in which exchange has become universalized, that undermines the agenda of the activist-reformer. There is a failure to respect that which falls outside and conditions the ‘empty’ system of legal norms. Thus, despite nothing logically precluding the use of international law to challenge the adverse effects of corporate conduct, whether that be through the imposition of direct obligations or the facilitation of access to domestic remedies, such initiatives are beholden to political and economic restraints to which formalist logic often blinds itself. Indeed, while the prospects of small victories in the legal sphere cannot be denied,Footnote 208 the uncritical pursuit of reform via formalist logic arguably obscures the deeper structural affinities between legal form, content, coercion and economy.

These considerations prompt questions concerning the adoption of legal strategies by movements aimed at challenging corporate power. Law cannot be taken uncritically as an empty vessel to be filled with progressive content.Footnote 209 Taken at face value, seemingly neutral and indifferent formalist theories such as Kelsen's are perhaps guilty of something more insidious. The question is whether Adorno's call to respect non-identity offers a glimmer of hope – whether the reflexivity of international lawyers and activist movements as to the uses and limits of law offers something salvageable. Immersed in CLS arguments surrounding legal indeterminacy and instability, Williams nonetheless acknowledges the difficulty in seeing ‘the idealistic or symbolic importance of rights being diminished with reference to the disenfranchised, who experience and express their disempowerment as nothing more or less than the denial of rights’.Footnote 210 Knowledge of the problems with legal strategies must be taken in hand with knowledge of the real-world benefits legal rights produce for subaltern communities.Footnote 211 Such a call also echoes through much of David Kennedy's work.Footnote 212

For his part, Koskenniemi highlights the institutional biases and unequal power dynamics lying behind international law, while retaining a belief that these material circumstances are not necessarily determinative either.Footnote 213 In doing so, Koskenniemi denies that international law has any objectively progressive or emancipatory character, and instead shifts any optimism to an ethic of responsibility inculcated within a reflexive subject.Footnote 214

[N]othing of our ability to challenge the bias is grounded in the law itself. The choice will be just that – a ‘choice’… The decision is made, and its consequences are thus attributable, not to some impersonal logic or structure but to ourselves.Footnote 215

This suggests that a subject aware of the contingency of a given system is ‘more ready to transform the field that is posited by the nature of [its] decision – given that the field, together with its frontiers, is the result of a decision and not the representation of a preceding “real”’.Footnote 216 But such a manoeuvre posits a subject who is ‘able to stand above and separate from his object of analysis… able to detach himself from the world he finds himself in and able to conduct his diagnosis in a space that is not occupied by the very objects he wishes to analyse’.Footnote 217 Such a subject is the mirror image of Koskenniemi's professionally-situated ‘managerialist’ who cannot see beyond the self-imposed limits of legal doctrine.Footnote 218 These characteristically liberal antinomies prompt Singh to question whether the subjects that emerge from Koskenniemi's work are ‘capable of realizing the politics of critical thought’.Footnote 219

For Miéville, reflexivity represents a ‘typically unsatisfactory, postmodern sleight of hand, a suggestion that an impossible manoeuvre can be made simply by being made aware of its impossibility’.Footnote 220 Adorno could be accused of the same; stressing the importance of critical thinking whilst acknowledging thought's inability to positively define the path to a better world.Footnote 221 There is no ‘right living’ in a fundamentally ‘wrong world’.Footnote 222 It is only possible to glimpse the falsity of the existing world immanently through determinate negation of its concepts.Footnote 223 Such is the connection with the positionality of this paper outlined in the Introduction. For Adorno, ‘critical negation of the existing states of affairs… discloses something equally negative: that which exists is not yet what it ought to be, and that what ought to be does not yet exist’.Footnote 224 Adorno could hardly be accused of radical idealism. He was deeply aware that changes in ideas will not necessarily precipitate ‘changes in the fundamental nature of the world’.Footnote 225

Adorno's reticence to place hope in a subject situated in the material circumstances of late-capitalism is well documented.Footnote 226 On this reading, any scope for the activist-reformer to adopt an enlightened empty formalism is always threatened by the alluring pull of identity-thinking in a world structured by the logic of the commodity-form. Any victories in the legal sphere ‘will be predicated on legal forms that not only make the categories ripe for counter-appropriation, but that can only be actualized in the coercive interpretations of the very States and other bodies whose interpretation and actions the radical lawyer is critiquing’.Footnote 227 Yet, these realizations need not prompt the wholesale abandonment of law by activists and scholars. As with Koskenniemi and Laclau, Adorno clearly saw some utopian potentiality, however small, in the Sisyphean struggle of critical thought; ‘the thinking that conceives the difference from what exists’.Footnote 228 International law, as with any system of signification, will always do violence to non-identity. But as Adorno repeatedly emphasized, the conceptual mediation between the subject and object cannot be overcome. Adorno's critical orientation seems to strive for ‘a “lesser violence” in a general economy of violence’.Footnote 229 Indeed, the absence of resistance through critical engagement in the legal sphere will not, on its own, lead to social transformation. Rather it risks losing any ground ceded. In this sense, law is a reality that must be lived with and harnessed, so far as possible, while striving to remain alive to its inherent limitations.

Conclusion

A number of insights concerning the role of law in activist efforts to effect social change can be drawn from the above. First, it is evident that empty formalism could conceivably serve some useful purpose. This is apparent in the field of business and human rights, where formalist logic may be employed in efforts to overcome longstanding doctrinal anxieties concerning the imposition of direct international obligations to corporate actors. By transcending the contractarian elision between law-maker and addressee, Kelsen's framing allows business and human rights advocates to glimpse the doctrinal potential for international law to directly constrain adverse corporate conduct. Koskenniemi's attempt to liberate the content of international law while retaining some semblance of disciplinary autonomy provides similar scope for the activist-reformer to pursue emancipatory projects. Such a stance entreats the subject-lawyer to think beyond seemingly rigid doctrinal and institutional constraints in a fashion common to business and human rights scholarship.

Yet, deeper issues with the adoption of an empty formalist stance are exposed by Adorno's critique of idealist epistemology. Its tendency to treat a subjectively-constituted conception of law as exhaustive serves to obstruct reflection on the material conditions which colour this mode of thought. This is most prominent in Kelsen's formalist framing, which implicitly and uncritically accepts as immutable the underlying social conditions of which it is a product, collapsing the radical separation between is and ought on which it is apparently founded. Yet, for all its flaws, Kelsen's thought is in a sense right. His formalism truthfully, if unthinkingly, mirrors dominant modes of thought in late-capitalism. It adopts the ‘rules of the game’ with an extreme rigour. This factor renders it vulnerable to Adorno's critique, but may also permit it to be taken seriously as part of an enlightened argumentative strategy advancing the progressive interpretation or elaboration of international instruments. The question is whether appeals to the logic of a society built on obfuscation – on the failure to respect the non-identical – can meaningfully challenge that very social order or will instead lead to its strengthening. The foregoing leads to a conclusion that falls somewhere between these polarities – between opportunity and impasse.

In reaching this conclusion, Adorno's critique of identity-thinking serves a dual function. First, it permits a novel critique of formalist jurisprudence, illuminating its subservience to material conditions and undermining its claim to invariance. Yet, combined with the scholarship of Pashukanis and Miéville, Adorno's work facilitates a second, bolder claim. Law itself is characterized as a fundamentally identitarian enterprise. Law is presented as integral to the establishment and preservation of stable exchange relationships. Law is a crucial component of capitalist exchange, permitting the formal equivalence of materially non-equivalent parties to be conceptualized. This insight, coupled with the indeterminacy of legal doctrine, characterizes law as a deceptive mirage through which social domination is preserved – a supposedly egalitarian and impartial phenomenon that is ultimately subservient to socio-economic power. Formalist jurisprudence may propagate this position, but its eschewal will not resolve the deeper problems with law, namely, the intimate relation between law and the underlying power disparities that permit even the most progressive content to be co-opted and distorted.

Yet, the possibility of ‘taking international law seriously, while refusing to see in it hope for progressive politics’ is acknowledged.Footnote 230 Thus, there may be scope for ‘a “principled opportunism”, where… international law is consciously used as a mere tool, to be discarded when not useful’.Footnote 231 In a similar vein, Adorno's insights demonstrate that thought can be used to move beyond dogmatic idealist accounts of law which serve to conceal the material factors that shape the legal form and its content. While unquestionably difficult to obtain, a reflexive stance of this type might permit advocacy groups to use law – including formalist argument – to the extent that it may be exploited for real-world benefits, while acknowledging its susceptibility to counter-appropriation. Despite Adorno's acknowledgment that all thought is mediated by existing material conditions, and thus unable to offer a definite path to emancipation, it at least offers a point of resistance that admits the possibility of a different world. So too, it remains viable to take seriously the opportunity for progressive interpretation of international law, while maintaining a critical awareness of a more fundamental impasse – its inability to transcend the material conditions of which it is in part a product, and the residual danger inherent in the employment of legal strategies.

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Patrick Capps, Rebecca Moosavian, and Adam Ramshaw for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Footnotes

1 Altwicker and Diggelmann Reference Altwicker and Diggelmann2014, 425.

2 Sinclair Reference Sinclair2017, 2.

3 Kennedy Reference Kennedy2000, 348.

4 Bradlow and Hunter Reference Bradlow and Hunter2020.

7 Cook Reference Cook2014, 78.

8 Buck-Morss Reference Buck-Morss1979, 89.

9 Skouretis Reference Skouretis2011, 6.

10 Charter of the United Nations (26 June 1945) 1 UNTS XVI, Preamble.

12 Kennedy Reference Kennedy1994, 335 (emphasis added).

14 Khoury and Whyte Reference Khoury and Whyte2017; Clapham Reference Clapham2006, 3–12.

17 Zerk Reference Zerk2006, 276–77; Weissbrodt and Kruger Reference Weissbrodt, Kruger and Alston2005.

19 Methven O'Brien Reference Methven O'Brien2018.

20 Karavias Reference Karavias2015, 91.

21 d'Aspremont Reference d'Aspremont2011, 13–19; Bergmann and Zerby Reference Bergmann and Zerby1945.

22 Paulson Reference Paulson2008, 37.

23 Leiter Reference Leiter1999, 1144; Reimann Reference Reimann1990, 860.

26 von Bernstorff Reference von Bernstorff2010, 237–38.

27 Shklar Reference Shklar1986, 33–34.

29 Kennedy Reference Kennedy2000, 408.

31 Simpson Reference Simpson1990, 834.

32 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2006, 602.

33 See e.g. Karavias Reference Karavias2013; McConnell Reference McConnell2016; Bittle and Snider Reference Bittle and Snider2013.

34 Kant [1781] Reference Kant1998, 114, Bxxvi.

35 Footnote Ibid., 172, A23/B38.

36 Footnote Ibid., 210, A77.

37 Footnote Ibid., 138, B5.

39 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1967, 193.

40 Portmann Reference Portmann2010, 47; Kelsen Reference Kelsen1949, 185.

41 Montevideo Convention on the Rights and Duties of States (1933) 165 LNTS 17, Article 1.

42 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1952, 314.

43 Hall Reference Hall2001, 300.

44 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1949, 437–38.

45 Paulson Reference Paulson1992, 320.

46 von Bernstorff Reference von Bernstorff2010, 115–16.

47 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1967, 72.

48 Ebenstein Reference Ebenstein1971, 628–39; Ross Reference Ross2001, 192.

49 Ebenstein Reference Ebenstein1969, 151.

51 Paulson Reference Paulson1992, 326–32.

53 Kammerhofer Reference Kammerhofer2011, 260–61.

56 Nevsun Resources Ltd. vs. Araya [2020] SCC 5.

57 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1952, 48–49; Portmann Reference Portmann2010, 177; Collins Reference Collins2016, 179–80.

60 Horkheimer and Adorno [1944] Reference Horkheimer and Adorno1997, xvi.

61 Held Reference Held2004, 148–56; Cook Reference Cook2014, 64–69.

62 Horkheimer and Adorno [1944] Reference Horkheimer and Adorno1997, 8.

63 Kant [1781] Reference Kant1998, 148, B23.

64 Horkheimer and Adorno [1944] Reference Horkheimer and Adorno1997, 11–12.

65 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 149.

66 Cook Reference Cook2014, 37.

67 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 146–48.

68 Jarvis Reference Jarvis1998, 22.

69 Marx and Engels [1867] Reference Marx and Engels2004, 47; Cook Reference Cook2006.

70 Jarvis Reference Jarvis1998, 149.

71 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 183–86.

72 Footnote Ibid., 181.

73 Footnote Ibid., 141.

74 Freyenhagen Reference Freyenhagen2013, 13–14; Adorno Reference Adorno1973, xx.

75 Buck-Morss Reference Buck-Morss1979, 96; Adorno Reference Adorno1977, 127.

76 Chimni Reference Chimni1993, 220.

77 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 135.

78 Cook Reference Cook2014, 62–63.

79 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 12.

81 Kant [1781] Reference Kant1998, 154, A19/B33.

82 Adorno [1956] Reference Adorno2013, 151; Jarvis Reference Jarvis1998, 161.

83 Copleston Reference Copleston1994, 236.

84 Kant [1781] Reference Kant1998, 166, A39/B56.

85 Adorno [1956] Reference Adorno2013, 151.

86 Footnote Ibid., 152.

87 Jarvis Reference Jarvis1998, 162.

88 Adorno [1959] Reference Adorno2002, 234.

89 Cook Reference Cook2014, 39.

91 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 141.

92 Buck-Morss Reference Buck-Morss1979, 80.

93 Jarvis Reference Jarvis1998, 153; O'Connor Reference O'Connor2004, 59–60.

94 Adorno Reference Adorno2005, 249.

95 Footnote Ibid., 253.

96 This perspective is in tension with the social idealism of Philip Allott, an approach stressing the constitutive role of ideas in human reality, as well as their seemingly unconstrained transformative potential: Allott Reference Allott2001, xxii; Allott Reference Allott2016, 186.

97 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 191.

98 Jarvis Reference Jarvis and Huhn2004, 93–94.

99 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 146–48.

100 Marx [1867] Reference Marx1976, 163–77.

101 Footnote Ibid., 166–69.

102 Footnote Ibid., 292, 300–02.

104 Adorno [1959] Reference Adorno2002, 172.

105 Horkheimer and Adorno [1944] Reference Horkheimer and Adorno1997, 7.

106 Chimni Reference Chimni1993, 219.

107 Footnote Ibid., 218–19.

108 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1967, 11; ibid., 219–20.

109 Krajewski Reference Krajewski2020; Nevsun Resources Ltd. vs. Araya [2020] SCC 5.

110 OHCHR, Revised Draft Treaty on Business and Human Rights (16/07/2019) available at: https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/HRBodies/HRCouncil/WGTransCorp/OEIGWG_RevisedDraft_LBI.pdf accessed 26 May 2020.

112 Suganami Reference Suganami2007, 526–28.

113 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1923, 42; von Bernstorff Reference von Bernstorff2010, 45–46.

114 Kammerhofer Reference Kammerhofer2011, 260–61.

115 Adorno Reference Adorno1977, 120–21.

116 Buck-Morss Reference Buck-Morss1979, 70; Cook Reference Cook2014, 69–70; Held Reference Held2004, 213.

118 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1949, 39.

119 Footnote Ibid., 42.

120 Ebenstein Reference Ebenstein1971, 641–42.

123 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1949, 373–76.

125 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 17.

126 Footnote Ibid., 11.

127 Footnote Ibid., 14.

128 Kammerhofer Reference Kammerhofer2009, 239–40.

129 Somek Reference Somek2007, 434.

130 Austin [1832] Reference Austin2001, 20.

131 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1949, 328–30.

132 Footnote Ibid., 331–36.

134 Kammerhofer Reference Kammerhofer2009, 227.

135 Footnote Ibid., 239–40.

136 Footnote Ibid., 241.

137 Footnote Ibid., 244.

138 Footnote Ibid., 243.

143 Jarvis Reference Jarvis1998, 47.

144 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 43.

148 Footnote Ibid., 79.

151 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 79.

153 Footnote Ibid., 114.

154 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 307.

155 Footnote Ibid., 309.

156 Warrington Reference Warrington1980; Head Reference Head2008, 215–18.

157 Marx [1894] Reference Marx1991, 442; Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 90–93.

158 Jessop Reference Jessop1990, 59.

160 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 307; Jarvis Reference Jarvis and Huhn2004, 93–94.

161 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 97; Koen Reference Koen2011, 144–47.

162 Kelsen Reference Kelsen1955, 89–111.

163 Footnote Ibid., 44.

164 Footnote Ibid., 5.

165 Jarvis Reference Jarvis1998, 184.

166 Footnote Ibid., 51–52.

167 Cook Reference Cook2014, 33–34.

168 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 122–28; Pashukanis [Reference Pashukanis1924] Reference Pashukanis1983, 89–93; Jessop Reference Jessop1990, 52.

170 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 140–41.

171 Footnote Ibid., 191.

172 Footnote Ibid., 128.

173 Charter of the United Nations (26 June 1945) 1 UNTS XVI, Article 2(1).

176 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 141.

177 Marx [1867] Reference Marx1976, 344.

178 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2006, 140–41; Purvis Reference Purvis1991, 113.

179 Kennedy Reference Kennedy1985, 999.

180 Footnote Ibid., 961.

181 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2006, 67, 71.

182 Footnote Ibid., 591.

183 Footnote Ibid., 589.

184 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2001, 500.

185 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2006, 519–21.

186 Footnote Ibid., 602.

187 Footnote Ibid., 513.

189 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2006, 568; Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2001, 504.

191 Devenney Reference Devenney2004, 63.

192 Laclau Reference Laclau1997, 17.

193 Laclau Reference Laclau1990, 220.

194 Footnote Ibid., 30.

196 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2001, 503.

197 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2006, 610.

198 Similarly, d'Aspremont accepts some necessary indeterminacy in both the form and content of international law, while emphasizing that formal indeterminacy may be reduced with reference to the social conventions and social practices of international lawyers and law-applying authorities. As discussed below, such social actors are inescapably situated within, and partially shaped by, particular material, social and institutional settings: d'Aspremont Reference d'Aspremont2011, 138–47.

199 Laclau Reference Laclau1990, 32; Laclau and Mouffe Reference Laclau and Mouffe1985, 142–43.

202 Marks Reference Marks2003, 144–45.

203 Knox Reference Knox2009, 417.

204 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 292.

205 Knox Reference Knox2009, 426.

206 Footnote Ibid., 420–23.

207 Footnote Ibid., 433.

208 Footnote Ibid., 427; Marks Reference Marks2003, 144; Chimni Reference Chimni1993, 208.

209 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 119.

210 Williams Reference Williams1987, 405.

211 Footnote Ibid., 410.

212 Kennedy Reference Kennedy2002, 102; Charlesworth Reference Charlesworth2002, 127.

213 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2006, 598.

214 Footnote Ibid., 536.

215 Footnote Ibid., 615.

216 Beardsworth Reference Beardsworth1996, 12.

217 Singh Reference Singh2016, 705–06.

218 Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2009, 15; Ibid., 717.

220 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 59.

221 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 352.

222 Adorno [1951] Reference Adorno2005, 39; Freyenhagen Reference Freyenhagen2013, 52.

223 Pritchard Reference Pritchard2002, 301–06.

224 Cook Reference Cook2014, 80.

225 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 59; Linarelli, Salomon and Sornarajah Reference Linarelli, Salomon and Sornarajah2018, 240.

226 Buck-Morss Reference Buck-Morss1979, 24–25.

227 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 304.

228 Adorno Reference Adorno1973, 313; Ibid., 89–90.

229 Beardsworth Reference Beardsworth1996, 219.

230 Miéville Reference Miéville2004, 60.

231 Knox Reference Knox2009, 433.

References

Adorno, Theodor. [1951] 2005. Minima Moralia. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. [1956] 2013. Against Epistemology: A Metacritique. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. [1959] 2002. Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. [1968] 2000. Introduction to Sociology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. 1973. Negative Dialectics. New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. 1976. “Introduction.” In The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology, edited by Adorno, Theodor, et al. , 167. London: Heinemann.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. 1977. “The Actuality of Philosophy.” Telos 31: 120–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. 2005. “On Subject and Object.” In Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords, 245–58. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Allott, Philip. 2001. Eunomia: New Order for a New World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allott, Philip. 2016. Eutopia: New Philosophy and New Law for a Troubled World. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Altwicker, Tilmann, and Diggelmann, Oliver. 2014. “How is Progress Constructed in International Legal Scholarship?European Journal of International Law 25(2): 425–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, John. [1832] 2001. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Beardsworth, Richard. 1996. Derrida and the Political. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bergmann, Gustav, and Zerby, Lewis. 1945. “The Formalism in Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law.” Ethics 55(2): 110–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernstein, Jay M. 2002. “Re-enchanting Nature.” In Reading McDowell: On Mind and World, edited by Smith, Nicholas, 217–45. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bittle, Steven, and Snider, Laureen. 2013. “Examining the Ruggie Report: Can Voluntary Guidelines Tame Global Capitalism?Critical Criminology 21(2): 177–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradlow, Daniel, and Hunter, David, eds. 2020. Advocating Social Change Through International Law. Boston: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buck-Morss, Susan. 1979. The Origin of Negative Dialectics. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1986. “Hans Kelsen and International Law.” In Essays on Kelsen, edited by Tur, Richard and Twining, William, 321–35. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Charlesworth, Hilary. 2002. “Author! Author! A Response to David Kennedy.” Harvard Human Rights Journal 15: 127–32.Google Scholar
Chimni, Bhupinder S. 1993. International Law and World Order: A Critique of Contemporary Approaches. New Delhi: Sage.Google Scholar
Choudhury, Barnali. 2011. “Exception Provisions as a Gateway to Incorporating Human Rights Issues into International Investment Agreements.” Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 49: 670716.Google Scholar
Clapham, Andrew. 2006. Human Rights Obligations of Non-State Actors. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Richard. 2016. The Institutional Problem in Modern International Law. Oxford: Hart/Bloomsbury Publishing.Google Scholar
Cook, Deborah. 2006. “Adorno's Critical Materialism.” Philosophy and Social Criticism 32(6): 719–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cook, Deborah. 2014. Adorno on Nature. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copleston, Frederick. 1994. A History of Philosophy, vol. 6. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
d'Aspremont, Jean. 2011. Formalism and the Sources of International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 1996. “Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism.” In Deconstruction and Pragmatism, edited by Mouffe, Chantal, 7990. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Deva, Surya, and Bilchitz, David, eds. 2017. Building a Treaty on Business and Human Rights: Context and Contours. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devenney, Mark. 2004. Ethics and Politics in Contemporary Theory. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ebenstein, William. 1969. The Pure Theory of Law. New York: AM Kelly.Google Scholar
Ebenstein, William. 1971. “The Pure Theory of Law: Demythologizing Legal Thought.” California Law Review 59(3): 617–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freyenhagen, Fabian. 2013. Adorno's Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Golder, Ben. 2016. “Theorizing Human Rights.” In The Oxford Handbook of the Theory of International Law, edited by Orford, Anne and Hoffmann, Florian, 684700. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hall, Stephen. 2001. “The Persistent Spectre: Natural Law, International Order and the Limits of Legal Positivism.” European Journal of International Law 12(2): 269307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hammer, Stefan. 1999. “A Neo-Kantian Theory of Knowledge in Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law.” In Normativity and Norms: Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Theory, edited by Paulson, Stanley and Litschewski-Paulson, Bonnie, 177–94. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hang, Sharon. 2014. “Investing in Human Rights: Using Bilateral Investment Treaties to Hold Multinational Corporations Liable for Labour Rights Violations.” Fordham International Law Journal 37(4): 1215–64.Google Scholar
Head, Michael. 2008. Evgeny Pashukanis: A Critical Reappraisal. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Held, David. 2004. Introduction to Critical Theory. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Hoffmann, Florian. 2009. “Human Rights, the Self and the Other: Reflections on a Pragmatic Theory of Human Rights.” In International Law and its Others, edited by Orford, Anne, 221–44. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, Max, and Adorno, Theodor. [1944] 1997. Dialectic of Enlightenment. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Jarvis, Simon. 1998. Adorno: A Critical Introduction. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Jarvis, Simon. 2004. “Adorno, Marx, Materialism.” In The Cambridge Companion to Adorno, edited by Huhn, Tom, 79100. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jessop, Bob. 1990. State Theory: Putting Capitalism in its Place. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Kammerhofer, Jörg. 2009. “Kelsen – Which Kelsen? A Reapplication of Pure Theory to International Law.” Leiden Journal International Law 22(2): 225–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kammerhofer, Jörg. 2011. Uncertainty in International Law. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kammerhofer, Jörg. 2016. “International Legal Positivism.” In Oxford Handbook of the Theory of International Law, edited by Orford, Anne and Hoffman, Florian, 407–26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. [1781] 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Karavias, Markos. 2013. Corporate Obligations under International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karavias, Markos. 2015. “Shared Responsibility and Multinational Enterprises.” Netherlands International Law Review 62(1): 91117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 1923. Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre: Entwickelt aus der Lehre von Rechtssatz. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 1949. General Theory of Law and State. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 1952. Principles of International Law. New York: Rinehart & Co.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 1955. The Communist Theory of Law. New York: Frederick A. Praeger Inc.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 1967. The Pure Theory of Law. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. 2000. “Legal Formalism and the Pure Theory of Law (1929).” In Weimar: A Jurisprudence in Crisis, edited by Jacobson, Arthur and Schlink, Bernhard, 7683. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kennedy, David. 1994. “A New World Order: Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow.” Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems 4(2): 329–76.Google Scholar
Kennedy, David. 2000. “When Renewal Repeats: Thinking Against the Box.” NYU Journal of International Law and Politics 32: 335500.Google Scholar
Kennedy, David. 2002. “The International Human Rights Movement: Part of the Problem?Harvard Human Rights Journal 15: 101–26.Google Scholar
Kennedy, Duncan. 1985. “The Role of Law in Economic Thought: Essays on the Fetishism of Commodities.” American University Law Review 34: 9391001.Google Scholar
Khoury, Stefanie, and Whyte, David. 2017. Corporate Human Rights Violations: Global Prospects for Legal Action. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Knox, Robert. 2009. “Marxism, International Law and Political Strategy.” Leiden Journal of International Law 22(3): 413–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koen, Raymond. 2011. “In Defence of Pashukanism.” Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 14(4): 104–69.Google Scholar
Koskenniemi, Martti. 2001. The Gentle Civilizer of Nations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koskenniemi, Martti. 2006. From Apology to Utopia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koskenniemi, Martti. 2009. “The Politics of International Law – 20 Years Later.” European Journal of International Law 20(1): 719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koskenniemi, Martti. 2017. “Between Commitment and Cynicism.” In International Law as a Profession, edited by d'Aspremont, Jean, 3866. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krajewski, Markus. 2020. “A Nightmare or a Noble Dream? Establishing Investor Obligations Through Treaty-Making and Treaty-Application.” Business and Human Rights Journal 5(2): 105–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laclau, Ernesto. 1990. Reflections on the Revolution of Our Time. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Laclau, Ernesto. 1997. “Converging on an Open Quest.” Diacritics 27(1): 1619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laclau, Ernesto. 2007. “Why do Empty Signifiers Matter in Politics.” In Ernesto Laclau Emancipation(s), 3646. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal. 1985. Hegemony and Socialist Strategy. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Leiter, Brian. 1999. “Review: Positivism, Formalism, Realism.” Columbia Law Review 99(4): 1138–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linarelli, John, Salomon, Margot E., and Sornarajah, M.. 2018. The Misery of International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marks, Susan. 2003. The Riddle of All Constitutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, Karl. [1867] 1976. Capital, vol. 1. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. [1894] 1991. Capital, vol. 3. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1973. Grundrisse. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl, and Engels, Friedrich. [1867] 2004. The German Ideology. New York: International Publishers.Google Scholar
McConnell, Lee. 2016. Extracting Accountability from Non-State Actors in International Law. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McConnell, Lee. 2017. “Assessing the Feasibility of a Business and Human Rights Treaty.” International and Comparative Law Quarterly 66(1): 143–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Methven O'Brien, Claire. 2018. “The Home State Duty to Regulate Human Rights Impacts of TNCs Abroad: A Rebuttal.” Business and Human Rights Journal 3(1): 4773.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miéville, China. 2004. Between Equal Rights: A Marxist Theory of International Law. Boston: Brill.Google Scholar
Miller, Russell. 2008. “Paradoxes of Personality: Transnational Corporations, Non-Governmental Organizations and Human Rights.” In Progress in International Law, edited by Miller, Russell and Bratspies, Rebecca M., 381406. Leiden: Martinus Nihoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Connor, Brian. 2004. Adorno's Negative Dialectic. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pashukanis, Evgeny. [1924] 1983. Law and Marxism: A General Theory. London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
Pashukanis, Evgeny. 1980. “Selections from the Encyclopaedia of State and Law.” In Pashukanis: Selected Writings on Marxism and Law, edited by Beirne, Piers and Sharlet, Robert, 165–85. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Paulson, Stanley. 1992. “The Neo-Kantian Dimension of Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 12(3): 311–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paulson, Stanley. 2008. “Formalism, Free Law, and the Cognition Quandary: Hans Kelsen's Approaches to Legal Interpretation.” University of Queensland Law Journal 27(2): 739.Google Scholar
Portmann, Roland. 2010. Legal Personality in International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, Elizabeth. 2002. “Bilderverbot Meets Body in Adorno's Inverse Theology.” Harvard Theological Law Review 95(3): 291318.Google Scholar
Purvis, Nigel. 1991. “Critical Legal Studies in Public International Law.” Harvard International Law Journal 32(1): 81127.Google Scholar
Reimann, Mathias. 1990. “Nineteenth Century German Legal Science.” Boston College Law Review 31: 837–97.Google Scholar
Ross, Hamish. 2001. “Hans Kelsen and the Utopia of Theoretical Purism.” Kings Law Journal 12(2): 174–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryan, Michael. 1982. Marxism and Deconstruction. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Ryngaert, Cedric. 2010. “Imposing International Duties on Non-State Actors and the Legitimacy of International Law.” In Non-State Actor Dynamics in International Law, edited by Ryngaert, Cedric and Noortmann, Math, 6991. Surrey: Ashgate Publishing.Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith. 1986. Legalism: Law, Morals and Political Trials. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Simpson, Alfred William Brian. 1990. “Legal Iconoclasts and Legal Ideals.” University of Cincinnati Law Review 58(3): 819–44.Google Scholar
Sinclair, Guy F. 2017. To Reform the World: International Organizations and the Making of Modern States. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singh, Sahib. 2016. “Koskenniemi's Images of the International Lawyer.” Leiden Journal of International Law 29(3): 699726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skouretis, Thomas. 2011. The Notion of Progress in International Law Discourse. The Hague: TMC Asser Press.Google Scholar
Somek, Alexander. 2007. “Kelsen Lives.” European Journal of International Law 18(3): 409–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suganami, Hidemi. 2007. “Understanding Sovereignty through Kelsen/Schmitt.” Review of International Studies 33(3): 511–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tur, Richard. 1986. “The Kelsenian Enterprise.” In Essays on Kelsen, edited by Tur, Richard and Twining, William, 149–86. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Van Dam, Cees, and Gregor, Filip. 2017. “Corporate Responsibility to Respect Human Rights vis-à-vis Legal Duty of Care.” In Human Rights in Business, edited by Álvarez Rubio, Juan José and Yiannibas, Katerina, 119–38. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
von Bernstorff, Jochen. 2010. The Public International Law Theory of Hans Kelsen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warrington, Ronnie. 1980. “Standing Pashukanis on His Head.” Capital and Class 12: 102–06.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weissbrodt, David, and Kruger, Muria. 2005. “Human Rights Responsibilities of Businesses as Non-State Actors.” In Non State Actors and Human Rights, edited by Alston, Philip, 315–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Patricia. 1987. “Alchemical Notes: Reconstructing Ideals from Deconstructed Rights.” Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 22(2): 401–34.Google Scholar
Zerk, Jennifer. 2006. Multinationals and Corporate Social Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar