Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T23:24:11.207Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Expectant Fathers, Abortion, and Embryos

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Today, multiple legal theories of parenthood interact to encompass all sorts of families. Adults and children bound through adoption, step-parenting, and assisted reproductive technologies (ART) demand familial recognition through some combination of biology, functionality, technology, and intent.

In the context of children born through ART, many scholars have proposed a more robust use of intent as a rule for identifying legal parents. When used to identify parents, intent asks who planned to become the parent of a child, and is often helpful when multiple adults simultaneously agreed to bring a child into the world. For example, in the case of surrogacy, as many as five adults — two intended parents, a gestational surrogate, and both a sperm and egg donor — could all contribute to bringing a single child into the world. Not only does intent provide a practical answer to such modern parentage dilemmas, but it recognizes the often-minimized emotional investment of men who wish to be fathers.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

See, e.g., Purvis, D. E., “Intended Parents and the Problem of Perspective,” Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 24, no. 2 (2012): 210253.Google Scholar
See Purvis, D. E., “The Origin of Parental Rights: Labor, Intent, and Fathers,” Florida State University Law Review 41, no. 3 (2014): 645696.Google Scholar
See Reber v. Reiss, 42 A.3d 1131 (Pa. Super. 2012), discussed infra Section II.A.Google Scholar
Hochschild, A. R. Machung, A., The Second Shift (New York: Penguin Books, 2003): At 4; Sanchez, L. Thomson, E., “Becoming Mothers and Fathers: Parenthood, Gender, and the Division of Labor,” Gender and Society 11, no. 6 (1997): 747–772, at 765.Google Scholar
See Greenhouse, L. Siegel, R. B., “Before (and After) Roe v. Wade: New Questions About Backlash,” Yale Law Journal 120, no. 8 (2011): 2028–287, at 2042–243; see also Ziegler, M., “Abortion and the Constitutional Right (Not) to Procreate,” University of Richmond Law Review 48, no. 4 (2014): 1263–1317, at 1278 (quoting Jan Liebman of the National Organization for Women arguing, “The woman is the one who carries the fetus, and gives birth to it, so she should be the only one to decide whether to carry it to term”).Google Scholar
Steinem, G., “The Verbal Karate of Florynce R. Kennedy, Esq.,” Ms. Magazine, March 1973 (quoting Florynce Kennedy), available at <http://www.msmagazine.com/summer2011/ver-balkarate.asp> (last visited April 14, 2015).+(last+visited+April+14,+2015).>Google Scholar
Planned Parenthood of Cent. Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U.S. 52, 69 (1976).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Bruno, C., “A Right to Decide Not to Be a Legal Father: Gonzales v. Carhart and the Acceptance of Emotional Harm as a Constitutionally Protected Interest,” George Washington Law Review 77, no. 1 (2008): 141171.Google Scholar
Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 165 n.67 (1973).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Lehr v. Robertson, 463 U.S. 248 (1983); Parham v. Hughes, 441 U.S. 347 (1979); Caban v. Mohammed, 441 U.S. 380 (1979); Stanley v. Illinois, 405 U.S.645 (1972).Google Scholar
Danforth, 428 U.S. at 58.Google Scholar
See Ziegler, , supra note 5, at 1277.Google Scholar
Id., at 1290.Google Scholar
Danforth, 428 U.S. at 69.Google Scholar
Id., at 93 (White, J., dissenting)Google Scholar
Id., at 90–91 (Stewart, J., concurring).Google Scholar
Id., at 71.Google Scholar
See Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992).Google Scholar
Id., at 895–896. The phrase “a living child raised by both” is important, as unwed biological fathers lack a constitutional interest in their child until they create a substantial relationship with the child. See Purvis, , supra note 2. If the biological father is not involved in raising the child, in other words, he lacks a cognizable constitutional interest in a relationship with the child.Google Scholar
Id., at 896.Google Scholar
Hiester, E. M., “Child Support Statutes and the Father's Right Not to Procreate,” Ave Maria Law Review 2 (2004): 213241, at 214–215.Google Scholar
See Lichtenberg, I. D. LeClair, J. B., “Advocating Equal Protection for Men in Reproductive Rights and Responsibilities,” Southern University Law Review 38, no. 1 (2010): 5378, at 63.Google Scholar
H.B. 252, 2009 Leg., 128th Sess. (Oh. 2009), available at <http://archives.legislature.state.oh.us/bills.cfm?ID=128_HB_252> (last visited April 24, 2015).+(last+visited+April+24,+2015).>Google Scholar
See Totz, M. A., “What's Good for the Goose Is Good for the Gander: Toward Recognition of Men's Reproductive Rights,” Northern Illinois University Law Review 15, no. 1 (1994): 141236, at 142–143.Google Scholar
Id., at 177.Google Scholar
See Pahl, M. R., “It Takes Two, Baby: Fathers, the Tort of Conversion, and Its Application to the Abortion of Pre-Viability Fetuses,” Whittier Law Review 24, no. 1 (2002): 221251.Google Scholar
See S.F. v. State ex rel. T.M., 695 So. 2d 1186, 1187 (Ala. Civ. App. 1996); see also State v. Frisard, 694 So. 2d 1032, 1035 (La. Ct. App. 1997) (alleging that a woman saved semen in a condom after oral sex and used it to impregnate herself).Google Scholar
See Jones, R., “Inequality from Gender-Neutral Laws: Why Must Male Victims of Statutory Rape Pay Child Support for Children Resulting from their Victimization?” Georgia Law Review 36, no. 1 (2002): 411463, at 432–443.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Bruno, C., “A Right to Decide Not to be a Legal Father: Gonzales v. Carhart and the Acceptance of Emotional Harm as a Constitutionally Protected Interest,” George Washington Law Review 77, no. 1 (2008): 141171; McCulley, M. G., “The Male Abortion: The Putative Father's Right to Terminate His Interests In and Obligations to the Unborn Child,” Journal of Law & Policy 7, no. 1 (1998): 1–55 (proposing a model statute allowing putative fathers to terminate parental status for several reasons, including that the putative father offered to pay for an abortion); Hiester, E. M., “Child Support Statutes and the Father's Right Not to Procreate,” Ave Maria Law Review 2 (2004): 213–241, at 239–240 (proposing model statute giving biological father the ability to terminate parental status for as long as the biological mother would have access to legal abortion).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Wallis v. Smith, 22 P.3d 683 (N.M. App. 2001); Welzenbach v. Powers, 660 A.2d 1133 (N.H. 1995); Stephen K. v. Roni L., 164 Cal. Rptr. 618 (Ct. App. 1980).Google Scholar
See Wallis, , 22 P.3d at 685; Stephen K, 164 Cal. Rptr. at 621 (adding that even had defendant been taking birth control pills, the rate of pregnancy prevention of birth control pills is less than 100%).Google Scholar
Dubay v. Wells, 506 F.3d 422, 426–8 (6th Cir. 2007).Google Scholar
The National Center for Men, available at <http://www.nationalcenterformen.org/index.shtml> (last visited April 14, 2015).+(last+visited+April+14,+2015).>Google Scholar
Fairyington, S., “The Parent Trap: Paternal Rights and Abortion,” Elle, March 17, 2013, available at <http://www.elle.com/life-love/society-career/the-parent-trap-paternal-rights-abortion-445117> (last visited April 14, 2015).+(last+visited+April+14,+2015).>Google Scholar
Hales, S. D., “Abortion and Fathers’ Rights,” in Humber, J. M. Almeder, R. F., eds., Biomedical Ethics Reviews: Reproduction, Technology, and Rights (Totowa: Humana Press, 1996): 526, at 11–12; see also Owens, L. L., “Coerced Parenthood as Family Policy: Feminism, the Moral Agency of Women, and Men's ‘Right to Choose,”’ Alabama Civil Rights & Civil Liberties Law Review 5 (2013): 1–33, at 18 (“Though he cannot choose whether or not a biologically-related fetus will be carried to term, the man should have the choice whether to actually be a parent (in the legal and social senses), even when he cannot decide whether he will become a biological parent.”); Jacobs, M. B., “Intentional Parenthood's Influence: Rethinking Procreative Autonomy and Federal Paternity Establishment Policy,” American University Journal of Gender, Social Policy and the Law 20, no. 3 (2012): 489–508 (questioning “why a man who has no intent or desire to be a father should be adjudicated a legal father against his will”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Hiester, , supra note 31, at 213 n.4.Google Scholar
Gaynor, M., “The Lesson of ‘Roe v. Wade for Men’: Making Abortion a Right Was Wrong,” RenewAmerica.com, March 10, 2006, available at <http://www.renewamerica.com/columns/gaynor/060310> (last visited April 14, 2015); see also Lopez, K., “Abortion Leads to Emotional Damage for Men, Too,” The Grand Island Independent, March 25, 2006, available at <http://www.priestsforlife.org/clippings/2006/06-03-25men.htm> (last visited April 14, 2015).+(last+visited+April+14,+2015);+see+also+Lopez,+K.,+“Abortion+Leads+to+Emotional+Damage+for+Men,+Too,”+The+Grand+Island+Independent,+March+25,+2006,+available+at++(last+visited+April+14,+2015).>Google Scholar
Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 927–28 (1992) (Blackmun, J., dissenting in part).Google Scholar
In the context of abortion, where prochoice advocates and the core holdings of Roe v. Wade and other abortion cases see the autonomy of the pregnant woman as central to the question, antiabortion advocates believe the status and attendant rights of the fetus as a person should decide the question. In pre-embryo disputes, many people would similarly grant the pre-embryos a right to life (and thus right to be implanted and developed to term), so the characterization of such disputes as expectational interest versus expectational interest is incomplete. Because none of the cases I will discuss treat preembryos as persons, however, the analysis is not altered by this caveat.Google Scholar
See Sanger, , About Abortion, supra note 38, at 862.Google Scholar
Use of the term pre-embryo versus embryo is disputed. On the one hand, many courts and commentators have found the distinction helpful, often using a rubric that a pre-embryo is developed at most for fourteen days and is not yet implanted in a woman's uterus. See Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 592–94 (1992); Weber, S. A., “Dismantling the Dictated Moral Code: Modifying Louisiana's In Vitro Fertilization Statutes to Protect Patients' Procreative Liberty,” Loyola Law Review 51, no. 3 (2005): 549601, at 559–560. On the other, the term pre-embryo has been criticized as an artificial distinction aimed at creating a moral or conceptual divide where none exists. See Zekan Makdisi, J. M., “Genetically Correct: The Political Use of Reproductive Terminology,” Pepperdine Law Review 32, no. 1 (2004): 1–37, at 5–17. For specificity and ease of use, I use the term pre-embryo.Google Scholar
See Upchurch, A. K., “The Deep Freeze: A Critical Examination of the Resolution of Frozen Embryo Disputes through the Adversarial Process,” Florida State University Law Review 33, no. 2 (2005): 395435, at 399–400.Google Scholar
See Kass v. Kass, 696 N.E.2d 174 (N.Y. 1998).Google Scholar
Id., at 180; see also Robertson, J. A., “Precommitment Strategies for Disposition of Frozen Embryos,” Emory Law Journal 50, no. 4 (2001): 9891046, at 1006.Google Scholar
See In re Marriage of Dahl and Angle, 194 P.3d 834 (Or. App. 2008); Roman v. Roman, 193 S.W.3d 40 (Tex. App. 2006); Litowitz v. Litowitz, 48 P.3d 261 (Wash. 2002) (en banc).Google Scholar
In re Dahl and Angle, 194 P.3d at 837.Google Scholar
See In re Marriage of Witten, 672 N.W.2d 768 (Iowa 2003).Google Scholar
Coleman, C. H., “Procreative Liberty and Contemporaneous Choice: An Inalienable Rights Approach to Frozen Embryo Disputes,” Minnesota Law Review 84, no. 1 (1999): 55127, at 59.Google Scholar
See Strasser, M. P., “You Take the Embryos But I Get the House (and the Business): Recent Trends in Awards Involving Embryos Upon Divorce,” Buffalo Law Review 57, no. 4 (2009): 11591225.Google Scholar
See In re Witten, 672 N.W.2d 768. One case from Massachusetts used the contemporaneous mutual consent approach, but only after determining that the written agreements as to disposition of the stored pre-embryos were unenforceable because the ex-husband signed blank consent forms, which his ex-wife filled in later stating that in the event of separation their wishes were that the pre-embryos be implanted in the wife. See A.Z. v. B.Z., 431 Mass. 150 (2000).Google Scholar
See Davis v. Davis, 1989 WL 140495 (Tenn. Cir. Ct. 1989).Google Scholar
See Davis v. Davis, 1990 WL 130807, *2 (Tenn. App. 1990).Google Scholar
Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 598 (Tenn. 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 603.Google Scholar
Id., at 604; see also Davis, 1990 WL 130807, at n.1.Google Scholar
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604.Google Scholar
See J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707, 711 (N.J. 2001) (quoting J.B. v. M.B., 331 N.J. Super. 223, 232 (2000)).Google Scholar
Id., at 720.Google Scholar
See Reber v. Reiss, 42 A.3d 1131, 1133 (Pa. Super. 2012).Google Scholar
Id., at 1134.Google Scholar
Id., at 1142.Google Scholar
Szafranski v. Dunston, 993 N.E.2d 502, 503 (Ill.App. 1 Dist. 2013).Google Scholar
Id., at 505.Google Scholar
Id., at 517–518.Google Scholar
Kass v. Kass, 696 N.E.2d 174, 179 n.4 (N.Y. 1998).Google Scholar
This is in contrast to the approach taken in other countries. For example, Israel gives significant weight to the desire to become a parent through use of frozen embryos. See. Waldman, E., “Cultural Priorities Revealed: The Development and Regulation of Assisted Reproduction in the United States and Israel,” Health Matrix: Journal of Law-Medicine 16, no. 1 (2006): 65106.Google Scholar
See Cohen, I. G., “The Right Not to be a Genetic Parent?” Southern California Law Review 81, no. 6 (2008): 11151196, at 1194–1195.Google Scholar
See Madeira, J. L., “Woman Scorned?: Resurrecting Infertile Women's Decision-Making Autonomy,” Maryland Law Review 71, no. 2 (2012): 339410.Google Scholar
One scholar who argues that courts should more strongly credit the difficulty that older unpartnered women face in becoming mothers supports her argument with data on what she terms “disappearing dads,” explicitly arguing that courts should credit the emotional stake held by women because men view fatherhood as simply writing checks. See Waldman, E., “The Parent Trap: Uncovering the Myth of ‘Coerced Parenthood’ in Frozen Embryo Disputes,” American University Law Review 53, no. 5 (2004): 1021–162.Google Scholar
Davis v. Davis, 1989 WL 140495 (Tenn. Cir. Sept. 21, 1989).Google Scholar
Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 590 n4 (Tenn. 1992).Google Scholar
Reber v. Reiss, 42 A.3d at 1139.Google Scholar
See, e.g., In re A.C., 533 A.2d 611 (D.C. 1987); Jefferson v. Griffin Spaulding County Hospital Authority, 274 S.E.2d 457 (Ga. 1981).Google Scholar
See Parness, J. A., “Pregnant Dads: The Crimes and Other Misconduct of Expectant Fathers,” Oregon Law Review 72, no. 4 (1993): 901918, at 906–908; Johnsen, D., “Shared Interests: Promoting Healthy Births without Sacrificing Women's Liberty,” Hastings Law Journal 43, no. 3 (1992): 569–614, at 571.Google Scholar
See Fernandez, M. Eckholm, E., “Pregnant, and Forced to Stay on Life Support,” New York Times, January 7, 2014, at A1.Google Scholar
Matsumura, K. T., “Public Policing of Intimate Agreements,” Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 25, no. 1 (2013): 159215, at 189 & n.230 (quoting Blankenhorn, D., Op-Ed., “How My View on Gay Marriage Changed,” New York Times, June 22, 2012, available at <http://www.nytimes.com/2012/06/23/opinion/how-my-view-on-gay-marriage-changed.html> (last visited April 14, 2015)).Google Scholar