Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-c654p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-26T07:08:53.191Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evolutionary and Ecological conceptualization of dynamic capabilities: Identifying elements of the Teece and Eisenhardt schools

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 July 2015

Felix Arndt*
Affiliation:
Nottingham University Business School China, University of Nottingham, Ningbo, China
Norbert Bach
Affiliation:
Faculty of Economic Sciences and Media, TU Ilmenau, Germany
*
Corresponding author: ffarndt@gmail.com
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press and Australian and New Zealand Academy of Management 2015 

Advancing Dynamic Capability Research Through Evolutionary Reasoning

Evolutionary theory has laid the foundations for the development of dynamic capabilities (Arndt, Pierce, & Teece, Reference Arndt, Pierce and Teeceforthcoming). The triad of variation, selection, and retention is a powerful paradigm that helps to explain the emergence, development, retainment, and replacement of dynamic capabilities (Helfat & Peteraf, Reference Helfat and Peteraf2003). However, despite dynamic capabilities being an inherently longitudinal construct, much research has used cross-sectional inquiries.

In this research note, we aim at refining some arguments made by Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) regarding inquiries that advance the evolutionary nature of dynamic capabilities. Although Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) make an important step with their study toward establishing an evolutionarily informed research agenda within the dynamic capability literature, we also note that the article would benefit from a clear separation of convoluted conceptual framings and empirical operationalization. In both existing conceptualizations of dynamic capabilities (according to Teece, Pisano, & Shuen, Reference Teece, Pisano and Shuen1997 and Eisenhardt & Martin, Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000), evolutionary elements play a primary role; only the emphasis of different elements differs. These points need to be taken into account and resolved when applying a Darwinian framework to dynamic capabilities, as Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) suggest.

We make three contributions in this research note. First, we expand the study by Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) by clarifying the evolutionary elements of dynamic capabilities and how they are implicated in existing frameworks describing dynamic capabilities. By no means has the literature ignored the evolutionary paradigm implicated in dynamic capabilities. However, we agree with Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) that there is no common understanding of the evolutionary paradigm that may be the origin for some confusion around dynamic capabilities (e.g., see Arend & Bromiley, Reference Arend and Bromiley2009). Second, a more thorough investigation of the variation–selection–retention paradigm leverages our further arguments regarding a separation of the frameworks by Teece, Pisano, and Shuen (Reference Teece, Pisano and Shuen1997) and Eisenhardt and Martin (Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000). Although the two frameworks feature some commonalities and may have some common ground, they are based on different evolutionary approaches. This observation has theoretical and empirical implications. Third, we suggest that the empirical inquiry of Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) would have benefited from a different level of analysis. We argue that the level of analysis may be different for each framework and that this difference needs to be taken into account for a meaningful analysis. Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) use the firm level of analysis, but really test ‘best practices’ in the sense of Eisenhardt and Martin (Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000). We suggest that for these best practices the unit of analysis should be oriented toward the industry level following a population ecology approach.

The remainder of this research note proceeds as follows. In the next section, we introduce dynamic capabilities as an evolutionary concept. We show how the different evolutionary elements variation, selection, and retention are implicated in dynamic capabilities. Then, we discuss the differences and inconsistencies between Galvin et al.’s theoretical analysis and their empirical investigation. Finally, we illustrate how these insights can inform future research and an evolutionary-driven research agenda.

The Variation–Selection–Retention Paradigm and Dynamic Capabilities

Dynamic capabilities follow an evolutionary tradition (Agarwal & Selen, Reference Agarwal and Selen2013). Peteraf, Di Stefano, and Verona (Reference Peteraf, Di Stefano and Verona2013) identify two distinct schools of dynamic capabilities. Both schools identify dynamic capabilities as a source of competitive advantage. Although the Teece, Pisano, and Shuen (Reference Teece, Pisano and Shuen1997) school shows how idiosyncratic dynamic capabilities lead to sustained competitive advantage, the Eisenhardt and Martin (Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000) school argues that dynamic capabilities often appear in the form of best practices, change the form in which they become observable in moderately and rapidly changing environments, and lead to temporary competitive advantage only. Both concepts build on evolutionary elements.

In their seminal article, Zollo and Winter (Reference Zollo and Winter2002) describe the variation–selection–retention logic of the knowledge evolution cycle. Herein, variation describes a firm’s externally and internally stimulated exploration processes. Selection refers to the evaluation of new opportunities that are the result of variation and includes a firm’s power constellations and legitimization processes. Retention includes diffusion (replication) and learning processes through rolling out solutions to address and exploit opportunities. In doing so, Zollo and Winter (Reference Zollo and Winter2002) expand the Teece tradition of studying idiosyncratic processes at the firm level. However, they also confirm one of the key differences between the Teece tradition and Eisenhardt and Martin (Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000) tradition. The degree of environmental change alters the emphasis of the evolutionary elements. According to Eisenhardt and Martin (Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000), in moderately changing environments the emphasis is on variation, whereas in rapidly changing environments the emphasis changes to selection. In such environments, dynamic capabilities degenerate to simple rules rather than more complex decision-making processes as the benefits of knowledge retention become increasingly transient.

Although Teece, Pisano, and Shuen (Reference Teece, Pisano and Shuen1997) rely on the idea of Nelson and Winter’s evolutionary theory that is routine based, Eisenhardt and Martin (Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000) refer to dynamic capabilities as best practices implicitly differentiating between firm internal selection and industry-level selection and retention processes. In this perspective it is not the dynamic capabilities that are the source of sustainable competitive advantage, but the outcome of applying ‘best practices’ in idiosyncratic ways (Eisenhardt & Martin, Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000: 1110). Hence, firms that develop or quickly adopt best practices and are able to apply them to their idiosyncratic resource endowments are likely to gain temporary advantages over their rivals.

Theoretical and Empirical Advances of Dynamic Capabilities Through a Darwinian Perspective

Core to this research note is the discussion of dynamic capabilities as idiosyncratic routines on the one hand and best practices on the other. Understanding evolutionary fitness is an important part of dynamic capability research. Alleviating the dynamic capability perspective from the burden to explain sustainable competitive advantage makes room for a more substantial analysis of how evolutionary theory explains dynamic capability application in (re)configuring the firm’s resource base. Understanding variation requires an outcome-independent conception of dynamic capabilities (although the hope would be that they are overall performance enhancing as Ambrosini & Bowman (Reference Ambrosini and Bowman2009) argue). In the sense, we interpret Eisenhardt and Martin in this research note, research on dynamic capabilities should not be focused on performance, but survival as a dependent variable. Curiously, Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) note that performance is an unsuitable dependent variable, but chose to use it despite their sample having the size and longitudinal character needed to dig deeper (see e.g., Wei & Lin, Reference Wei and Lin2015).

Consider the variation–selection–retention framework introduced by Galvin et al. and the levels of cause and effect (dependent variable). According to the authors, variation as an outcome of dynamic capabilities appears in both environment and firms. Dynamic capabilities ‘drive’ variation at the firm level, and firms coevolve with the market or industry, as they create and drive environmental variation. In such a setting, the order and direction of cause and effect remain unclear. Particularly, the empirical setting leaves open many questions regarding a (quasi-experimental) setting to better test dynamic capabilities. This, however, was the aspired goal of this article and the origin of the claim that general Darwinian evolution might impact the way the research on dynamic capabilities can progress.

Our criticism is also manifested in the way Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) operationalize dynamic capabilities. First, instead of survival, the authors study firm performance. It would have been interesting to see differences between the 75% survivors and the 25% nonsurvivors in the original ABS sample. Second, as independent variables the authors chose to study ‘capability development’ and ‘market development.’ The authors de facto study ‘best practice’ and exclude internalization processes that would reflect the idiosyncratic character of routines. For us, it becomes clear that the study could have benefited from a best practice view rather than the attempt to tie the analysis to idiosyncrasies for which neither the theoretical framing nor the data are well suited. Third, we note that Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) use sales growth in order to reflect selection processes. However, we argue that market development (e.g., market expansions through best practices) rather reflect retention in an evolutionary sense than selection.

Overall, we find several indicators that Galvin, Rice, and Liao (Reference Galvin, Rice and Liao2014) conceive dynamic capabilities in a tradition that tries to explain competitive advantage originating from firm heterogeneity and market imperfection – which the authors claim not to pursue.

We suggest that in order to contribute to a theoretical foundation and the empirical assessment applying an evolutionary perspective of dynamic capabilities, the variation–selection–retention framework should be consistently applied to one school of dynamic capabilities. We suggest that analyzing ‘dynamic capabilities as best practice’ as survival (on the routine, firm, and industry level) seems to be a more promising approach in understanding firms’ resource alteration decision and processes.

Conclusion

In this research note, we argue for a population ecology perspective of dynamic capabilities applying the framework of Eisenhardt and Martin (Reference Eisenhardt and Martin2000). Such an approach has the potential to advance the field and break out of the current most salient weaknesses in this literature (see also Galvin & Arndt, Reference Galvin and Arndt2014). Namely, the theoretical framing in this literature is convoluted by two different schools and the often cross-sectional empirical settings hardly allow meaningful analysis.

If dynamic capabilities are both ‘best practice across firms’ and firm routines, then dynamic capabilities are subject to variation–selection–retention at both levels: the individual firm level and the industry level. We suggest that entrepreneurial actions of firms, that is, their management teams, trigger variation and thereby evolution (O’Shannassy, Reference O’Shannassy2014). In this understanding, industry evolution is driven by firm evolution, which is driven by entrepreneurial management teams that opt for variation. New market offerings either exploit existing opportunities or create opportunities. Our claim is that a dynamic capability perspective – especially when studying dynamic capabilities empirically – needs to clarify the theoretical conception of dynamic capabilities and the level at which the evolutionary mechanisms are studied.

References

Agarwal, R., & Selen, W. (2013). The incremental and cumulative effects of dynamic capability building on service innovation in collaborative service organizations. Journal of Management & Organization, 19(5), 521543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ambrosini, V., & Bowman, C. (2009). What are dynamic capabilities and are they a useful construct in strategic management? International Journal of Management Reviews, 11(1), 2949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arend, R., & Bromiley, P. (2009). Assessing the dynamic capabilities view: Spare change, everyone? Strategic Organization, 7(1), 7590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arndt, F., Pierce, L., & Teece, D. (forthcoming). Industrial and Corporate Change. The behavioral and evolutionary roots of dynamic capabilities. Available at SSRN 1161171.Google Scholar
Eisenhardt, K. M., & Martin, J. A. (2000). Dynamic capabilities: What are they? Strategic Management Journal, 21(1), 11051121.3.0.CO;2-E>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galvin, P., & Arndt, F. (2014). Strategic management: Building depth as well as breadth. Journal of Management & Organization, 20(2), 139147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galvin, P., Rice, J., & Liao, T. S. (2014). Applying a Darwinian model to the dynamic capabilities view: Insights and issues. Journal of Management & Organization, 20(2), 250263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helfat, C. E., & Peteraf, M. A. (2003). The dynamic resource-based view: Capability lifecycles. Strategic Management Journal, 24(10), 9971010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Shannassy, T. (2014). Investigating the role of middle managers in strategy-making process: An Australian mixed method study. Journal of Management & Organization, 20(2), 187205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peteraf, M., Di Stefano, G., & Verona, G. (2013). The elephant in the room of dynamic capabilities: Bringing two diverging conversations together. Strategic Management Journal, 34(12), 13891410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teece, D., Pisano, G., & Shuen, A. (1997). Dynamic capabilities and strategic management. Strategic Management Journal, 18, 509533.3.0.CO;2-Z>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wei, Y. C., & Lin, C. Y. Y. (2015). Intangible assets and decline: A population ecology perspective. Journal of Management & Organization , 117.Google Scholar
Zollo, M., & Winter, S. G. (2002). Deliberate learning and the evolution of dynamic capabilities. Organization Science, 13(3), 339351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar