Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m42fx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T04:13:55.887Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Sentences implying their own provability

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

David Guaspari*
Affiliation:
St. John's College, Annapolis, Maryland 21404

Extract

We begin with a simple observation and a simple question. If we fix Th(x), some reasonable formulation of “x is the Gödel number of a theorem of Peano Arithmetic”, then for any sentence σ, Peano Arithmetic proves σ → Th(⌈σ⌉). (Here ⌈σ⌉ is the canonical term denoting the Gödel number of σ.) This observation is crucial to the proof of the Second Incompleteness Theorem. Call ψ a self-prover (with respect to Th(x)) if ψ → Th(⌈ψ⌉) is a theorem of Peano Arithmetic (from now on, PA). Our simple question is this: Does the observation have a converse—must every self-prover be provably equivalent to a sentence? Whatever φ happens to be, the formula φ ∧ Th(⌈φ⌉) is a self-prover. This makes it seem clear that there must exist self-provers which are not provably : We need only use a suitably complicated φ.

Deciding what sort of complication is “suitable” and finding such a φ is surprisingly annoying. Here is a quick example: One might guess that any φ which is unprovable and would work. In that case we could take φ to be CON—that is, ¬Th(⌈0 = 1⌉); but CON ∧ Th(⌈CON⌉) is refutable in PA, so is provably equivalent to the quantifier-free formula 0 = 1.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1983

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

[1]Guaspari, D., Partially conservative extensions of arithmetic, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 254 (1979), pp. 4768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Guaspari, D. and Solovay, R.M., Rosser sentences, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 16 (1979), pp. 8189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]Hajkova, M. and Hajek, P., On interpretability in theories containing arithmetic, Fundamenta Mathematical vol. 76 (1972), pp. 131137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[4]Smorynski, C., Calculating self-referential sentences, I: Explicit calculations, Studia Logica, vol. 38 (1979), pp. 1736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5]Smorynski, C., Calculating self-referential sentences: Guaspari sentences of the first kind, this Journal, vol. 45 (1980), pp. 8095.Google Scholar
[6]Smorynski, C., Beth's theorem and self-referential sentences, Logic colloquium '77 (Macintyre, A., Pacholski, L. and Paris, J., editors) North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1978, pp. 253261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7]Solovay, R.M., Provability interpretations of modal logic, Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 25 (1976), pp. 287304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar