Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-16T14:34:33.300Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

TWO EXAMPLES CONCERNING EXISTENTIAL UNDECIDABILITY IN FIELDS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 November 2023

PHILIP DITTMANN*
Affiliation:
INSTITUT FÜR ALGEBRA TECHNISCHE UNIVERSITÄT DRESDEN 01062 DRESDEN, GERMANY
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We construct an existentially undecidable complete discretely valued field of mixed characteristic with existentially decidable residue field and decidable algebraic part, answering a question by Anscombe–Fehm in a strong way. Along the way, we construct an existentially decidable field of positive characteristic with an existentially undecidable finite extension, modifying a construction due to Kesavan Thanagopal.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

Given a field K, one may ask whether there is an algorithm to decide which multivariable polynomials with coefficients in the prime field have zeroes in K—in short, whether K is existentially decidable. Motivated by Hilbert’s Tenth Problem, much research has been done on this question in particular in global fields and function fields (see for instance the monograph [Reference Shlapentokh24]). On the other hand, this question is also of interest in henselian valued fields, where it is the first step of a good model-theoretic understanding of the full first-order theory. See in particular [Reference Anscombe, Dittmann and Fehm1, Reference Anscombe and Fehm3, Reference Anscombe and Jahnke4, Reference Kartas17] for recent related work.

The chief aim of this note is to prove the following theorem, giving an interesting example of existential undecidability.

Theorem 1.1. Let p be a prime number. There exists a complete discretely valued field $(E,v)$ of characteristic $0$ and residue characteristic p such that the residue field $Ev$ is existentially decidable, the set of polynomials in $\mathbb {Q}[X]$ with a zero in E is decidable, but the field E is existentially undecidable.

This answers a question by Anscombe–Fehm in a strong way (see Remark 5.3 for a discussion). The existential theories of complete discretely valued fields of mixed characteristic (or more generally finitely ramified henselian valued fields) are further explored in [Reference Anscombe, Dittmann and Jahnke2].

In order to prove Theorem 1.1, we use an example of a different phenomenon in existential decidability, which seems interesting in its own right.

Theorem 1.2. Let p be a prime number. There exists an existentially decidable field of characteristic p with an existentially undecidable quadratic extension.

A variant of this problem was first considered in Kesavan Thanagopal’s thesis [Reference Thanagopal26], where an example was given in characteristic $0$ . We modify the construction given there, based on Ershov’s theory of fields with a strong local–global principle presented in [Reference Ershov10].

2 A useful family of varieties

Let p be a prime number, and $q>1$ a power of p. In this section we prove the following proposition, which will be useful later.

Proposition 2.1. Let $n \geq 1$ . There exists a smooth projective geometrically integral variety $V/\mathbb {F}_q$ such that for any $m \geq 1$ we have:

  • if $m \mid n$ , then $V(\mathbb {F}_{q^m}) = \emptyset $ ;

  • if $\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(m, n) \geq 4n$ , then $V(\mathbb {F}_{q^m}) \neq \emptyset $ .

For definiteness, in this article we take a variety (over a specified base field) to be a separated scheme of finite type, although almost all varieties occurring will be quasi-projective and geometrically integral.

The proof of Proposition 2.1 relies on the following lemma.

Lemma 2.2. There exists a smooth projective geometrically integral curve $C/\mathbb {F}_q$ such that $C(\mathbb {F}_q) = \emptyset $ , but $C(k) \neq \emptyset $ for any field extension $k/\mathbb {F}_q$ with $4 \leq [k : \mathbb {F}_q] < \infty $ .

Proof Let g be the smallest integer bigger than $\frac {q-3}{2}$ with $g \equiv\ -1\ \ \pmod {p}$ , so $\frac {q-3}{2} < g \leq \frac {q-3}{2} + p$ . By [Reference Becker and Glass6, Lemma 2.2], there exists a hyperelliptic curve $C/\mathbb {F}_q$ of genus g with $C(\mathbb {F}_q) = \emptyset $ .

The number of $\mathbb {F}_{q^m}$ -rational points of C is at least $q^m + 1 - 2g\sqrt {q^m} \geq q^m + 1 - (q-3 + 2p)q^{m/2}$ by the Hasse–Weil bound. This is positive if $q-3 + 2p \leq q^{m/2}$ , which is the case if $m \geq 4$ .

Remark 2.3. The situation would be neater if we could strengthen the lemma to say that $C(k) \neq \mathbb {F}_q$ for any proper finite extension $k/\mathbb {F}_q$ , in which case we could also strengthen the proposition to say that $V(\mathbb {F}_{q^m}) = \emptyset $ if and only if $m \mid n$ .

In order to improve the lemma in this way, one would need to improve the construction of Becker and Glass, finding a bound for the genus which is better than linear in q. This works at least for specific values for q in any characteristic $p> 3$ (see [Reference Yekhanin27]).

Proof of the proposition

Let $C/\mathbb {F}_{q^n}$ be a curve as in the lemma, so that $C(\mathbb {F}_{q^n}) = \emptyset $ , but $C(\mathbb {F}_{q^{nl}}) \neq \emptyset $ for $l \geq 4$ . Let $V/\mathbb {F}_q$ be the Weil restriction of C. It is a smooth projective geometrically integral variety over $\mathbb {F}_q$ because $C/\mathbb {F}_{q^n}$ is so: Indeed, by [Reference Conrad, Gabber and Prasad8, Proposition A.5.9] V is smooth and geometrically connected (hence geometrically integral), and by [Reference Conrad, Gabber and Prasad8, Proposition A.5.8] and [Reference Bosch, Lütkebohmert and Raynaud7, Proposition 7.6/5] V is quasi-projective and proper, hence projective.

By the defining property, for any m, the set $V(\mathbb {F}_{q^m})$ is in bijection to $C(\mathbb {F}_{q^m} \otimes _{\mathbb {F}_q} \mathbb {F}_{q^n})$ . For $m \mid n$ we have $C(\mathbb {F}_{q^m} \otimes _{\mathbb {F}_q} \mathbb {F}_{q^n}) = C(\mathbb {F}_{q^n}^m) = C(\mathbb {F}_{q^n})^m = \emptyset $ .

Now let $m \geq 1$ with $\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(n, m) \geq 4n$ . We have $\mathbb {F}_{q^m} \otimes _{\mathbb {F}_q} \mathbb {F}_{q^m} = \mathbb {F}_{q^{\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(n,m)}}^{nm/\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(n,m)}$ . Then $C(\mathbb {F}_{q^m} \otimes _{\mathbb {F}_q} \mathbb {F}_{q^n}) = C(\mathbb {F}_{q^{\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(n,m)}}^{nm/\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(n,m)}) \neq \emptyset $ since $C(\mathbb {F}_{q^{\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(n,m)}}) \neq \emptyset $ by the defining property of C. This proves the desired property of V.

Remark 2.4. It will be important for us later that for given q and m, a variety V as in the proposition can be effectively determined. This follows from the proofs, since both the construction of [Reference Becker and Glass6, Lemma 2.2] and Weil restriction as in the proof of Proposition 2.1 are effective. On the other hand, this is also clear without going back into the proofs, merely using the existence statement: simply enumerate candidate varieties, test for points over small fields, and use the Hasse–Weil bound.

3 The construction

Fix again a prime p. We find an extension field $\mathbb {K}$ of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ satisfying a strong local–global principle, after Ershov.

We first fix some terminology. A discrete valuation is a Krull valuation whose value group is isomorphic to $\mathbb {Z}$ , i.e., is given by a discrete valuation ring in the usual sense of commutative algebra. We do not distinguish between valuations and their valuation rings, so in particular we identify equivalent valuations. Given a valuation v on a field K, we write $Kv$ for the residue field and $K_v^h$ for the henselisation. A valuation of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ is said to be above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ if its valuation ring contains $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ , i.e., if it is not the degree valuation of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ .

Proposition 3.1. There exists a countable regular field extension $\mathbb {K}/\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ together with a family V of discrete valuations such that the following hold:

  1. (1) For every $v \in V$ , the restriction of v to $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ is again a discrete valuation, which lies above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ . Further, the extension $(\mathbb {K},v)/(\mathbb {F}_p(t), v|_{\mathbb {F}_p(t)})$ is immediate, i.e., the residue fields $\mathbb {K} v$ and $\mathbb {F}_p(t)v|_{\mathbb {F}_p(t)}$ agree and a uniformiser for $v|_{\mathbb {F}_p(t)}$ remains a uniformiser for v.

  2. (2) For every discrete valuation $v_0$ of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ there is precisely one $v \in V$ prolonging $v_0$ .

  3. (3) Any $x \in \mathbb {K}$ is in the valuation ring of all but finitely many $v \in V$ .

  4. (4) If a geometrically integral variety $X/\mathbb {K}$ has a smooth $\mathbb {K}_v^h$ -point for every $v \in V$ , then it has a $\mathbb {K}$ -point.

Proof This is a consequence of [Reference Ershov10, Theorem 3.6.3], as we now explain.

Let $V_0$ be the family of discrete valuation rings of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ . Then any two distinct members of $V_0$ are independent; $V_0$ is a near Boolean family in Ershov’s sense since $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ is an “NB-ring” [Reference Ershov10, Remark 2.5.1] and the valuation rings of the valuations in $V_0$ are precisely the localisations of $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ at its maximal ideals [Reference Ershov10, Proposition 2.5.3]; and the residue fields of $V_0$ are “regularly closed at infinity” [Reference Ershov10, Section 3.4, p. 172], as they are finite fields with only finitely many of cardinality lower than a given bound, and so the desired property follows from the Lang–Weil bounds [Reference Poonen21, Theorem 7.7.1(iv)].

Thus by [Reference Ershov10, Theorem 3.6.3], there exists a countable regular extension $\mathbb {K}/\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ with a family of valuation rings V such that every valuation $v \in V$ lies over a valuation $v_0 \in V_0$ , this induces a bijection between V and $V_0$ , and the extension of valued fields $(\mathbb {K}, v)/(\mathbb {F}_p(t), v_0)$ is immediate. In particular every $v \in V$ is discrete, and conditions (1) and (2) are satisfied.

The bijection $V \to V_0$ is furthermore a homeomorphism with respect to the Zariski topologies on V and $V_0$ (see [Reference Ershov10, Section 2.2]), which means that for all $x \in \mathbb {K}$ the (“Zariski closed”) set $C_x := \{ v \in V \colon v(x) < 0 \}$ is either finite or all of V since the analogous statement holds in $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ . However, we cannot have $C_x = V$ , since otherwise for a suitable element $b \in \mathbb {F}_p(t)^\times $ (a high power of a uniformiser for some valuation in $V_0$ ) the set $C_{xb}$ would be infinite but strictly contained in V, violating the homeomorphism property. Therefore the set $C_x$ is finite for all $x \in \mathbb {K}$ . This gives condition (3).

In addition, the family V satisfies Ershov’s “arithmetic local–global principle” LGA, and therefore also the “geometric local–global principle” LGG [Reference Ershov10, Proposition 3.2.5], which gives our condition (4) for geometrically integral affine varieties $X/\mathbb {K}$ . Now take an arbitrary geometrically integral variety $X/\mathbb {K}$ , and let $X_0/\mathbb {K}$ be an affine dense open subvariety. If X has a smooth $\mathbb {K}_v^h$ -point for every $v \in V$ , then the same holds for $X_0$ : This is the ampleness of the henselian field $\mathbb {K}_v^h$ (see [Reference Ershov10, Corollary 3.1.6] and the surrounding discussion). Hence we have $\emptyset \neq X_0(\mathbb {K}) \subseteq X(\mathbb {K})$ by the affine case, proving (4) in full generality.

Remarks 3.2.

  1. (1) Fields $\mathbb {K}$ as in the proposition are weak analogues of the “surprising extensions of $\mathbb {Q}$ ” considered in [Reference Ershov9] (also variously translated as “wonderful” or “amazing” extensions). Note, however, that there also the place at infinity, i.e., the real place of $\mathbb {Q}$ , is included.

  2. (2) Since it plays no role in the sequel, we have not imposed the condition which is called maximality in [Reference Ershov9], i.e., that for every proper separable algebraic extension $L/\mathbb {K}$ , some valuation in V has no immediate extension to L. This condition can, however, always be added (see [Reference Ershov10, Proposition 4.4.3, Remark 4.4.3, and Proposition 4.4.4]).

  3. (3) Any non-trivial valuation v of $\mathbb {K}$ not in V always has separably closed henselisation, and hence poses no obstruction to the existence of rational points on varieties. This follows from [Reference Ershov10, Corollary 3.5.4] (there stated for Boolean families of valuations, but the same proof works for near-Boolean families with residue fields regularly closed at infinity). In particular, the family V simply consists of all discrete valuations of $\mathbb {K}$ .

  4. (4) Instead of starting with the discrete valuations of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ , we could have worked with the coordinate ring of any irreducible smooth affine curve over $\mathbb {F}_p$ and its function field.

We henceforth fix a field $\mathbb {K}$ as in the proposition.

Lemma 3.3. Let $L/\mathbb {K}$ be a finite separable extension. Let $X/\mathbb {F}_p$ be a smooth projective geometrically integral variety. Then $X(L) \neq \emptyset $ if and only if for every $v \in V$ and every prolongation w of v to L, X has a point over the residue field $Lw$ .

Proof Let W be the family of prolongations of valuations in V to L. By [Reference Ershov10, Proposition 3.4.1] (a Weil restriction argument), the same local–global principle as for V holds for W. In particular, $X(L) \neq \emptyset $ if and only if X has a point over all henselisations $L_w^h$ , $w \in W$ .

Let $w \in W$ . If X has a point over the henselisation $L_w^h$ , then it has a point over the residue field $Lw$ , using that X is projective (given homogenous coordinates of an $L_w^h$ -point of X, clear denominators and reduce).Footnote 1 Conversely, if X has a point over the residue field $Lw$ , then it has a point over the henselisation $L_w^h$ since there exists an embedding $Lw \hookrightarrow L_w^h$ (apply Hensel’s Lemma to the minimal polynomial of a primitive element of $Lw$ over $\mathbb {F}_p$ ). Together with the local–global principle, this proves the statement.

Remark 3.4. None of the hypotheses of smoothness, projectivity, and geometric integrality can be omitted in Lemma 3.3. This explains why these hypotheses, in particular smoothness and geometric integrality, recur throughout this article. We sketch a few examples to demonstrate this.

For the variety X which is the affine line $\mathbb {A}^1$ punctured at each of its $\mathbb {F}_p$ -points—equivalently, X is the plane curve described by the equation $y x (x-1) \dotsm (x-(p-1)) = 1$ —we have $X(\mathbb {K}) \neq \emptyset $ , but for the residue field $\mathbb {F}_p$ of the unique valuation $v \in V$ above the t-adic valuation of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ we have $X(\mathbb {F}_p) = \emptyset $ by construction. Thus one direction of the lemma fails for $L=\mathbb {K}$ with the non-projective smooth geometrically integral variety X.

In the other direction, both smoothness and geometric integrality are needed in general for Ershov’s local–global principle to apply. Consider a finite extension $L_0/\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ which is the function field of a smooth projective geometrically integral $\mathbb {F}_p$ -curve without rational points and set $L = L_0 \mathbb {K}$ . Then L is regular over $\mathbb {F}_p$ , but carries no valuation with residue field $\mathbb {F}_p$ . Let $\mathbb {F}_q$ be a finite field which occurs as the residue field of some discrete valuation on L. Let $C/\mathbb {F}_p$ be a smooth projective geometrically integral curve without $\mathbb {F}_q$ -points. Then C has no L-point, but it has an $Lw$ -point for all but finitely many discrete valuations w on L by the Hasse–Weil bound. For a suitable list $\mathbb {F}^{(1)}, \dotsc , \mathbb {F}^{(n)}$ of proper finite extensions of $\mathbb {F}_p$ , the $\mathbb {F}_p$ -variety $C' := C \coprod \operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {F}^{(1)}) \coprod \dotsb \coprod \operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {F}^{(n)})$ has an $Lv$ -point for all discrete valuations v on L, but no L-point (since none of its connected components has an L-point by construction). Thus $C'$ is a reducible smooth projective $\mathbb {F}_p$ -variety for which the statement of the lemma does not hold.

To find a projective non-smooth geometrically integral example, one can again start with L and C as above, and construct a curve $C"$ from C not by adding finitely many points, but by a pinching construction (see for instance [Reference Serre23, Section 1.3] for an explanation in principle, but only for curves over algebraically closed fields, and [Reference Ferrand11] for the generality needed here): thus C will be the normalisation of $C"$ , and by wisely choosing the pinching data, one forces $C"$ to have rational points over all residue fields of L, but none over L itself. We omit the details.

We next wish to find finite extensions $L/\mathbb {K}$ such that the discrete valuations of L have prescribed residue fields. This is achieved by the following lemmas.

Lemma 3.5. Let $S_1$ , $S_2$ be two disjoint finite sets of prime numbers greater than $4$ . There exists a cyclic extension $L_0/\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ of degree $4$ such that:

  1. (1) For every $l \in S_1$ , there exists a discrete valuation of $L_0$ above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ with residue field $\mathbb {F}_{p^l}$ .

  2. (2) For every $l \in S_2$ and every $\mathbb {F}_{p^m}$ occurring as the residue field of a valuation of $L_0$ , we have $\operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(l,m) \geq 4l$ .

Proof Let $L_0/\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ be a cyclic extension of degree $4$ in which each of the (non-zero) finitely many discrete valuations of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ with residue field $\mathbb {F}_{p^l}$ , $l \in S_1$ , is completely split, and each of the finitely many discrete valuations of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ with residue field $\mathbb {F}_{p^n}$ , $S_1 \not \ni n \leq 4 \max (S_2)$ , is inert. The existence of such an extension follows from the Grunwald–Wang Theorem [Reference Neukirch, Schmidt and Wingberg19, Theorem 9.2.8], which allows the construction of abelian extensions of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ in which the decomposition behaviour of finitely many places is prescribed. The field $L_0$ satisfies the required properties.

Lemma 3.6. Let $S_1$ , $S_2$ be two disjoint finite sets of prime numbers greater than $4$ . Then there exists a cyclic extension $L/\mathbb {K}$ of degree $4$ such that conditions (1) and (2) from Lemma 3.5 hold for L (in place of $L_0$ ).

Proof Take $L_0/\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ as in Lemma 3.5, and let $L = \mathbb {K} L_0$ (free compositum, equivalently the tensor product $\mathbb {K} \otimes _{\mathbb {F}_p(t)} L_0$ ). For any discrete valuation v of L, the restriction w to $L_0$ is also a discrete valuation and we have the inclusion of residue fields $L_0w \subseteq Lv$ . Thus condition (2) transfers from $L_0$ to L: Indeed, if $m_0 = [L_0w : \mathbb {F}_p]$ and $m = [Lv : \mathbb {F}_p]$ , we have $m_0 \mid m$ and thus $4l \leq \operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(l, m_0) \mid \operatorname {\mathrm {lcm}}(l, m)$ .

On the other hand, for every discrete valuation w of $L_0$ above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ , the restriction $v_0$ to $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ is again discrete, and the defining property of $\mathbb {K}$ affords a discrete valuation v on $\mathbb {K}$ such that $(\mathbb {K},v)/(\mathbb {F}_p(t), v_0)$ is immediate. In particular, $\mathbb {K}$ embeds into the completion $\widehat {\mathbb {F}_p(t)}_{v_0}$ over $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ . Thus L embeds into the completion $\widehat {L_0}_w$ over $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ since both $\mathbb {K}$ and $L_0$ have such an embedding and are linearly disjoint over $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ . Therefore L carries a discrete valuation above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ with residue field $L_0w$ . Thus condition (1) transfers from $L_0$ to L.

We can now show that $\aleph _0$ -saturated elementary extensions $\mathbb {K}^\ast $ of $\mathbb {K}$ have existentially undecidable finite extensions.

Recall (see for instance [Reference Soare25, Definition 1.6.8]) that a set of natural numbers A is many-one reducible to a set of natural numbers B if there exists a computable function $f \colon \mathbb {N} \to \mathbb {N}$ such that for any $x \in \mathbb {N}$ we have $f(x) \in B$ if and only if $x \in A$ . This is a formalisation of the notion that membership in A is no harder to decide than membership in B. (A different formalisation is given by Turing reducibility, which is implied by many-one reducibility.)

By fixing a standard Gödel coding, we identify formulae of a given finite first-order language with natural numbers. In particular, computability-theoretic terms such as decidability and many-one reducibility make sense for sets of formulae. We generally work in the language of rings $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}} = \{ +, -, \cdot , 0, 1 \}$ .

Theorem 3.7. Let S be a set of prime numbers. Then any $\aleph _0$ -saturated elementary extension $\mathbb {K}^\ast $ of $\mathbb {K}$ has a cyclic extension $L/\mathbb {K}^\ast $ of degree $4$ such that S is many-one reducible to the existential theory of L. In particular, there exist cyclic extensions $L/\mathbb {K}^\ast $ of degree $4$ with undecidable existential theory.

Proof For every prime number l, let $V_l/\mathbb {F}_p$ be a variety as in Proposition 2.1 (with $q=p$ , $n=l$ ). We claim that we can choose L such that for all primes $l> 4$ , we have $V_l(L) \neq \emptyset $ if and only if $l \in S$ . Since $V_l$ can be computed from l by Remark 2.4, and $V_l(L) \neq \emptyset $ is straightforwardly translated into an existential sentence, this L solves the problem.

It thus remains to find L satisfying the claim. Recasting the search for L as the search for the coefficients of an irreducible polynomial of degree $4$ over $\mathbb {K}^\ast $ with a root generating L, saturation reduces us to finding, for every finite set of primes $S_1$ disjoint from S and finite $S_2 \subseteq S$ , an extension $L/\mathbb {K}$ of degree $4$ with $V_l(L) = \emptyset $ for $4 < l \in S_1$ and $V_l(L) \neq \emptyset $ for $4 < l \in S_2$ . This problem is solved by Lemma 3.6: Indeed, the field L produced there satisfies the condition by Lemma 3.3 and the construction of the $V_l$ .

The “in particular” holds because if S is an undecidable set, then the existential theory of L cannot be decidable.

Remark 3.8. The passage to an elementary extension of $\mathbb {K}$ is due to the need to realise a certain type, given by the requirements for the coefficient tuple of an irreducible polynomial defining L. Given that this is only one type, a well-chosen countable elementary extension $\mathbb {K}^\ast $ of $\mathbb {K}$ (depending on S) would be sufficient in place of an $\aleph _0$ -saturated one.

4 Existential decidability

Let again p be a prime number, $\mathbb {K}/\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ as in the last section. In this section we prove that the existential theory of $\mathbb K$ is decidable.

Lemma 4.1. Let $X/\mathbb {F}_p$ be a geometrically integral smooth affine variety. Then $X(\mathbb {K}) \neq \emptyset $ if and only if $X(\mathbb {F}_p(\!(s)\!)) \neq \emptyset $ .

Proof First observe that since $\mathbb {K}$ carries a discrete valuation with residue field $\mathbb {F}_p$ (for instance the prolongation in V of the t-adic valuation of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ ), $\mathbb {K}$ embeds into $\mathbb {F}_p(\!(s)\!)$ , and therefore the existence of a $\mathbb {K}$ -rational point of X implies the existence of an $\mathbb {F}_p(\!(s)\!)$ -rational point.

Suppose conversely that X has an $\mathbb {F}_p(\!(s)\!)$ -rational point. Then it has a point over the henselisation $\mathbb {F}_p(s)_s^h$ at the s-adic valuation, since the fields $\mathbb {F}_p(\!(s)\!)$ and $\mathbb {F}_p(s)_s^h$ have the same existential theory by [Reference Anscombe and Fehm3, Corollary 7.2] (or by [Reference Kuhlmann18, Theorem 5.9]). Therefore X has a rational point over the henselisation $\mathbb {K}_v^h$ for every v, since every such henselisation embeds $\mathbb {F}_p(s)_s^h$ (sending s to a uniformiser). Now $X(\mathbb {K}) \neq \emptyset $ follows from the local–global principle.

The following general lemma reduces the existential theory of a field to information about which smooth affine varieties have rational points. This may well have appeared elsewhere in the literature, but I am unaware of a reference. As usual, given a field F, the language $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(F)$ is simply the expansion of $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}$ by constants for the elements of F. In particular, every extension $E/F$ is naturally an $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(F)$ -structure.

Lemma 4.2. Let F be a field, and $E_1/F$ , $E_2/F$ two regular extensions. Assume that for every geometrically integral smooth affine F-variety X we have $X(E_1) \neq \emptyset $ if and only if $X(E_2) \neq \emptyset $ . Then the existential $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(F)$ -theories of $E_1$ and $E_2$ agree.

Proof By standard reductions (disjunctive normal form, elimination of inequalities) it suffices to show that for any $f_1, \dotsc , f_k \in F[X_1, \dotsc , X_n]$ , the $f_i$ have a common zero in $E_1$ if and only if they have a common zero in $E_2$ . In other words, we must show that for every affine F-variety X we have $X(E_1) \neq \emptyset $ if and only if $X(E_2) \neq \emptyset $ .

By passing to the reduction of X is necessary, and using that for every reduced variety the regular locus is open and not empty [Reference Görtz and Wedhorn12, Corollary 12.52(2)], we can write X as a union of finitely many regular integral affine locally closed subvarieties. In other words, it suffices to consider integral regular affine X.

If X is not geometrically integral, then $X(E_1) = \emptyset = X(E_2)$ : Indeed, the base-changed varieties $X_{E_1}/E_1$ and $X_{E_2}/E_2$ are regular [Reference Grothendieck13, Proposition 6.7.4], integral [Reference Görtz and Wedhorn12, Corollary 5.56(3)], but not geometrically integral, and therefore they have no rational points (see for instance [Reference Poonen20, Lemma 10.1]).

Thus let us assume that X is geometrically integral. Then the smooth locus $X_{\mathrm {sm}} \subseteq X$ is dense open [Reference Görtz and Wedhorn12, Theorem 6.19 and Remark 6.20(ii)]. Any $E_1$ -rational point on X is necessarily smooth [Reference Grothendieck14, Proposition 17.15.1], i.e., is an $E_1$ -rational point on the geometrically integral smooth variety $X_{\mathrm {sm}}$ . By the assumption applied to the open affine subvarieties of $X_{\mathrm {sm}}$ , we must then also have an $E_2$ -rational point on $X_{\mathrm {sm}}$ and therefore on X. By symmetry, this shows that $X(E_1) \neq \emptyset $ if and only if $X(E_2) \neq \emptyset $ , as desired.

Proposition 4.3. The existential theory of $\mathbb {K}$ agrees with the existential theory of $\mathbb {F}_p(\!(s)\!)$ . In particular, it is decidable.

Proof The first statement follows from the two preceding lemmas (take $F=\mathbb {F}_p$ , $E_1 = \mathbb {K}$ , and $E_2 = \mathbb {F}_p(\!(s)\!)$ ). The “in particular” is [Reference Anscombe and Fehm3, Corollary 7.5].

Corollary 4.4. There exists an existentially decidable field K of characteristic p with an existentially undecidable separable quadratic extension. We can choose K such that the relative algebraic closure of $\mathbb {F}_p$ in K is finite.

Proof Let $\mathbb {K}^\ast $ be an $\aleph _0$ -saturated elementary extension of $\mathbb {K}$ , and let $L/\mathbb {K}^\ast $ be a cyclic extension of degree $4$ which is existentially undecidable (Theorem 3.7). Let $L_0/\mathbb {K}^\ast $ be the unique quadratic intermediate field. Since $\mathbb {K}$ is regular over $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ , the prime field $\mathbb {F}_p$ is relatively algebraically closed in $\mathbb {K}$ and thus in $\mathbb {K}^\ast $ . Hence the relative algebraic closure of $\mathbb {F}_p$ in L is finite. Since $\mathbb {K}^\ast $ is existentially decidable as $\mathbb {K}$ is, either $L_0/\mathbb {K}^\ast $ or $L/L_0$ is a pair of fields as desired.

This proves Theorem 1.2 from the introduction. As mentioned previously, the analogue in characteristic $0$ was established in [Reference Thanagopal26, Theorem 3.3.1], with a similar technique. There the full first-order theory of the base field is decidable, so the result is stronger than ours (inspection of the proof yields that the quadratic extension still has undecidable existential theory). Decidability of the full first-order theory seems out of reach in positive characteristic with the current method, as our understanding of the model theory of valued fields is insufficient.

Conditionally on a conjecture related to resolution of singularities, we can establish a slightly stronger decidability result in the language $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(\mathbb {F}_p(t))$ . Here we fix a natural coding of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ (specifically, a coding witnessing the computability of the field $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ ) to identify $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(\mathbb {F}_p(t))$ -formulae with natural numbers. Since every element of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ is quantifier-freely $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}$ -definable in terms of the constant t, instead of $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(\mathbb {F}_p(t))$ we could equivalently work in the expansion of $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}$ by a single constant symbol for t.

Lemma 4.5. Assume the consequence (R4) of local uniformisation from [Reference Anscombe, Dittmann and Fehm1]. Then there is an algorithm which, given as input $k, n> 0$ and polynomials $f_1, \dotsc , f_k \in \mathbb {F}_p(t)[X_1, \dotsc , X_n]$ such that the affine variety described by the $f_i$ is geometrically integral and smooth over $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ , decides whether the variety has a $\mathbb {K}$ -rational point, i.e., whether the $f_i$ have a common zero in $\mathbb {K}$ .

Proof Let $V_0$ be the set of discrete valuations of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ above $\mathbb {F}_p[t]$ . By [Reference Poonen21, Remark 7.7.3] (a combination of the Lang–Weil bounds and Hensel’s Lemma) one can effectively determine a finite subset $S \subseteq V_0$ such that for all $v \in V_0 \setminus S$ the $f_i$ have a common zero in the completion $\widehat {\mathbb {F}_p(t)}_v$ , and therefore in the henselisation $\mathbb {F}_p(t)_v^h$ since $\mathbb {F}_p(t)_v^h$ is existentially closed in $\widehat {\mathbb {F}_p(t)}_v$ [Reference Kuhlmann18, Theorem 5.9].

In order to decide whether the $f_i$ have a common zero in $\mathbb {K}$ , by the local–global principle it therefore suffices to decide whether they have a common zero in the henselisation $\mathbb {K}_v^h$ for each discrete valuation v of $\mathbb {K}$ above one of the valuations in S. The decidability of this problem (under the assumption (R4)) follows from [Reference Anscombe, Dittmann and Fehm1, Theorem 4.12]. Indeed, for each such v, the henselisation $\mathbb {K}_v^h$ (with the canonical valuation) is an immediate extension of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ (with the restricted valuation), and therefore its universal/existential $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(\mathbb {F}_p(t))$ -theory is formally entailed by the first-order axioms expressing that it is a henselian valued field extending $(\mathbb {F}_p(t), v|_{\mathbb {F}_p(t)})$ with the same residue field and uniformiser.

Proposition 4.6. Assume (R4). Then the existential $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(\mathbb {F}_p(t))$ -theory of $\mathbb {K}$ is decidable.

Proof Consider the $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}(\mathbb {F}_p(t))$ -theory T given by the following system of axioms:

  1. (1) the field axioms;

  2. (2) the quantifier-free diagram of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ ;

  3. (3) for each irreducible polynomial $f \in \mathbb {F}_p(t)[X]$ the sentence $\forall x (f(x) \neq 0)$ ;

  4. (4) for any finite list of polynomials $f_1, \dotsc , f_k \in \mathbb {F}_p(t)[X_1, \dotsc , X_n]$ describing a geometrically integral smooth affine $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ -variety, an axiom asserting that the $f_i$ have a common zero if this is the case in $\mathbb {K}$ , and otherwise an axiom asserting that they do not have a common zero.

We claim that this system of axioms is computably enumerable. This is clear for the field axioms, follows from the computability of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ for the quantifier-free diagram, and from the existence of a splitting algorithm for $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ for the third point. For the fourth point, this is essentially the preceding lemma and the observation that it is decidable whether a system of polynomials defines a geometrically integral smooth variety (for instance by Gröbner basis techniques and the Jacobian criterion).

The models of T are field extensions E of $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ in which $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ is relatively algebraically closed, i.e., which are regular over $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ , and such that the same geometrically integral smooth affine $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ -varieties have rational points in E as in $\mathbb {K}$ . By Lemma 4.2, the theory T is therefore complete for universal and existential $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ -sentences, i.e., for any existential $\mathbb {F}_p(t)$ -sentence, T entails either the sentence or its negation. A proof calculus therefore gives a decision procedure for existential consequences of T, which proves the claim since $\mathbb {K} \models T$ .

5 An existentially undecidable complete valued field

Let p be a fixed prime. We prove the following (stated as Theorem 1.1 in the introduction):

Theorem 5.1. There exists a complete discretely valued field $(E, v)$ with ${\operatorname {\mathrm {char}} E = 0}$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {char}} Ev = p$ , such that the existential theory of $Ev$ is decidable, but the existential theory of E is undecidable. We can furthermore choose E such that the set of one-variable polynomials in $\mathbb {Q}[X]$ with a zero in E is decidable.

Proof By Corollary 4.4, we may select an existentially decidable field K of characteristic p with an existentially undecidable separable quadratic extension L, such that furthermore the relative algebraic closure of $\mathbb {F}_p$ in K is finite.

There is an element $\alpha \in L$ with $L = K(\alpha )$ and $a := \alpha ^2 - \alpha \in K$ . (We use this equation instead of $a = \alpha ^2$ to handle all characteristics simultaneously.)

Let $(F, v)$ be the unique complete discretely valued field of characteristic $0$ with residue field K and uniformiser p. (See for instance [Reference Anscombe and Jahnke4, Theorem 2.10 and Corollary 6.6] for the (classical) existence and uniqueness of such $(F,v)$ in terms of the valuation ring, although we do not in fact need the uniqueness.) Let $b \in F$ be a lift of a, and set $E = F(\sqrt {p (1 + 4b)})$ . We continue to write v for the unique prolongation to finite extensions of F, in particular to E.

We claim that $(E, v)$ is as desired. Note first that $v(1+4b) = 0$ : this is clear if $p=2$ , and holds for odd p since otherwise $a = -1/4$ and so the polynomial $X^2 - X - a$ would be reducible in K. Therefore the extension E is obtained by adjoining to F a square root of the uniformiser $p(1+4b)$ , and is thus totally ramified. In particular $Ev = Fv = K$ , which is existentially decidable.

On the other hand, the field $E(\sqrt {p})$ contains the element $\sqrt {1 + 4b}$ , and therefore a root of the polynomial $X^2 - X - b$ , so the residue field $E(\sqrt {p})v$ must be $K(\alpha ) = L$ . In the complete discretely valued field $(E(\sqrt {p}), v)$ both the valuation ring $\mathcal {O}_v$ and its maximal ideal $\mathfrak {m}_v$ are existentially $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}$ -definable (without parameters), since for a natural number $n> 2$ coprime to p a well-known application of Hensel’s Lemma shows that

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal{O}_v \kern1.7pt{=}\kern1.7pt \{ x \kern1.7pt{\in}\kern1.7pt E(\sqrt{p}) \colon \exists y (1 + px^n \kern1.8pt{=}\kern1.8pt y^n) \}, \quad\! \mathfrak{m}_v \kern1.6pt{=}\kern1.6pt \{ x \kern1.7pt{\in}\kern1.7pt E(\sqrt{p}) \colon \exists y (1 + x^n/p \kern1.7pt{=}\kern1.7pt y^n)\} .\end{align*}$$

Therefore the residue field L is (parameter-freely) existentially interpretable in $E(\sqrt {p})$ (i.e., we have an interpretation satisfying the property of [Reference Hodges15, Theorem 5.3.2 and Remark 3]), so the existential $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}$ -theory of $E(\sqrt {p})$ is undecidable. (See [Reference Hodges15, Theorem 5.3.2 and Remark 4] for generalities on transfer of decidability under interpretations.) Consequently, the existential $\mathcal {L}_{\mathrm {ring}}$ -theory of E is likewise undecidable, since $E(\sqrt {p})$ is quantifier-freely interpretable in E.

Lastly, consider the subfield $\mathbb {Q}_p \subseteq F$ (given as the topological closure of the subfield $\mathbb {Q}$ ). Since the relative algebraic closure of $\mathbb {F}_p$ in $Fv = K$ is finite and $(F,v)$ has uniformiser p, the fundamental equality for algebraic extensions of $\mathbb {Q}_p$ (see for instance [Reference Ershov10, Proposition 1.4.6]) shows that the relative algebraic closure of $\mathbb {Q}_p$ in F is a finite extension of $\mathbb {Q}_p$ , and therefore the same holds in E. Thus the algebraic part of E is the same as the algebraic part of a local field of characteristic zero. The local fields of characteristic zero have decidable first-order theory [Reference Prestel and Roquette22, Corollary 5.3], so in particular it is decidable whether a given polynomial in $\mathbb {Q}[X]$ has a zero in E.

Remark 5.2. The condition that the set of polynomials in $\mathbb {Q}[X]$ with a zero in E be decidable is occasionally phrased as E having “decidable algebraic part,” in the sense that it allows to decide which elements of an algebraic closure of $\mathbb {Q}$ lie in E (up to conjugacy). There is, however, a certain ambiguity in this expression, as it may also be understood to assert that the field $E \cap \overline {\mathbb {Q}}$ is decidable, i.e., has decidable full first-order theory, which is a stronger condition. Our proof of Theorem 5.1 shows that even this stronger condition is satisfied, since the algebraic part of a local field is an elementary substructure and therefore shares its (decidable) first-order theory [Reference Prestel and Roquette22, Theorem 3.4 and Theorem 5.1].

Remark 5.3. In [Reference Anscombe and Fehm3, Remark 7.6] it was asked whether there exists an existentially undecidable henselian valued field of mixed characteristic with existentially decidable residue field and pointed value group (i.e., value group with a constant for the value of p). Theorem 5.1 provides an example for this phenomenon, as even the full first-order theory of the value group $\mathbb {Z}$ is decidable [Reference Hodges15, Theorem 3.3.8] (and expanding by a constant symbol for $v(p)$ does not change this, since any constant in $\mathbb {Z}$ is definable).

It was previously pointed out that there must exist (non-discrete) examples of valued fields with the desired property in [Reference Kartas16, Remark 3.6.9], using an inexplicit counting argument. However, the reason for existential undecidability of the examples there is due to it not being decidable which one-variable polynomials over $\mathbb {Q}$ have roots, unlike in our example.

The algebraic part has been known for some time as an obstruction in the model theory of henselian valued fields of mixed characteristic (see for instance [Reference Anscombe and Kuhlmann5, Corollary 1.6] and [Reference Anscombe and Fehm3, Remark 7.4]). Our theorem shows that the obvious attempt to repair the failure of the decidability statement [Reference Anscombe and Fehm3, Corollary 7.5] in mixed characteristic, by requiring a decidable axiom scheme describing the algebraic part, still fails, even in the case of value group $\mathbb {Z}$ .

In the case of finitely ramified fields (generalising the situation of value group $\mathbb {Z}$ in mixed characteristic), a satisfactory replacement for [Reference Anscombe and Fehm3, Corollary 7.5] is obtained in [Reference Anscombe, Dittmann and Jahnke2, Theorem 5.10]: here the obstruction from Theorem 5.1 is surmounted by considering the residue field in a certain expansion of the language of rings.

Acknowledgements

I became aware of the examples presented here some years ago. I would like to thank Arno Fehm for encouraging me to commit them to writing, as well as for comments on a draft version.

Footnotes

1 Using the valuative criterion of properness, it would suffice to assume that X is proper instead of projective.

References

REFERENCES

Anscombe, S., Dittmann, P., and Fehm, A., Axiomatizing the existential theory of $\mathbb{F}_q(t)$ . Algebra & Number Theory , vol. 17 (2023), no. 11, pp. 20132032.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, S., Dittmann, P., and Jahnke, F., Ax–Kochen–Ershov principles for finitely ramified henselian fields, preprint, 2023, arXiv:2305.12145 [math.LO].Google Scholar
Anscombe, S. and Fehm, A., The existential theory of equicharacteristic henselian valued fields . Algebra & Number Theory , vol. 10 (2016), no. 3, pp. 665683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, S. and Jahnke, F., The model theory of Cohen rings . Confluentes Mathematici , vol. 14 (2022), no. 2, pp. 128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, S. and Kuhlmann, F.-V., Notes on extremal and tame valued fields, this Journal, vol. 81 (2016), no. 2, pp. 400–416.Google Scholar
Becker, R. and Glass, D., Pointless hyperelliptic curves . Finite Fields and Their Applications , vol. 21 (2013), pp. 5057.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bosch, S., Lütkebohmert, W., and Raynaud, M., Néron Models , Springer, Berlin–Heidelberg, 1990.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conrad, B., Gabber, O., and Prasad, G., Pseudo-Reductive Groups , second ed., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ershov, Y. L., Doklady Akademii Nauk, vol. 373 (2000), no. 1, pp. 1516. Translated as: On surprising extensions of the field of rationals. Doklady Mathematics , vol. 62 (2000), no. 1, pp. 8–9.Google Scholar
Ershov, Y. L., Multi-Valued Fields . Springer, New York, 2001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferrand, D., Conducteur, descente et pincement . Bulletin de la Société Mathématique de France , vol. 131 (2003), no. 4, pp. 553585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Görtz, U. and Wedhorn, T., Algebraic Geometry I . Vieweg+Teubner, Wiesbaden, 2010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grothendieck, A., Éléments de géométrie algébrique: IV. Étude locale des schémas et des morphismes de schémas, Seconde partie . Publications Mathématiques de l’IHÉS , vol. 24 (1965), pp. 5231.Google Scholar
Grothendieck, A., Éléments de géométrie algébrique: IV. Étude locale des schémas et des morphismes de schémas, Quatrième partie . Publications Mathématiques de l’IHÉS , vol. 32 (1967), pp. 5361.Google Scholar
Hodges, W., Model Theory , Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kartas, K., Decidability via the tilting correspondence . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 174 (2023), no. 2, Article no. 103203.Google Scholar
Kartas, K., Diophantine problems over tamely ramified fields . Journal of Algebra , vol. 617 (2023), pp. 127159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhlmann, F.-V., The algebra and model theory of tame valued fields . Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik , vol. 719 (2016), pp. 143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neukirch, J., Schmidt, A., and Wingberg, K., Cohomology of Number Fields , second ed., Springer, Berlin–Heidelberg, 2007.Google Scholar
Poonen, B., Existence of rational points on smooth projective varieties . Journal of the European Mathematical Society , vol. 11 (2009), no. 3, pp. 529543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poonen, B., Rational Points on Varieties , American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2017.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prestel, A. and Roquette, P., Formally $\boldsymbol{p}$ - adic fields . Springer, Berlin–Heidelberg, 1984.Google Scholar
Serre, J.-P., Groups algébriques et corps de classes , Publications de l’Institut de Mathématique de l’Université de Nancago, vol. VII, Herrmann, Paris, 1959.Google Scholar
Shlapentokh, A., Hilbert’s Tenth Problem: Diophantine Classes and Extensions to Global Fields , Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2009.Google Scholar
Soare, R. I., Turing Computability , Springer, Berlin–Heidelberg, 2016.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thanagopal, K., On the decidability of finite extensions of decidable fields , Ph.D. thesis, University of Oxford, 2018. Available at https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:c5b04608-c6ff-4b15-b332-36cadf56144e.Google Scholar
Yekhanin, S., A note on plane pointless curves . Finite Fields and Their Applications , vol. 13 (2007), no. 2, pp. 418422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar