Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-08T07:30:11.053Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Institutional Genidentity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 November 2023

JOSHUA RUST*
Affiliation:
STETSON UNIVERSITY jrust@stetson.edu

Abstract

An abbreviated history of marriage helps motivate the question of whether ancient Roman marriage and contemporary love marriage could qualify as stages of the same (token) institution despite carrying significantly different functions, deontological powers, and constitutive rules. Having raised the question of institutional identity over time, I proceed to answer the question by appealing to Kurt Lewin's notion of genidentity. Lewin intends the notion of genidentity to track the spatiotemporal unfolding of different physical and biological processes, such as ontogenesis. I extend the notion of genidentity to the institutional sphere by identifying two ‘re-anchoring mechanisms’ that would describe the conditions under which institutions with different characteristics could nevertheless qualify as the same institution across time. First, formal institutions can be re-anchored by way of a self-amending secondary rule. Second, informal institutions can be re-anchored by leveraging the inherent indeterminacy of the exemplars that indexically define them. I then argue ancient Roman marriage and contemporary love marriage are genidentical in virtue of the actions of a (mostly) informal re-anchoring mechanism.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Philosophical Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful for the feedback I received from Åsa Burman, Thomas Brouwer, Anna Strasser, Melinda Hall, and the anonymous referees and editor of this journal.

References

Austin, Christopher J. (2020) ‘Organisms, Activity, and Being: On the Substance of Process Ontology’. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 10 (2), 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayers, Michael R. (1981) ‘Locke's Doctrine of Abstraction: Some Aspect of its Historical and Philosophical Significance’. In Brandt, Reinhard (ed.), John Locke: Symposium, Wolfenbüttel, 1979. (Berlin: De Gruyter), 524.Google Scholar
Boniolo, Giovanni, and Carrara, Massimiliano. (2004) ‘On Biological Identity’. Biology and Philosophy, 19 (3), 443–57. https://doi.org/10.1023/B:BIPH.0000036163.02581.15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brännmark, Johan. (2018) ‘Contested Institutional Facts’. Erkenntnis, 84, 1047–64. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-9994-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brouwer, Thomas. (2022) ‘Social Inconsistency’. Ergo, 9, 2. https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2258.Google Scholar
Burman, Åsa. (2022) ‘Telic Power and Its Applications’. Journal of Political Power, 1, 4758. https://doi.org/10.1080/2158379X.2022.2138192.Google Scholar
Carse, James P. (1986) Finite and Infinite Games: A Vision of Life as Play and Possibility. Washington, DC: Free Press.Google Scholar
Castoriadis, Cornelius. (1998) The Imaginary Institution of Society. Boston, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Coontz, Stephanie. (2004) ‘The World Historical Transformation of Marriage’. Journal of Marriage and Family, 66 (4). 974–79. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0022-2445.2004.00067.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coontz, Stephanie. (2006) Marriage, a History: How Love Conquered Marriage. New York, NY: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
DiFrisco, James. (2018) ‘Biological Processes: Criteria of Identity and Persistence’. In Nicholson, Daniel J. and Dupré, John (eds.), Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology (Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press), 7695.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DiFrisco, James, and Mossio, Matteo. (2020) ‘Diachronic Identity in Complex Life Cycles: An Organizational Perspective’. In Meincke, Anne Sophie and Dupré, John (eds.), Biological Identity: Perspectives from Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Biology (New York, NY: Routledge), 177–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobson, James. (2003) ‘Marriage on the Ropes?Focus on the Family Newsletter. September 2003. https://www.catholicfamilycatalog.com/dr-james-dobson-on-marriage.htm.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael. (1975) ‘Wang's Paradox’. Synthese, 30 (3/4), 301–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dupré, John, and Nicholson, Daniel. (2018) ‘A Manifesto for a Processual Philosophy of Biology’. In Nicholson, Daniel and Dupré, John (eds.) Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Brian. (2014) ‘How Many Kinds of Glue Hold the Social World Together?’ In Gallotti, Mattia and Michael, John (eds.), Perspectives on Social Ontology and Social Cognition (New York: Springer), 41-56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Brian. (2015) The Ant Trap: Rebuilding the Foundations of the Social Sciences. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Brian. (2016) ‘A Framework for Social Ontology’. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 46, 147–67. https://doi.org/10.1177/0048393115613494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferguson, Michaele L. (2016) ‘Vulnerability by Marriage: Okin's Radical Feminist Critique of Structural Gender Inequality’. Hypatia, 31, 687703.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. (1794) Foundations of Natural Right. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Griffiths, Paul, and Stotz, Karola. (2018) ‘Developmental Systems Theory as a Process Theory’. In Nicholson, Daniel J. and Dupré, John (eds.), Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 139–66.Google Scholar
Guala, Francesco. (2016) Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Guay, Alexandre, and Pradeu, Thomas. (2015) ‘To Be Continued: The Genidentity of Physical and Biological Processes’. In Guay, Alexandre and Pradeu, Thomas (eds.), Individuals Across the Sciences (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 317–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanna, Robert, and Maiese, Michelle. (2009) Embodied Minds in Action. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (2012) The Concept of Law. Oxford UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hennig, Willi. (1966) Phylogenetic Systematics. Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Herwitz, Daniel. (2012) Star as Icon: Celebrity in the Age of Mass Consumption. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Hindriks, Frank. (2009) ‘Constitutive Rules, Language, and Ontology’. Erkenntnis, 71, 253–75. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-009-9178-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David. (1970) ‘Contemporary Systematic Philosophies’. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 1, 1954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David. (1978) ‘A Matter of Individuality’. Philosophy of Science, 45, 335–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David. (1979) ‘The Limits of Cladism’. Systematic Zoology, 28, 416–40. https://doi.org/10.2307/2412558.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David. (1986) ‘Conceptual Evolution and the Eye of the Octopus’. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 114, 643–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David. (1994) ‘Individual’. In Keller, Evelyn Fox and Lloyd, Elisabeth A. (eds.), Keywords in Evolutionary Biology (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press), 8187.Google Scholar
Innis, Robert. (2001) ‘Philosophy and the Play of Life’. Focaal, 37, 122.Google Scholar
James, Henry. (1921) The Bostonians. New York, NY: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Khalidi, Muhammad Ali. (2013) Natural Categories and Human Kinds: Classification in the Natural and Social Sciences. Cambridge MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. (2011) Art, Self and Knowledge. Oxford UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewin, Kurt. (1920) Die Verwandtschaftsbegriffe in Biologie und Physik und die Darstellung Vollständiger Stammbäume. Berlin: Verlag von Gebrüder Borntraeger. http://hdl.handle.net/2027/uc1.b3349241.Google Scholar
Lewin, Kurt. (1922) Der Begriff der Genese in Physik, Biologie und Entwicklungsgeschichte: Eine Untersuchung zur vergleichenden Wissenschaftslehre. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-26457-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, Emma. (2019) ‘Contracts, Activist Feminism, and “The Wife of Bath's Tale”’. The Chaucer Review, 54, 335–51. https://doi.org/10.5325/chaucerrev.54.3.0335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ludwig, Kirk. (2017) From Plural to Institutional Agency: Collective Action. Vol. 2.Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas. (1996) Social Systems. Translated by Bednarz, John Jr. and Baecker, Dirk. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas. (2008) Law as a Social System. Translated by Ziegert, Klaus. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst. (1969) Principles of Systematic Zoology. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst. (1982) The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance. Harvard MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nicholson, Daniel. (2018) ‘Reconceptualizing the Organism: From Complex Machine to Flowing Stream’. In Nicholson, Daniel J. and Dupré, John (eds.), Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 139–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Okin, Susan M. (1989) Justice, Gender, and the Family. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Olberding, Amy. (2008) ‘Dreaming of the Duke of Zhou: Exemplarism and the Analects’. Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 35, 625–39. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-6253.2008.00508.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olberding, Amy. (2011) Moral Exemplars in the Analects: The Good Person Is That. Oxfordshire UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ovalle, David. (2016) ‘Miami Money-Laundering Case May Define Whether Bitcoin Is Really Money’. Miami Herald. May 27. https://web.archive.org/web/20201112222217/https://www.miamiherald.com/news/local/crime/article80421072.html.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. (1986) Reasons and Persons. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pradeu, Thomas. (2018) ‘Genidentity and Biological Processes’. In Nicholson, Daniel J. and Dupré, John (eds.), Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 96112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. (1923) ‘Vagueness’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1, 8492. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402308540623.Google Scholar
Rust, Joshua. (2021a) ‘Max Weber and Social Ontology’. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 51, 312–42. https://doi.org/10.1177/0048393120986244CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rust, Joshua. (2021b) ‘Von Baer, the Intensification of Uniqueness, and Historical Explanation’. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 43,122. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-021-00473-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John R. (1969) Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John R. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter. (2007) ‘The Thread of Persistence’. In Kanzian, Christian (ed.), Persistence (Berlin: De Gruyter), 165–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simons, Peter. (2018) ‘Processes and Precipitates’. In Nicholson, Daniel J. and Dupré, John (eds.), Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 4960.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Barry, and Mulligan, Kevin. (1982) ‘Pieces of a Theory.’ In Smith, Barry and Kunne, Wolfgang (eds.), Parts and Moments Studies in Logic and Formal Ontology (Munich: Philosophia Verlag), 15109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suber, Peter. (1990) The Paradox of Self-Amendment: A Study of Logic, Law, Omnipotence, and Change. Switzerland: Peter Lang Publishing.Google Scholar
Suits, Bernard Herbert. (1978) The Grasshopper: Games, Life, and Utopia. Ontario: Broadview Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. (2009) Philosophical Investigations. Translated by Schulte, Joachim, Hacker, P. M. S., and Anscombe, G. E. M.. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wollstonecraft, Mary. ([1792] 2013) A Vindication of the Rights of Woman: Abridged, with Related Texts. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda. (2010) ‘Exemplarist Virtue Theory’. Metaphilosophy, 41, 4157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda. (2017) Exemplarist Moral Theory. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar