Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T11:44:52.007Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Emerging sacred values: Iran’s nuclear program

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Morteza Dehghani*
Affiliation:
Northwestern University, Evanston, IL
Rumen Iliev
Affiliation:
Northwestern University, Evanston, IL
Sonya Sachdeva
Affiliation:
Northwestern University, Evanston, IL
Scott Atran
Affiliation:
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris, France
Jeremy Ginges
Affiliation:
New School for Social Research, New York, NY
Douglas Medin
Affiliation:
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris, France
*
*Address correspondence to: Morteza Dehghani, Northwestern University, 2145 Sheridan Road, Evanston, IL 60208, USA. Email: morteza@northwestern.edu.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Sacred values are different from secular values in that they are often associated with violations of the cost-benefit logic of rational choice models. Previous work on sacred values has been largely limited to religious or territorial conflicts deeply embedded in historical contexts. In this work we find that the Iranian nuclear program, a relatively recent development, is treated as sacred by some Iranians, leading to a greater disapproval of deals which involve monetary incentives to end the program. Our results suggest that depending on the prevalence of such values, incentive-focused negotiations may backfire.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2009] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

At least since the end of the Second World War economic and foreign policy decision-making has been dominated by the “rational actor” perspective which assumes that decision-makers model the world on the basis of rational choice (“cost-benefit”) calculations that are commensurable across cultures (Allison & Zelikow, Reference Allison and Zelikow1999). Although it is well accepted that decision makers often fail to make normatively rational choices, the assumption that they nonetheless are seeking to maximize utility dominates. For example, the makeup and performance of the principal forums for U.S. policy (National Security Presidential Directive, 2001; National Economic Council, 2006) leaves little doubt that policy decisions should result from instrumental choices by goal-oriented political and economic actors. The official national security strategy of the United States explicitly states a commitment to “results-oriented planning” that focuses on “actions and results rather than …rule-making” (National Security Strategy of the United States, 2006).

Recent work on “protected” (Baron & Spranca, Reference Baron and Spranca1997; Ritov & Baron, Reference Ritov and Baron1999) or “sacred” (Tetlock, Reference Tetlock2003) values has challenged the presumption that issues under dispute in inter-group conflicts are fungible and can be valued along a common scale. This new body of research has emphasized that protagonists in disputes often invest values with transcendental qualities (Durkheim, 1912/1995) which affect decision-making. For example in a large scale study of Israelis and Palestinians, Ginges, Atran, Medin & Shikaki (Reference Ginges, Atran, Medin and Shikaki2007) presented subjects with peace deals involving mutual compromises over core issues, such as the future of Jerusalem, and experimentally varied incentives to compromise within each deal. In sharp contrast with the rational actor perspective, subjects who viewed the issues under dispute as sacred values responded with greater outrage to deals with added material incentives to compromise those values. Material incentives to compromise backfired presumably because they made salient the taboo against measuring commitment to sacred values along instrumental metrics. However, this paradoxical effect held only for people who treated the issue as a sacred value and not for those who saw the values as important but not sacred.

The existing empirical work on sacred values has been focused predominantly on conflicts embedded in a complex historical contexts often marking the life and identity of several generations (Atran, Axelrod & Davis, Reference Atran and Davis2007), such as, dealing with issues such as sovereignty over Jerusalem, Gaza and the West Bank (Ginges et al., Reference Ginges, Atran, Medin and Shikaki2007; Rozin & Wolf, Reference Rozin and Wolf2008), conflict over the Babri Mosque in India (Sachdeva & Medin, Reference Sachdeva and Medin2009), and centuries old Sharia law in Indonesia (Ginges & Atran, Reference Atran and Ginges2009). Yet, it seems possible that issues with a much narrower historical context can become sacred values, especially when they involve identity-related issues such as sovereignty. In the research reported here, we investigate whether such values would also lead to judgments and decisions that would not be instrumentally rational. Specifically, we focus on Iran’s stance on its national nuclear program, using it as a test bed for emerging sacred values.

In the past few years, the Iranian government has actively defended its right to having a nuclear program in part by framing the dispute as analogues to past historical events in which the advancement of the Iranian nation was interrupted by foreign powers. Specifically, the Iranian government has made “a conscious effort to link the proliferation issue to the struggle for nationalization of oil half a century ago, a struggle that continues to strongly resonate with the Iranian people” (J. Afary, personal communication, December 14, 2009). By drawing parallels between these events, the nuclear dispute is essentially framed as an ongoing resistance with deep historical context. Consequently, the Iranian government has vigorously defended its “inalienable rights” (“Iran Ready to Talk”, 2009) for having the program: at recent news conference Iran’s Foreign Minister Motakki argued, “we cannot have any compromise with respect to the Iranian nation’s inalienable right” to acquire a nuclear capability (Jaseb & Dahl, Reference Jaseb and Dahl2009). While the public discourse in the West about the Iranian nuclear program is focused on risks, costs and benefits, the Iranian position that they “will not retreat one iota” (“Iran Vows”, 2007) and “will ’never ever’ compromise on nuclear dispute” (“Iran will ’never ever”’, 2009) is mainly in the domain of sacred rhetoric (Marietta, 2009).

We investigated whether Iranians who treat the Iranian nuclear program as a sacred value would be amenable to material incentives to compromise. The U.S. and its allies, including the U.K. and France, are currently contemplating material “sanctions that bite” (Obama, Reference Obama2009). It is critical, therefore, to know what the possible reactions of Iranians to sanctions may be. Our results have both theoretical and pragmatic implications, suggesting that depending on the prevalence of such sacred values, incentive-focused negotiations may backfire.

2 Method

Seventy-five Iranian subjects (mean age = 27.8; 34 females, 41 males; 96% having at least a bachelor’s degree) participated in an online survey conducted in English. Subjects were recruited using snowball sampling which consisted of asking subjects to forward the link to the survey to any number of people that they know. First, we assessed subjects’ values regarding the Iranian nuclear program using Baron and Spranca’s (Reference Baron and Spranca1997) measure. The subjects were offered a choice between four options regarding the possibility of Iran giving up its nuclear program:

  1. a. I think this definitely needs to happen.

  2. b. I do not object this.

  3. c. This is acceptable only if the benefits of stopping the program are great enough.

  4. d. This is shouldn’t be done no matter how great the benefits are.

The subjects who answered “d” were categorized as holding this issue as a sacred value. Next, in two between-subject conditions the subjects evaluated a hypothetical deal on the Iranian nuclear program. Half of them responded to the following “Taboo” deal:

Imagine the following hypothetical situation: Iran will give up its nuclear program, while US will drastically reduce its military aid to Israel.

The other half of our subjects responded to a “Taboo+” deal which was the Taboo deal plus an added material incentive:

Imagine the following hypothetical situation: Iran will give up its nuclear program, while US will drastically reduce its military aid to Israel. In addition the EU will pay $ 40 billion to Iran.Footnote 1

We measured support/opposition to the deal indirectly because of political sensitivities. Subjects were asked to predict the extent to which the Iranian people would approve of the deal, be angry about the deal, and believe that the deal was intended to mislead Iranians. This last item was added in order to control for the possibility that people who hold a sacred value might see the instrumental incentive as a signal for a bad compromise and feel suspicious about the deal. Each question was answered on a 6-point scale (1 = they will definitely disapprove it, 6 = they will definitely approve it; 1 = they will definitely get angry, 6 = they will definitely not get angry; 1 = the deal is definitely not misleading, 6 = the deal is definitely misleading).

3 Results

Eleven percent (8 subjects) perceived the Iranian nuclear program as a SV (choice d; 23% selected choice a, 15% choice b, 52% choice c). For predicted anger and predicted approval as separate dependent variables, we ran a 2×2 between-subject ANOVA, where the first factor was the type of deal (Taboo or Taboo+) and the second factor was whether the subject held a sacred value or not. There was a significant interaction for predicted approval (see Figure 1; F(1, 71) = 4.89, p=.0303) and predicted anger (see Figure 2; F(1, 71) = 12.31, p=.0008).

Figure 1: Predicted approval (means, with standard-error bars) as a function of additional Incentives (Taboo vs Taboo+) and Sacred Value (SV). Each small gray point is a subject.

Subjects who held the nuclear program to be sacred predicted less support (t(6)=2.40, p = .0536, d = 1.96) and more anger (t(6)=6.24, p = .0008, d = 4.65) for the materially superior Taboo+ deal, compared to the Taboo deal. Subjects who did not hold Iranian nuclear power as a sacred value were uninfluenced by the added material incentive. Using the measure of suspiciousness toward the deal as a covariate in the analyses did not change the results; therefore the backfire effect of material incentives cannot be attributed to greater suspicions regarding the Taboo+ deal.

4 Discussion

Figure 2: Predicted anger (means and standard errors, with the scale reversed so that high numbers represent greater anger) as a function of additional incentives (Taboo vs Taboo+) and Sacred Value (SV). Each small gray point is a subject..

Previous research into the backfire effect of offering material incentives to induce compromise over sacred values has concentrated on issues with predominantly religious connotations, such as sacred land. The present results suggest that relatively short-lived political discussions can result in strong attitudes which have properties of sacred values. It is important to note that these effects were found in an online, English-speaking sample, a sample which is probably less exposed to the Iranian sacred rhetoric. Although the effect sizes were large, we would predict that Iranians living in Iran with limited access to Western media might show even stronger effects.Footnote 2

It appears that achieving nuclear capability has the capacity for assuming sacredness for Iranians. Some have cautioned the U.S. administration that “You don’t bring down a quasi-holy symbol — nuclear power — by cutting off gasoline sales” (Cohen, Reference Cohen2009).Footnote 3 Our empirical results support this stance, suggesting that a policy wholly based on a “carrots and sticks” approach may actually backfire. In conflicts involving sacred values, symbolic compromises which may lack any material benefits, such as apologies for past disrespects, may be key to solving the issue (Atran, Axelrod & Davis, Reference Atran and Davis2007). To the extent that these sentiments pervade thinking and policymaking in Iran, the debate may need to shift from sanctions and “business-like” negotiations to symbolic gestures (Atran & Ginges, Reference Ginges, Atran, B. H., Bartels, Bauman, L. J. and Medin2009). Given the enormous political stakes involved in these types of issues, further research along these lines is urgently needed.

Footnotes

*

MD, RI and SS contributed equally to this work and took leading roles. SA, JG and DM were primarily involved in the writing and analysis stages of this work. This work was supported by the National Science Foundation (NSF SES 0527396) and by Air Force Office of Scientific Research (AFOSR FA9550-05-1-0321 and AFOSR FA9550-09-C-0119).

1 It is worthy to note that in politics often cash incentives are used both for reparation and compromise. Germany’s offer of material aid to Israel, which Israel initially rejected although the country was in dire financial straits (Lustick, Reference Lustick2006) and Japan’s offer to give monetary compensation to countries that it had subjected to sexual slavery (Onishi, Reference Onishi2007) are among examples where cash incentives were used for reparation. More recently, US offered $ 25 million for information leading to capture of Osama bin Laden, which violated a sacred Pashtun value that tribesmen are generally willing to defend to the death (Atran, Reference Atran2009). Moreover, the removal or lifting of economic sanctions could be seen as a form of cash incentive, although we did not present it that way.

2 We also note that the critical sample, those with sacred values, was quite small, 8 subjects. We still feel that these results should be taken seriously. First, the present results are a conceptual replication of the Ginges et al. (Reference Ginges, Atran, Medin and Shikaki2007) study in a different context, thus plausible and not surprising in themselves. Second, small samples as such do not compromise the meaning of statistical significance. Significant results with small samples require large effect sizes. It is worth noting that, in general, the probability of replication of a result is dependent on p-levels but not affected by sample size (e.g., Killeen, Reference Killeen2005).

3 Events at the time of writing are instructive. On November 27, 2009 The New York Times reported that the United States was working on a package of sanctions to impose on Iran if the Iranians did not halt the construction of an Iranian uranium enrichment facility at Qum (Cooper & Broad, Reference Cooper and Broad2009). Two days later, the BBC reported the Iranians countering with an “act of defiance” (“Iran planning 10 new uranium enrichment sites”, 2009)

References

Allison, G., Zelikow, P. (1999) Essence of decision: explaining the Cuban missile crisis. New York: Addison-Wesley Longman.Google Scholar
Atran, S. (2009, December 13) To beat al Qaeda, look to the east. The New York Times. Retrieved December 13, 2009 from http://www.nytimes.com/2009/12/13/opinion/13atran.htmlGoogle Scholar
Atran, S. Axelrod, R. & Davis, R. (2007) Sacred barriers to conflict resolution. Science, 317 10391040.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Atran, S. & Ginges, J. (2009, January 24) How words could end a war. The New York Times. Retrieved December 16, 2009 from http://www.nytimes.com/2009/01/25/opinion/25atran.htmlGoogle Scholar
Baron, J. & Spranca, M. (1997)Protected values. Organizational Behavior and Decision Processes, 70 116.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cohen, R. (2009, September 27) The U.S.-Iranian triangle. The New York Times. Retrieved September 28, 2009 from http://www.nytimes.com/2009/09/28/opinion/28iht-edcohen.html.Google Scholar
Cooper, H. & Broad, W. J. (2009, November 28) Russia and China endorse agency’s rebuke of Iran. The New York Times. Retrieved December 10, 2009 from http://www.nytimes.com/2009/11/28/world/28nuke.html Google Scholar
Durkheim, E. (1995). The elementary form of the religious life. Free Press. (Original Work Published in 1912)Google Scholar
Ginges, J., Atran, S., Medin, D. & Shikaki, K. (2007). Sacred bounds on rational resolution of violent political conflict. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104 7357-7360.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ginges, J., & Atran, S. (2009) Noninsturmental reasoning over sacred values: An Indonesian case study. In B. H., Ross (Series Ed.) & Bartels, D. M. , Bauman, C. W.L. J., Skitka , & Medin, D. L. (Eds.), pp. 193206. Psychology of Learning and Motivation, Vol. 50: Moral Judgment and Decision Making. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iran planning 10 new uranium enrichment sites (2009, November 29). British Broadcasting Corporation. Retrieved November 29, 2009, from http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/middle_east/8385275.stmGoogle Scholar
Iran ready to talk but refuse negotiations on “inalienable rights”. (2009). Retrieved July 14, 2009, from http://www.highbeam.com/doc/1P2-16072214.html Google Scholar
Iran will “never ever” compromise in nuclear dispute (2008). Retrieved July 14, 2009, from http://news.trend.az/index.shtml?show=news&newsid=1139736&lang=EN Google Scholar
Iran vows not to “retreat one iota” in nuclear pursuit (2007). Retrieved July 14, 2009, from http://www.cnn.com/2007/WORLD/meast/02/21/iran.nuclear/index.htmlGoogle Scholar
Jaseb, H. & Dahl, F. (2009) Iran signals no compromise on nuclear issue. Reuters news service,Retrieved September 12, 2009 from http://www.reuters.com/article/idUSLA38110920090912 .Google Scholar
Killeen, P. R. (2005). An alternative to null-hypothesis significance testing. Psychological Science, 16 345353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lustick, I. (2006)Negotiating truth: the Holocaust, Lehavdil, and al-Nakba. Journal of International Affairs, 60, 5180.Google Scholar
Marietta, M. (2008). From my cold, dead hands: Democratic consequences of sacred rhetoric. The Journal of Politics, 70 767779.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
National Security Presidential Directive (2001).Organization of the National Security Council System. Retrieved December 1, 2009 from http://www.fas.org/irp/offdocs/nspd/nspd-1.htmGoogle Scholar
National Economic Council (2006.); Retrieved December 1, 2009 from http://www.whitehouse.gov/nec/Google Scholar
National Security Strategy of the United States (2006.); Retrieved December 1, 2009 from http://www.whitehouse.gov/nsc/nss/2006/nss2006.pdfGoogle Scholar
Obama, B. H. (2009). G20 summit. Pittsburgh, USA (September 25, 2009).Google Scholar
Onishi, N. (2007, April 25). Japan’s atonement to former sex slaves stir anger. The New York Times.Google Scholar
Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1999). Protected values and omission bias. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 79, 79–94.Google Scholar
Rozin, P. & Wolf, S. (2008). Attachment to land: The case of the land of Israel for American and Israeli Jews and the role of contagion. Judgment and Decision Making, 3 325334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sachdeva, S., & Medin, D. (2009). Group Identity Salience in Sacred Value Based Cultural Conflict: An Examination of the Hindu-Muslim Identities in the Kashmir and Babri Mosque Issues. In the Proceedings of the 31th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (CogSci), Amsterdam, Holland.Google Scholar
Tetlock, P. (2003). Thinking the Unthinkable: Sacred Values and Taboo Cognitions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7 320–24.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Figure 0

Figure 1: Predicted approval (means, with standard-error bars) as a function of additional Incentives (Taboo vs Taboo+) and Sacred Value (SV). Each small gray point is a subject.

Figure 1

Figure 2: Predicted anger (means and standard errors, with the scale reversed so that high numbers represent greater anger) as a function of additional incentives (Taboo vs Taboo+) and Sacred Value (SV). Each small gray point is a subject..

Supplementary material: File

Supplementary material

Supplementary material
Download Supplementary material(File)
File 2.3 KB