Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qlrfm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-08T12:39:41.208Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A republican defence of the constitutional referendum

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Eoin Daly*
Affiliation:
UCD School of Law
*
Eoin Daly, University College Dublin, Law, Belfield, Dublin 4, Ireland. Email: eoin.daly@ucd.ie

Abstract

The constitutional referendum is often conceptualised as the ultimate institutional expression of popular sovereignty. However, ‘direct democracy’ is viewed apprehensively by many political and legal theorists, particularly republican scholars. They argue that referendums risk engendering a dangerous ‘populism’ while detracting from the deliberative and moderating virtues of parliamentary democracy. In this paper, I defend the political value of the constitutional referendum from within republican theory, arguing that there is a misplaced focus on parliamentary supremacy within much of the literature on ‘political constitutionalism’. However, I argue it should be valued neither as a mechanism for giving expression to popular will, nor as an intervention by the mythologised ‘constituent power’ – or indeed, contra Tierney, as a ‘sovereign’ exercise in any sense. Rather, it has two main, overlapping virtues: first, its role in facilitating the contestation and checking of executive power in the area of constitutional change, and secondly, its instrumental role in fostering a wider culture of civic participation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Society of Legal Scholars 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Madison, JFederalist Paper no 10’ in Rossiter, C (ed) The Federalist Papers: Hamilton, Madison, Jay (New York: Mentor, 1961) p 81.Google Scholar

2. Tierney, S Constitutional Referendums: The Theory and Practice of Republican Deliberation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012) p 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3. Pettit, PDeliberative democracy, the discursive dilemma and republican theory’ in Fishkin, J and Laslett, P (eds) Philosophy, Politics and Society, vol 7 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003) pp 138162.Google Scholar

4. Pettit, P Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997);Google Scholar Skinner, Q Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998).Google Scholar

5. Pettit, PAbolition of Seanad would be significant loss to democracyIrish Times 28 July 2012. For a wider view of Pettit's advocacy of democracy through ‘responsive’ representative institutions and the most recent statement of his overall political theory, seeGoogle Scholar Pettit, P On the People's Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2013).Google Scholar

6. See eg Bellamy, R Political Constitutionalism (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007);CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed Tomkins, A Our Republican Constitution (Oxford: Hart, 2005).Google Scholar

7. See Montesquieu, C Spirit of the Laws (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1748/1989).Google Scholar

8. Honohan, I Civic Republicanism (London: Routledge, 2002) ch 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9. Rousseau, JJ Du Contrat Social (Paris: ENAG, 1988).Google Scholar

10. See generally Skinner, above n 4; Cicero On Duties (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999);Google Scholar Pocock, Jga The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003).Google Scholar

11. Above n 4.

12. Honohan, above n 8, p 25.

13. Ibid, pp 219–222.

14. Pettit, PThe tree of liberty: republicanism, American, French and Irish’ (2005) 1 Field Day Rev 30, 30.Google Scholar

15. Pettit On the People's Terms, above n 5, ch 1.

16. Ibid, chs 4 and 5.

17. Pettit, above n 4, p 18.

18. This is used in reference to the ‘neo-Roman’ strand.

19. Pettit, PLaw and liberty’ in Besson, S and Marti, JL (eds) Legal Republicanism: National and International Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).Google Scholar

20. Tomkins, above n 6, ch 4.

21. Pettit, above n 4, p 193.

22. Above 6.

23. Cinneide, C O'“the people are the masters” – the paradox of constitutionalism and the uncertain status of popular sovereignty within the Irish constitutional order’ (2012) Irish Jurist 249 at 256.Google Scholar

24. Pettit, above n 4, p 8.

25. Pettit, above n 3, pp 152–155.

26. Clark, SA populist critique of direct democracy’ (1998) 112 Harv L Rev 434 at 435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27. Bellamy, above n 6, ch 5.

28. Ibid, p 5.

29. Tomkins, above n 6, p 3.

30. Ibid.

31. Bellamy, RRepublicanism, democracy and constitutionalism’ in Laborde, C and Maynor, J (eds) Republicanism and Political Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 2008) p 164.Google Scholar

32. Bellamy, above n 6, p 262.

33. Honohan, above n 8, p 222.

34. Tierney, SConstitutional referendums: a theoretical inquiry’ (2009) Mod L Rev 360 at 368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

35. Ibid.

36. Pettit, above n 3, p 140.

37. Ibid.

38. Serdült argued before the House of Lords Select Committee on the Constitution: ‘direct democracy is an institutional weapon for organized interests (political parties, interest groups, employer's and employee's associations)’. 12th Report of Session 2009–2010: ‘Referendums in the United Kingdom’, at 137. See also Honohan, above n 8, pp 220–230, 237.

39. Haider-Markel, I, Querze, A and Lindaman, KLose, win, or draw? a reexamination of direct democracy and minority rights’ (2007) 60 Pol Res Q 304; B Frey and L Goette ‘Does the popular vote destroy civil rights?’ (1998) 42 Am J Pol Sci 1343;Google Scholar Moeckli, DOf minarets and foreign criminals: Swiss direct democracy and human rights11(4) Hum Rts L Rev (2011) 774. Moeckli asserts (p 778) ‘Empirical work testing that assumption is surprisingly sparse.’Google Scholar

40. Honohan, above n 8, p 218.

41. O'Cinneide, above n 233, p 256.

42. Wolin, S Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Western Political Thought (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2009), p 565 (as cited in O'Cinneide, above n 23, p 265).Google Scholar

43. Tierney, above n 34.

44. Ibid, p 368.

45. See Tierney, above n 2, pp 132–135.

46. Tierney, above n 34, at 361, 362.

47. Tierney, above n 2, p 15; Tierney, above n 34, at 364.

48. Tierney, above n 2, p 13.

49. The popular initiative is more commonly used for ordinary-legislative issues than for constitutional amendment. However, there are exceptions: Arts 138–139 of the Swiss Constitution provide that it can be amended by a referendum initiated by a petition of 100,000 electors.

50. The term ‘referendum’ as used in this paper refers to plebiscites, generally including those triggered by voter petition.

51. Moeckli, above n 39.

52. Tierney, above n 2, p 127.

53. See eg Setälä, MReferendums in Western Europe – a wave of direct democracy?’ (1999) 22 Scand Pol Stud 327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

54. See above n 49.

55. Kissane, BIs the Irish referendum majoritarian?’ In Marxer, W (ed) Direct Democracy and Minorities (Wiesbaden: Springer VS, 2012).Google Scholar

56. Articles 46 and 47.

57. Danish Constitution of 1953, s 88; Constitution of Switzerland, ss 138–139.

58. Chapter VIII, s 128.

59. ‘… [A]s a matter of constitutional law a referendum cannot be binding in this country’. ‘Referendums in the United Kingdom’, above n 38, at 134.

60. See section 3.

61. Tierney, above n 2, p 128.

62. Tierney, above n 34, at 361, emphasis added.

63. Ibid, at 364, emphasis added.

64. For the Swiss example, see Moeckli, above n 39, at 781.

65. Tierney, above n 2, p 13. In ch 7, Tierney uses the examples of plebiscites in South Sudan and East Timor.

66. Ibid, p 15.

67. See Colón-Ríos, JDe-constitutionalizing democracy’ (2010) 47(1) Cal W L Rev 41 at 90.Google Scholar

68. Tierney, above n 2, p 15.

69. Tierney, above n 34, at 367.

70. Tierney, above n 2, p 14.

71. Tierney, above n 34, at 379.

72. Tierney distinguishes between ‘constitution-changing’ referendums as exercises of ‘command sovereignty’, and ‘constitution-framing’ referendums as exercises of ‘constituent sovereignty’. Tierney, above n 2, pp 14–16.

73. See Sinnott, RCleavages, parties and referendums: relationships between representative and direct democracy in the Republic of Ireland’ (2003) 41 Eur J Pol Res 811.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

74. ‘Referendums in the United Kingdom’, above n 38, at 74. See also European Union Act 2011, below, 78.

75. Tierney above n 34, at 361.

76. Pettit, above n 3.

77. See Coffey, DJudicial review in the Irish Free State’ (2011) Dublin U L J 61.Google Scholar

78. This is strengthened by the European Union Act 2011. Bogdanor claims ‘conventions have grown up’ that a referendum is required before ‘any significant devolution of powers away from Westminster’ or ‘when a wholly novel constitutional arrangement is proposed’, but ‘not in relation to the European Union’. ‘Referendums in the United Kingdom’, above n 38, at 25. However, Hazell argued: ‘at best, we can venture a partial doctrine that referendums are required for devolution, for a constitutional change whereby the Westminster Parliament delegates legislative power to a subordinate legislative body’. Ibid, Q2.

79. Pettit, above n 3.

80. Ibid, p 155.

81. Articles 26, 34.3.1.

82. Third Amendment of the Constitution Bill 1958; Third Amendment of the Constitution Bill 1968.

83. Kissane, above n 55, p 152.

84. Thirtieth Amendment of the Constitution Bill 2011.

85. See eg Fifteenth Amendment of the Constitution Bill 1996; Eight Amendment of the Constitution 1983.

86. Seventeenth Amendment of the Constitution 1997.

87. In the Irish Free State, ordinary Acts inconsistent with the Constitution were simply accepted by the courts as amendments to it. State (Ryan) v Lennon [1935] IR 170.

88. Kissane, above n 55, p 153.

89. Chiaramonte, A and Alimonte, RDThe twilight of the Berlusconi era: local elections and national referendums in Italy, May and June 2011’ (2012) 17 S Eur Soc'y & Pol 261 at 329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

90. Fabbrini, SHas Italy rejected the referendum path to change? the failed referenda of May 2000’ (2001) 6 J Mod Ital Stud 38 at 53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

91. Sinnott, above n 73, at 811. ‘Only four of the 27 referendums held in the Republic of Ireland have involved major inter-party conflict’; p 815.

92. Bellamy, above n 31, p 364.

93. See Carolan, ERecovering the Republic? Democratic representation and the mixed theory of government’ (2012) Irish Jurist 173.Google Scholar

94. Tierney above n 34, at 364.

95. This challenges Tierney's claim that ‘constitutional referendums implicate what is perhaps the central relationship within constitutional democracy – that between constituent power and constitutional form’; ibid.

96. Ibid, at 363.

97. Ibid, at 366.

98. O'Cinneide, above n 23, at 256.

99. Jacobsohn, JAn unconstitutional constitution? a comparative perspective’ (2006) 4(3) Int'l J Const L 460.Google Scholar

100. Dáil Éireann debates, vol 67, cols 74–76, 11 May 1937.

101. [1972] IR 241.

102. [1972] IR 241, 262.

103. Webb v Ireland [1988] IR 353. See also Doherty v Government of Ireland [2010] IEHC 369.

104. Sullivan v Robinson [1954] IR 161, 174.

105. The Supreme Court rejected a claim that the Constitution protected consensual adult same-sex relations on the grounds that in 1937, the people, given their Christian beliefs, could not have ‘intended’ it to apply this way. Norris v Att. Gen. [1984] IR 36.

106. Article 46 provides that ‘any provision’ of the Constitution may be amended ‘whether by way of variation, addition or repeal’.

107. Finn v Att. Gen [1983] IR 154; Riordan v An Taoiseach (No 2) [1998] IEHC.

108. Re Article 26 and the Regulation of Information (Services Outside the State for Termination of Pregnancies) Bill 1995 [1995] 1 IR 1.

109. See generally Schachter, JThe pursuit of “popular intent”: interpretive dilemmas in direct democracy’ (1995) 105 Yale L J 107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

110. This argument was addressed in section 2.

111. Honohan, above n 8, p 220.

112. Clark, above n 26.

113. Dáil Éireann debates, vol 67, col 40, 11 May 1937.

114. See generally Honohan, above n 8.

115. Pitkin, H.Justice: on relating private and public’ (1981) 9 Pol Theory 327 at 349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

116. Pettit, above n 4, p 185.

117. Honohan, above n 8, p 217, emphasis in original.

118. Ibid, p 215.

119. O'Cinneide, above n 2, p 269.

120. Ibid, p 256.

121. Dworkin, R Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1978) p xi.Google ScholarPubMed

122. Loughlin, M and Walker, NIntroduction’ in Loughlin, M and Walker, N (eds) The Paradox of Constitutionalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007) p 1.Google Scholar

123. O'Cinneide, above n 23, p 268.

124. Ibid, p 260.

125. See Cohen, JReflections on Habermas and democracy’ (1999) 4 Ratio Juris 385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

126. Pettit, above n 4, p 201.

127. Rawls, J Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007) p 224.Google Scholar

128. Dagger, RNeo-republicanism and the civic economy’ (2006) 5 Pol, Phil, Econ 151 at 155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

129. JJ Rousseau ‘Considerations on the government of Poland’ (1772). For a translation, see Considerations on the government of Poland’ in F Watkins Rousseau: Political Writings (Edinburgh: Thomas Nelson, 1953).Google Scholar

130. Goodin, RFolie républicaine’ (2003) 6 Ann Rev Pol Sci 55 at 63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

131. Callan, E Creating Citizens: Political Education and Liberal Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar

132. Bellamy, above n 6; Tomkins, above n 6; Waldron, JThe core of the case against judicial review’ (2006) 115 Yale L J 1346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

133. O'Cinneide argues ‘giving more authority to legislatures may not necessarily enhance the substantive dimension of democracy, i.e. the background conditions that must be in place to enable the public at large to genuinely engage with the democratic process’; above n 23, p 268.

134. Ibid, p 219.

135. Ibid, p 165.

136. Ibid.

137. Bellamy, above n 6, p 6.

138. Honohan, above n 8, p 216.

139. Ibid, p 217.

140. See eg Svensson, PDenmark: the referendum as minority protection’ in Gallagher, M and Uleri, PV The Referendum Experience in Europe (London: Macmillan, 1996) pp 3351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

141. Smith argued before the House of Lords Select Committee: ‘by offering the opportunity to participate directly in policy-making, [referendums] made the public more likely to participate in political activity, as they understand that their participation in the electoral process has real policy implications’; above n 38, at 141. See Smith, DA and Tolbert, C Educated by Initiative: The Effects of Direct Democracy on Citizens and Political Organizations in the American States (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

142. Mendelsohn, M and Cutler, FThe effect of referendums on democratic citizens: information, politicization, efficacy and tolerance’ (2000) 30 Br J Pol Sci 685 at 691–696.Google Scholar

143. Callan, above n 131.

144. Honohan, above n 8, p 223.

145. Ibid, p 217

146. Barber, B Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1984) p 284.Google Scholar

147. Smith and Tolbert, above n 141, p xiv.

148. Ibid, p xvi.

149. Ibid, p xviii.

150. Mendelsohn and Cutler, above n 142, at 698.

151. Honoha, above n 8, p 242. In the UK, see the Political Parties, Elections and Referendums Act (PPERA) 2000. In Ireland, the Supreme Court held that the Constitution prohibits the use of public funds to campaign for a ‘Yes’ vote. McKenna v An Taoiseach (no 2) [1995] 2 IR 10. The Referendum Act 1998 facilitated the creation of an independent Referendum Commission.

152. V Bogdanor ‘Nothing to lose but our free time’ Times Higher Education, 23 September 2005.

153. Constant, BDe la liberté des anciens comparée à celle des modernes’ in Constant, B Ecrits Politiques (Paris: Gallimard/Folio, 1997) pp 591619.Google Scholar

154. Bellamy, above n 6, p 146.

155. Ibid, p 154.

156. O'Cinneide, above n 23, p 258.