Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-9q27g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T14:50:48.128Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Old Germanic Law analogies in International Law, or the State as Homo Liber

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 May 2009

Get access

Extract

In his collected lectures, the late legal historian in the University of Groningen, Professor P.W.A. Immink, draws an interesting parallel between Old Germanic law on the one hand, and present-day international law on the other hand. His argument runs as follows.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © T.M.C. Asser Press 1978

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. De wording van Staat en souvereiniteit in de Middeleeuwen (The Genesis of State and Sovereignty in the Middle Ages), 2nd ed. (Groningen, 1969).Google Scholar

2. Op. cit, pp. 1314Google Scholar, Professor Immink sees an Old Germanic period (roughly until A.D. 500), a Frankish (Merovingian and Caiolingian) period (A.D. 500–1000), and, in the Northern Netherlands, a period dominated by bishops, dukes, counts, etc. who shook off the king or emperor, becoming sovereigns themselves (the landsheerlijke periode, starting around A.D. 1000 and lasting until A.D. 1581, the year King Philip II of Spain, then landsheer, was abjured).

3. Op. cit., pp. 2126.Google Scholar

4. Ibid. p. 40.

5. Ibid. p. 38.

6. Ibid. pp. 18–19: just like the Roman Emperor had auctoritas over the Old Germanic tribes with whom he concluded a treaty and the latter had but potestas, there now are permanent members of the Security Council with a right of veto which the other members lack. But see the refutation of this view at p. 60 infra.

7. Ibid. pp. 27–28.

8. Professor H.J. Scheltema in his In Memoriam for Professor Immink. See De wording van Staat en souvereiniteit in de Middeleeuwen, p. XIV.Google Scholar

9. ProfessorImmink, , op. cit., p. 27.Google Scholar

10. Ibid. p. 95.

11. Ibid. pp. 29–30. To avoid an overdose of subjectiveness, objective criteria were developed for malicious intent, for example, stealth instead of openness.

12. Being a Penonenverbandsstaat (Germ.), that is, a “State” based on the personal (feudal) bond between superiors and vassals. Comp. Immink, , op.cit., pp. 45 and 73.Google Scholar

13. Brunner, Otto, Land und Herrschaft – Grundfragen der territorialen Verfassungsgeschichte Südostdeutschlands im Mittelalter, 2nd. ed. (Brünn-Munich-Vienna, 1942), p. 121.Google Scholar

14. Ibid. pp. 19, 83 and 107.

15. Ibid. pp. 5–6.

16. Ibid. p. 13.

17. Ibid. pp. 5 and 121.

18. Ibid. pp. 10–11.

19. Ibid. p. 20.

20. Ibid. p. 31.

21. Ibid. pp. 12–13. Janssen, , Die Anfänge des modernen Völkerrechts und der neuzeitlichen DiplomatieGoogle Scholar, Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte, XXXVIII. Band (1964) p. 476Google Scholar, rightly points out the total contrast between Brunner's view and the traditional one interpreting feuds as illegal imitations of State wars, as “bloody sport” (Nuszbaum). Brunner's view he calls well documented.

22. Brunner, , op. cit., pp. 148153Google Scholar; and see p. 162: “So lebt denn das einheitliche Rechtsbewusstsein der Frühzeit während des ganzen Mittelalters fort”.

23. Ibid. pp. 156 and 161.

24. Ibid. p. 156.

25. Ibid. p. 13. Comp. the present-day concept of “une Europe civile”.

26. Brunner, , op. cit., p. 31.Google Scholar

27. Ibid. p. 122 (this writer's translation).

28. Ibid. pp. 2 and 13, footnote 3.

29. Immink, , op. cit., pp. XIVXVI and 1719.Google Scholar

30. In all probability, the “Frankish” kings to whom reference is going to be made infra were not “Germanic” kings, stricto sensu, but the question has to be passed over, here. On the origin of the Franks, see Grand, , Recherches sur l'origine des Francs (Paris, 1965).Google Scholar

31. See footnote 12 supra.

32. Seep. 51 supra.

33. Immink, , op. cit., pp. 4546 and 4950.Google Scholar

34. Ibid. pp. 56 and 58–59.

35. Ibid. p. 74.

36. Ibid. pp. 76–78.

37. Ibid. pp. 79 and 87.

38. Ibid. pp. 84 and 86.

39. Ibid. p. 89.

40. Brunner, , op. cit., pp. 3739 and 7071.Google Scholar

41. See footnote 2 supra.

42. Brunner, , op. cit., p. 39.Google Scholar One of the techniques of restriction was ever more to diminish the number of those entitled to feud. See Janssen, , loc. cit., p. 477.Google Scholar

43. Brunner, , op. cit., p. 38.Google Scholar

44. Ibid. p. 107: “Die Fehde ist (….) Kampf urns Recht”.

45. Ibid. p. 54.

46. Ibid. pp. 153–154.

47. Immink, , op. cit., pp. 91105.Google Scholar

48. An implied reference to the idea of allodium in connextion with the State is to be found in SirWhevell, Henry Sumner Maine's. Lectures on International Law (London, 1888) pp. 5657Google Scholar: “Evidentally the fundamental conception was that the territory belonged to the Tribe, and that the Sovereign was Sovereign of the Tribe. The fact is that the feudalisation of Europe had to be completed before it was possible that Sovereignty could be associated with a definite portion of soil”.

49. In abstracto, for no account is taken of the destructive effects of too much violence.

50. See p. 58 supra.

51. In the Middle Ages as well as in Jean Bodin's view of the absolutist ruler, even the so-called princeps legibus solutus was subject to the ius divinum et naturae. See Brunner, , op. cit., p. 437Google Scholar (and pp. 435–442 on the principle princeps legibus solutus generally, five different meanings of which are discussed).

52. See p. 52 supra.

53. See the present writer's study “Principles of Rational Organization as Applied in the Process of Law” in Essays on International Law and Relations in honour of Tammes, A.J.P., 24 N.I.L.R. (1977) pp. 43 et seq.Google Scholar

54. In the same vein, see SirFitzmaurice, Gerald, The Future of Public International Law and of the International Legal System in the Circumstances of Today, Institut de Droit International, Livre du Centenaire 18731973 (Basle, 1973), pp. 257258.Google Scholar The author excludes “as chimerical a world in which all national divisions had been abolished, and which functioned as would a single unitary State”. But see Janssen, , loc. cit., p. 478Google Scholar: a unitary State only with obligatory jurisdiction and powers to enforce will be in a position to match the individual State's achievement in the abolition of feuds, and to ban war.