Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-swr86 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T16:26:53.914Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Strategic Discrimination

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 September 2020

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Why are women and people of color under-represented in U.S. politics? I offer a new explanation: strategic discrimination. Strategic discrimination occurs when an individual hesitates to support a candidate out of concern that others will object to the candidate’s identity. In a series of three experiments, I find that strategic discrimination exists, it matters for real-world politics, and it can be hard to overcome. The first experiment shows that Americans consider white male candidates more electable than equally qualified Black and white women, and to a lesser extent, Black men. These results are strongly intersectional, with Black women rated less electable than either Black men or white women. The second experiment demonstrates that anti-Trump voters weigh Democratic candidates’ racial and gender identities when deciding who is most capable of beating Donald Trump in 2020. The third experiment finds that while some messages intended to combat strategic discrimination have no effect, diverse candidates can increase their perceived electability by showing that they have a path to victory. I conclude by arguing that strategic discrimination is especially salient in contemporary U.S. politics due to three parallel trends: increasing diversity among candidates, growing awareness of sexism and racism, and high levels of political polarization.

Type
Special Section: The Glass Ceiling/Gender
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

When women and people of color run for office in the United States, they do well. Female candidates win as often as male candidates (Smith and Fox Reference Smith and Fox2001; Lawless and Pearson Reference Lawless and Pearson2008; Dolan Reference Dolan2014; Anastasopoulos Reference Anastasopoulos2016),Footnote 1 and racial bias appears not to play a decisive role in most modern elections (Highton Reference Highton2004; Abrajano and Alvarez Reference Abrajano and Alvarez2005; Mas and Moretti Reference Mas and Moretti2009; Juenke and Shah Reference Juenke and Shah2016).Footnote 2 Indeed, in the 2018 midterms, female and nonwhite candidates won at rates that equaled or exceeded their white male counterparts (Reflective Democracy Campaign 2019).

So why do women and people of color remain underrepresented in U.S. politics? The candidate emergence literature suggests this disparity may originate in the pre-primary period, when prospective candidates test the waters, decide to run, and establish their viability (e.g., Shah Reference Shah2014; Shah, Scott, and Juenke Reference Shah, Scott and Juenke2019; Doherty, Dowling, and Miller Reference Doherty, Dowling and Miller2019). During this critical time, even slight headwinds can derail a nascent campaign—and compared to white men, women and people of colorFootnote 3 must navigate a rockier path to candidacy, with more bumps and off ramps along the way. Female and nonwhite candidates have to deal with overt harassmentFootnote 4 and disparities in financial resources (Crowder-Meyer Reference Crowder-Meyer2013), party recruitment (Niven Reference Niven1998; Lawless and Fox Reference Lawless and Fox2010; Crowder-Meyer Reference Crowder-Meyer2013; Butler and Preece Reference Butler and Preece2016), personal and professional networks (Fox and Lawless Reference Fox and Lawless2008; Carroll and Sanbonmatsu Reference Carroll and Sanbonmatsu2013; Crowder-Meyer Reference Crowder-Meyer2013), and political ambition and self-efficacy (Lawless and Fox Reference Lawless and Fox2010; Fox and Lawless Reference Fox and Lawless2011).

On top of these well-documented challenges, I identify another obstacle facing diverse candidates in the pre-primary period: strategic discrimination. Strategic discrimination occurs when an individual hesitates to support a candidate out of concern that others will object to some aspect of the candidate’s identity. The problem is not animus toward the candidate. In contrast to direct bias, strategic discrimination is motivated by the belief that a candidate’s identity will cause other people not to donate, volunteer, or vote for him or her.

Strategic discrimination is closely related to the idea of electability. In the run-up to a primary election, party leaders, donors, and activists want to recruit and support a well-qualified candidate who shares their policy preferences. But they also need a candidate who will be capable of winning the general election. So party gatekeepers and primary voters attempt to guess how others will react to prospective candidates. Will a candidate be able to raise the money necessary to run an aggressive campaign? Will he or she generate positive media coverage? Will enough general election voters support a candidate, or will they refuse to vote for him or her?

In this “futures market” of politics (Bai Reference Bai2004), female and nonwhite candidates are at a disadvantage. If party leaders, donors, and primary voters think a candidate could face discrimination later in the campaign season, they may hesitate to place their bets on him or her. Strategic discrimination thus forces female and nonwhite candidates to work doubly hard to establish themselves as real contenders. In addition to running a “traditional campaign,” they also have to run a parallel “‘campaign of belief’ convincing people that it is possible for them to win” (Barbara Lee Family Foundation 2019, 6).

After developing a theory of strategic discrimination, I present a series of three survey experiments that provide initial evidence of strategic discrimination. The first experiment finds that when presented with profiles of hypothetical gubernatorial candidates, Americans consider white men more electable than equally qualified Black women, white women, and less significantly, Black men.

The second experiment was conducted amidst the 2020 Democratic presidential primary. The results suggest that anti-Trump subjects consider candidates’ racial and gender identities when making strategic calculations about who is most likely to beat Donald Trump in 2020. When anti-Trump subjects are primed to think about the strategic importance of male and white voters, they evaluate female and Black Democratic presidential candidates, especially Elizabeth Warren and Kamala Harris, as significantly less likely to beat Trump.

The third experiment investigates possible strategies for combatting strategic discrimination. It finds that informing subjects about the true, low levels of bias against female and Black candidates has no effect. Neither does identifying strategic discrimination as a problem and discouraging subjects from engaging in it. More promisingly, when anti-Trump subjects read a message emphasizing the strategic importance of Black voters, they see Black Democratic presidential candidates as more competitive vis-à-vis Trump. A priming message about the success of a Black female congressional candidate in a majority-white Trump-leaning district has similar if smaller effects for both female and Black candidates. Rather than attempting to change misperceptions of others’ biases, diverse candidates may be better served by emphasizing their own strategic advantages.

Taken in combination, these three experiments suggest that strategic discrimination exists in the abstract, it can affect perceptions of real-world candidates, and it can be tricky to combat. While more research remains to be done, these preliminary results show that strategic discrimination can complicate the road to candidacy for women and people of color. When it comes to candidate emergence, the rules of the game are both raced and gendered.Footnote 5

A New Theory of Discrimination in Politics

Shortly after Abdul El-Sayed began running in the 2018 Democratic primary for governor of Michigan, “very powerful people who call a lot of the shots in the party” sat him down for a little chat. According to El-Sayed, these party insiders told him, “We think you’re great. You just, you know, it’s not that we’re racist. It’s just that we think that people outside of Southeast Michigan are racist, and so you can’t win. See? It makes sense” (quoted in Culham Reference Culham2018).

Variants of this conversation occurred across the United States throughout the 2018 campaign cycle. When former Representative Katie Hill started her campaign in California’s 25th district, key gatekeepers–including a member of the House Democratic leadership–told her they didn’t think a woman could beat incumbent Steve Knight (Kitchener Reference Kitchener2019). A few districts over, California Democratic Party delegates told congressional candidate Omar Siddiqui he was “too brown to win” (Fox News 2018). Similarly, in Alabama, a Democratic party official told congressional candidate Adia Winfrey, “You can’t win because you’re Black” (Gontcharova Reference Gontcharova2018). In Georgia, some longtime allies of Stacey Abrams would not support her gubernatorial campaign because “they did not believe a Black woman could win” (Chira Reference Chira2019).

Suneel Gupta encountered similar concerns during his primary campaign in Michigan’s 11th congressional district. Reflecting on his experience, Gupta concluded that there are

two types of biases. One is the type of bias that you face with [a] person directly. We talk about the type of bias that person has towards you. Then there’s another bias that we don’t talk about enough, which is the bias of, “I’m not racist, but my neighbor is racist, right, and therefore I don’t think you would be a strong candidate, not because I wouldn’t vote for you, but because my neighbor would have a tough time voting for you.” And I think that the second is much harder to address, because it’s not talked about enough. And that is ultimately the thing that I think holds a lot of candidates down. (First We Marched Reference Marched and Ran2019)

I call this second type of bias strategic discrimination. Strategic discrimination occurs when an individual discriminates against someone out of concern that others will object to some aspect of that person’s identity. Even individuals who value diversity may consciously or unconsciously engage in strategic discrimination if they believe that other people are biased.

As in strategic voting, individuals engaged in strategic discrimination support candidates for strategic reasons, rather than according to their true preferences. Yet strategic discrimination also involves behaviors other than voting, such as donating to candidates, volunteering, and making endorsements. These actions shape the field early in a primary, determining who appears on the ballot come election day.

Theoretically, strategic discrimination can affect any candidate who is outside the norm due to his or her sexual orientation, class, age, religion, national origin, parental status, or other dimensions of their identity. However, I focus on gender and race because these are especially salient characteristics, and there is a robust literature on racial and gender discrimination in politics.

Canonical works (e.g., Blank, Dabady, and Citro Reference Blank, Dabady and Citro2004, 56-65) commonly delineate four types of discrimination: intentional or explicit discrimination; subtle or unconscious discrimination; statistical discrimination (also known as profiling); and structural or institutional discrimination. Strategic discrimination is fundamentally different from all these forms of discrimination. The first three types involve an individual directly discriminating against another individual (whether consciously or not); the fourth type identifies structures, institutions, and procedures that unfairly disadvantage some groups while privileging others. Strategic discrimination, by contrast, occurs when an individual makes a judgment or takes an action in anticipation of discrimination by other people.

Intriguingly, strategic discrimination has some parallels to customer-driven discrimination in the labor market. Becker (Reference Becker1971) proposed that taste-based discrimination could originate with employers, coworkers, or customers. Becker’s model implies that customer discrimination should be the most difficult for the market to eradicate, and indeed, racial discrimination is most significant in hiring for jobs requiring direct contact with customers (Nunley et al. Reference Nunley, Pugh, Romero and Seals2015), especially when a business’s customers are of a different race than an applicant (Holzer and Ihlanfeldt Reference Holzer and Ihlanfeldt1998). However, customer discrimination is driven by the actual actions of customers. Strategic discrimination, by contrast, is more centrally motivated by beliefs about the inferred biases of other people, whether or not those biases really exist.Footnote 6

Because strategic discrimination in contemporary U.S. politics is based on incorrect beliefs about others’ willingness to vote for diverse candidates, it has strong similarities to the concept of pluralistic ignorance (Weisz Reference Weisz2020). Pluralistic ignorance occurs when individuals privately hold a belief, but they incorrectly assume that others think differently, misperceiving the aggregate norm (Allport Reference Allport1924; Katz and Allport Reference Katz and Allport1931; O’Gorman Reference O’Gorman1986; Miller and Prentice Reference Miller and Prentice1994). For example, individuals may personally oppose racial segregation while erroneously thinking others in their group support it (O’Gorman Reference O’Gorman1975; Fields and Schuman Reference Fields and Schuman1976; O’Gorman and Garry Reference O’Gorman and Garry1976). Such misperceptions can shape individuals’ behavior and perpetuate unpopular norms. Though seldom referenced in political science,Footnote 7 social psychologists have found evidence of pluralistic ignorance in realms as varied as alcohol consumption (Prentice and Miller Reference Prentice and Miller1993), sexual behavior (Lambert, Kahn, and Apple Reference Lambert, Kahn and Apple2003), and use of paternity leave policies (Miyajima and Yamaguchi Reference Miyajima and Yamaguchi2017).

When it comes to attitudes on race and gender, Americans typically over-estimate others’ levels of intolerance (O’Gorman Reference O’Gorman1975; Fields and Schuman Reference Fields and Schuman1976; O’Gorman and Garry Reference O’Gorman and Garry1976; Williams Reference Williams1990; Do et al. Reference Do, Samuels, Adkins, Clinard and Koveleskie2013; Sobotka Reference Sobotka2020). This reflects the “conservative lag” of pluralistic ignorance: even after individuals have changed their beliefs, they may not realize that others have also updated their attitudes (Miller and Prentice Reference Miller and Prentice1994, 543). Pluralistic ignorance can thus act as a “brake on social change” (ibid.), anchoring decision-making in the prejudices of the past.

This dynamic explains why concerns about the electability of women and people of color are so persistent. Even as large majorities of Americans are themselves comfortable with the idea of a female or Black president (Burden, Ono, and Yamada Reference Burden, Ono and Yamada2017; McCarthy Reference McCarthy2019; Gallup 2019), they doubt that others feel the same way (e.g., King, Elbeshbishi, and della Cava Reference King, Elbeshbishi and Cava2019). In Study 1, for example, a national sample of U.S. adults estimates that on average 47% of other Americans would not vote for a woman for president, and 42% of other Americans would not vote for a Black person for president. Though not precise measures of U.S. public opinion, these estimates are notable because they far exceed recorded levels of bias against female and Black presidential candidates, as illustrated in figure 1.Footnote 8 With such a high degree of skepticism about others’ willingness to support diverse candidates, conditions are ripe for strategic discrimination.

Note: Gray bars show yearly population estimates, based on weighted data from the General Social Survey (GSS). Black lines are 95% confidence intervals calculated with design-corrected standard errors. Subjects were asked, “If your party nominated a woman for president, would you vote for her if she were qualified for the job?” and “If your party nominated a [Negro/Black/African-American] for president, would you vote for him if he were qualified for the job?” I code subjects as unwilling to vote for a female or Black candidate if they said anything other than “yes.” (Other responses include “no,” “don’t know,” “wouldn’t vote,” or refused to answer.) Note that the question about a Black presidential candidate assumes the candidate is a man. The GSS has never measured public opinion on a Black woman president.

Figure 1 Perceptions versus reality

Study 1: Strategic Discrimination in the Abstract

In 1971, leading presidential candidate Senator Edmund Muskie was asked whether he would consider selecting a Black running mate, should he be the Democratic nominee. Muskie said he would not, because “in [his] judgment such a ticket was not electable” (quoted in Naughton Reference Naughton1971).

Nearly fifty years later, some commentators argue that electability is still code for “white and male” (e.g., Bacon Reference Bacon2018; Zhou Reference Zhou2019). To evaluate this claim, I designed a survey experiment in the tradition of the Goldberg paradigm (Reference Goldberg1968).Footnote 9 Study 1 investigates whether Americans consider white male candidates more electable than equally qualified female and Black candidates.

Methodology

Study 1 was conducted with a nationally representative sample of 1,947 U.S. adults on May 23–7, 2019. The implementing vendor (Lucid) constructed the sample to match the census on key demographics. While not the same as probabilistic sampling, Lucid samples have been shown to return experimental results that correspond closely to results from random samples (Coppock and McClellan Reference Coppock and McClellan2019).

The experiment was part of a collaborative survey fielded by MIT’s Political Experiments Research Lab (PERL). After answering demographic questions, an attention check question, and questions about political ideology and knowledge, subjects were asked to evaluate a series of three profiles of hypotheticalFootnote 10 gubernatorial candidates.Footnote 11 The profiles appeared in random order, one at a time, on three successive screens. As described in table 1, each profile listed the candidate’s current position, prior offices held, education, profession, age, race [Black/white], and gender [male/female]. Race and gender were randomized so that 25% of the profiles were white female candidates, 25% were white male candidates, 25% were Black female candidates, and 25% were Black male candidates.

Table 1 Candidate profiles for Study 1

Dependent Variables

Below each profile, the subjects were asked, “If this candidate ran for governor in your state, how electable would [he/she] be?” with a 4-point response scale ranging from very electable (4) to very unelectable (1). Based on this question, I construct two dependent variables: an electability score (Electability) and a binary variable indicating whether each candidate profile is considered “very electable” (VeryElectable).

Hypothesis

Study 1 tests a single hypothesis:

H1: White male candidates will be evaluated as more electable than otherwise identical white female, Black female, and Black male candidates.

Results

Table 2 reports the results of Study 1.Footnote 12 On average, when candidate profiles are labeled as Black women, white women, and Black men, they receive lower electability scores than when the same profiles are labeled as white men. This effect is statistically significant for Black female (p<0.001) and white female candidates (p<.05), but not for Black male candidates.

Table 2 Variation in perceived electability by candidate race and gender

All models are OLS. Robust standard errors clustered by respondent are in parentheses.

* = p<0.05, ** = p<0.01, *** = p<0.001

Table 3 Democratic presidential candidates in Study 2

Similarly, as compared to white male candidates, subjects are less likely to consider Black women, white women, and Black men “very electable.” Candidate profiles identified as white men are rated “very electable” 37% of the time. For Black male candidates, this number is 35%; for white women, 32.5%; and for Black women, 30.4%. The differences between white men and white women and white men and Black women are statistically significant (p<0.05 and p<0.001, respectively), but the difference between white men and Black men is not statistically significant (p=.283).

Robustness Checks and Quality Control

The results reported in table 2 are substantively the same if estimated with ordered probit (Electability) or probit (VeryElectable), and they are robust to the inclusion of profile fixed effects (refer to online appendix tables 1.1-1.3). Dropping subjects who failed an attention-check question increases the magnitude and significance of the results, and the difference in electability scores for Black male candidates becomes statistically significant (p<0.05; online appendix table 1.4). Similarly, the results of Study 1 are not driven by politically disengaged respondents who would be unlikely to participate in a primary election (online appendix tables 1.12-1.13). To the contrary, subjects with higher levels of political knowledge tend to show stronger responses to the experimental manipulation (online appendix tables 1.5-1.10).

Table 4 Average treatment effects, male voters treatment

Strategic Discrimination and Direct Discrimination as Possible Mechanisms

Theoretically, subjects may be rating white male candidates as more electable than other types of candidates due to both the subjects’ own biases (direct discrimination) and their estimates of others’ biases (strategic discrimination). It is difficult to adjudicate between these two mechanisms.Footnote 13 Direct discrimination probably plays some role in influencing how subjects rate candidates’ electability. Yet at the same time sub-group analysis suggests that direct discrimination cannot fully explain the results of Study 1.Footnote 14

In the United States, sexism and racism are strongly correlated with older age and lower educational attainment (Heerwig and McCabe Reference Heerwig and McCabe2009; Parker, Graf, and Igielnik Reference Parker, Graf and Igielnik2019). However, the results of Study 1 do not show any clear generational patterns (online appendix tables 1.16-1.17), and the effects of Study 1 are largest among the most educated subjects (online appendix tables 1.14-1.15). These sub-group results are puzzling and inconsistent with the idea that direct discrimination is the only mechanism at work in Study I.

So is strategic discrimination driving the results of Study 1? Perhaps. In addition to completing the candidate evaluation exercise, Study 1 asked subjects to estimate the percentage of other Americans who would not vote for a woman for president and the percentage who would not vote for a Black person for president. Among subjects who over-estimate others’ biases, Study 1’s main findings have greater magnitude and statistical significance (online appendix tables 1.19-1.29), with the results for Black male candidates reaching conventional levels of statistical significance (online appendix tables 1.24-1.29). By contrast, among subjects who have accurate or low estimates of others’ levels of bias, Study 1 generally produces null effects (online appendix tables 1.19-29). In some model specifications, subjects with accurate or low estimates of others’ racism actually rate Black men as significantly more electable than white men (online appendix tables 1.24 and 1.27).

Though not a smoking gun, these patterns are consistent with the notion that concern about others’ biases could be causing individuals to doubt the electability of diverse candidates. But are subjects’ estimates of others’ levels of racism and sexism simply a reflection of their own beliefs? Research on pluralistic ignorance finds that individuals’ estimates of others’ views are shaped by two biases: “looking glass bias” and “conservative bias” (Fields and Schuman Reference Fields and Schuman1976). It is true that individuals project their own views onto others. Yet at the same time they also tend to assume that others’ beliefs are more conservative than they really are. Taken in combination, these two biases typically produce a weak positive correlation between subjects’ own beliefs and their estimates of others’ beliefs, as in Mildenberger and Tingley (Reference Mildenberger and Tingley2019) and Sobotka (Reference Sobotka2020).Footnote 15 In studies of racism and sexism, even highly tolerant subjects have been shown to over-estimate others’ levels of intolerance (Fields and Schuman Reference Fields and Schuman1976; O’Gorman Reference O’Gorman1975; O’Gorman and Garry Reference O’Gorman and Garry1976; Do et al. Reference Do, Samuels, Adkins, Clinard and Koveleskie2013; Sobotka Reference Sobotka2020). This may explain why in Study 1, subjects’ estimates of others’ levels of bias are not correlated with known predictors of racism and sexism (online appendix table 1.33).

Partisan Cues as an Alternative Mechanism?

Do subjects consider female and Black candidates less electable because of their racial and gender identities, or because race and gender are cues for partisanship? To evaluate this possibility, I analyzed Study 1 for two sub-groups: subjects in states with Democratic governors, and subjects in states with GOP governors. For white female and Black female candidates, the results are largely consistent across the two sub-groups. Black male candidates, however, are rated less electable only by subjects whose states have GOP governors (online appendix table 1.18). This suggests that inferred partisanship could be driving Study 1’s limited findings regarding Black male candidates. By contrast, Black and white female gubernatorial candidates are seen as less electable even among subjects from Democratic-leaning states.

Discussion and Context

Study 1 finds that perceptions of electability vary according to candidates’ racial-gender identities. The perceived electability gap is especially severe for Black women. Compared to an identical white man, a hypothetical Black female gubernatorial candidate is about 20% less likely to be rated “very electable.” The numbers are even worse when considering only responses from the types of people most likely to participate in candidate selection; subjects who are attentive, politically knowledgeable, and ideological rate Black female candidates “very electable” 27.5% of the time, as compared to 37.7% for white male candidates. Yet with the notable exception of Philpot and Walton (Reference Philpot and Walton2007), Black female candidates are largely ignored in studies of public opinion toward candidates.Footnote 16 The results of Study 1 cry out for greater attention to intersectionality in future work in this field.

Sub-group analysis suggests that in addition to direct discrimination, strategic discrimination is a plausible mechanism for the results of Study 1. However, Study 1 is based on evaluations of hypothetical candidate profiles in an artificial, abstract context. In actual elections, people form opinions about candidates based on many different factors. The next experiment assesses whether and how strategic discrimination can influence the perceived competitiveness of real-world candidates.

Study 2: Strategic Discrimination in the 2020 Democratic Presidential Primary

In the 2020 Democratic presidential primary, electability was a top concern for voters (Quinnipiac 2019)—and the concept was often linked to race and gender. For example, some activists worried that “after the experience of 2016” their party “might need to flee to the safety of a white, male candidate” (Weigel Reference Weigel2019).

Yet even as they referenced candidates’ racial-gender identities, debates about electability also invoked candidates’ policy positions and qualifications. Consider this statement from South Carolina State Senator Dick Harpootlian, a prominent supporter of former vice-president Joe Biden:

This is do-or-die, and Joe Biden is the best candidate to go against Trump in November. Would Joe Biden be running if he thought any of these other folks could beat Donald Trump? No way. We can’t risk this thing with someone who has not done this before, who is unchallenged, who is untested. There is something to be said for two old white guys going at it. The African Americans in the State Senate with me are going to be with him overwhelmingly. Because this is a pragmatic year. This isn’t a battle of ideologies or identity or Medicare for All or Green New Whatever. It’s all about who can stop this juvenile narcissist from getting a second term. (quoted in Hamby Reference Hamby2019)

Harpootlian weaves together multiple arguments, ranging from Biden’s experience to the apparent desirability of seeing “two old white guys going at it.” How can we disentangle these factors?

To deal with this challenge, I conducted a survey experiment that exposes some subjects to priming messages designed to cue the strategic importance of white or male voters. If as compared to the control group, the subjects exposed to these treatments consider Black and female candidates less competitive, that would show how strategic concerns about race and gender can play a role in shaping assessments of real-world candidates’ competitiveness.Footnote 17 To clarify, Study 2 does not measure actual levels of bias present in the 2020 Democratic primary,Footnote 18 nor is it a study of voting behavior.Footnote 19 Rather, this experiment seeks to evaluate whether a candidate’s race and gender can influence perceptions of their competitiveness, even in the noisy, multi-dimensional context of an ongoing election.

Methodology

Study 2 was fielded on MTurk from May 6–11, 2019. High-quality MTurk workers who live in the United States were eligible to participate. Out of 3,386 people who took the initial screening questions, 1,702 subjects met the criteria for inclusion: they stated that they voted in the 2016 presidential election, they did not vote for Donald Trump, and they do not support Donald Trump’s reelection in 2020.

The subjects who completed the survey experiment are evenly divided between women and men. In 2016, the Democratic primary electorate was 58% female (Brownstein Reference Brownstein2019a), so women are under-represented in Study 2. The subjects are also younger (modal age range 25–34 years) and less racially diverse (70% white) than Democratic primary voters, who were 62% white in 2016 (Brownstein Reference Brownstein2019a). Online appendix table 1.34 contains a full demographic profile of the subjects.

Control and Treatment Groups

The subjects who were screened into the full survey were randomly divided into four equal groups. All subjects were told that a large number of Democrats are competing to run against Donald Trump in 2020. Then they saw the names, titles, and photos of the top eight Democratic presidential contenders, based on current polls at the time of the experiment. The candidates appeared one at a time in random order.

After viewing the candidates, the control group proceeded directly to a screen where they were asked which candidates had the best chance of beating Donald Trump in 2020. They were given a randomly ordered list of the eight candidates, and they were asked to drag their top three candidates into a box on the screen. The instructions specified that the candidate in the #1 position should be the person with the best chance of beating Trump, the candidate in the #2 position should have the second-best chance, and the candidate in the #3 position should have the third-best chance. After this exercise, the control group proceeded to a concluding module with demographic questions.

Before doing the ranking exercise, the subjects randomized into the “Male Voters” treatment group read a priming message emphasizing the strategic importance of winning male voters in 2020. Another treatment group (“White Voters”) read a priming message emphasizing the strategic importance of winning white voters in 2020. Both messages were condensed from actual narratives circulating in late 2018 and early 2019 (e.g., Hohman Reference Hohman2018; Brownstein Reference Brownstein2019b; Riccardi Reference Riccardi2019). The full text of the messages is in online appendix table 1.36.

The third treatment group (“Estimate Bias”) was informed that to beat Donald Trump in 2020, the Democratic presidential nominee needed to be able to win key swing states. These subjects were then asked to estimate the percentage of swing-state voters who would not vote for a woman for president and the percentage who would not vote for a Black person for president. As in Study 1, most respondents overestimated others’ biases. On average, they estimated that 38.5% of swing state-voters would not vote for a woman for president, and 37.4% would not vote for a Black candidate.

Dependent Variables

The main dependent variables are binary measures of whether each subject’s list of the top three candidates with the best chances of beating Trump includes at least one woman (IncludeWoman) or at least one Black candidate (IncludeBlack). Because there are multiple ways of interpreting the ranking exercise, I also code four additional dependent variables. Two are binary measures of whether a female (TopWoman) or Black (TopBlack) candidate occupies the #1 position in a subject’s list. The others are the total number of Black (TotalBlack) and female (TotalWomen) candidates included in a subject’s list of the top three most competitive candidates.

In some extensions of the analysis, I also code dependent variables that measure outcomes for specific candidates, including binary measures of whether each candidate was included among the top three most competitive candidates and whether each candidate occupied the top position.

Hypotheses

Study 2 tests three hypotheses:

H2: When subjects are told that winning the support of male voters is key to victory in 2020, they will evaluate female candidates as being less capable of beating Trump.

H3: When subjects are told that winning the support of white voters is key to victory in 2020, they will evaluate Black candidates as being less capable of beating Trump.

H4: When subjects are asked to estimate the percentages of swing state voters who will not vote for female and Black presidential candidates, they will evaluate female and Black candidates as being less capable of beating Trump.

Results—Strategic Messaging Treatments

All results are average treatment effects (ATEs). Each ATE is the difference in the means of the control group and a treatment group, estimated using Welch’s t-test.

Male Voters Treatment

When subjects are told that winning male votes is the path to victory in 2020, they are less likely to say female candidates are well-positioned to beat Donald Trump. In the control group, 70.5% of subjects include at least one woman in their list of the top three most competitive candidates, compared to 56.4% in the male voters treatment group. This effect is statistically significant (p<0.001). Similarly, subjects in the male voters treatment group include fewer women in their top three list, and they are less likely to list a female candidate as having the best chance of beating Trump (7.7% versus 15.6% in the control group, p<0.001).

White Voters Treatment

In the control group, 49% of subjects include at least one Black candidate in their list of the top three most competitive candidates. Among subjects told that white voters are the key to beating Trump, 41% do so (p<0.05). Subjects in the white voters treatment group are also less likely to say that a Black candidate has the best chance of beating Trump (4% versus 9.2%, p<0.01), and they include fewer Black candidates in their top three lists (p<0.05).

Candidate-Specific Results

Moving beyond the main results of Study 2, figures 2 and 3 show the average treatment effects by candidate. Each arrow shows the differences between the control group and the treatment group. Black arrows have p-values < 0.1; gray arrows are statistically insignificant.

Figure 2 Average treatment effects by candidate, male voters treatment

Figure 3 Average treatment effects by candidate, white voters treatment

Table 5 Average treatment effects, white voters treatment

Compared to the control group, the male voters treatment group is markedly less optimistic about Elizabeth Warren’s and Kamala Harris’s chances of beating Donald Trump.Footnote 20 In the control group, 7.5% of subjects say Harris has the best chance of beating Trump, compared with 3.5% in the male voters treatment group (p<0.05). Warren experiences a similar decline from 7.1% to 3.3% (p<0.05). Both Warren and Harris also see their chances of being considered among the top three most competitive candidates decrease by about ten percentage points.

Highlighting the importance of intersectionality, Kamala Harris is penalized again by the message about the strategic importance of white voters. As illustrated in figure 3, Harris’s probability of being rated most competitive falls from 7.5% in the control group to 2.6% in the white voters treatment group (p<0.001).Footnote 21

On average, white candidates benefit from the white voters treatment, and male candidates benefit from the male voters treatment. But intriguingly, figures 2 and 3 show that these increases in perceived competitiveness are not distributed evenly across all male and white candidates. This unexpected result may be due to the specific dynamics of the 2020 Democratic presidential primary, or it could reflect a broader pattern of some kind. Future researchers may want to explore the question of who benefits most from strategic discrimination, and under what circumstances.

Results—Estimate Bias Treatment

Before they rated the candidates’ competitiveness, a third treatment group was asked to estimate the percentage of swing-state voters who would not vote for a woman for president, and the percentage of swing-state voters who would not vote for a Black person for president. As reported in table 6, the effects of this treatment are statistically insignificant—though the negative effects for TotalBlack and IncludeBlack are close to conventional levels of statistical significance (p=0.116 and p=0.132, respectively).

Table 6 Average treatment effects, estimate others’ biases treatment

These results may be statistically insignificant because subjects responded to the treatment heterogeneously. Most subjects over-estimate others’ biases, while about one-quarter of subjects have accurate or low perceptions of others’ racism and sexism. Compared to the subjects who have low estimates, subjects who over-estimate others’ biases are more likely to construct all-male or all-white lists of candidates best able to beat Trump, and on average they include fewer Black and female candidates. These correlations are consistent with the theory of strategic discrimination, though it is important to note that they are correlations, not evidence of a causal effect.Footnote 22

Discussion and Context

Study 2 is best understood as a proof-of-concept experiment.Footnote 23 The results show that under certain circumstances, subjects can be induced to consider primary candidates’ racial-gender identities as they decide who would be most competitive in a general election. Study 2 also suggests that media coverage and analysis from pundits may affect the perceived competitiveness of candidates of different races and genders.

That said, Study 2 has some limitations. In particular, readers should be cautious about generalizing too broadly from these results. Study 2 was conducted at a unique moment in history, in the aftermath of Hillary Clinton’s 2016 loss to Donald Trump and within recent memory of the Obama presidency. Furthermore, Study 2 was conducted with a specific set of candidates. Pre-existing beliefs about those candidates likely interacted with the experimental treatments. There is no way to know if the same results would have been obtained had a different mix of candidates decided to seek the 2020 Democratic presidential nomination.

Study 3: Combatting Strategic Discrimination

When candidates encounter strategic discrimination, how should they respond? Early in 1996, this question was front of mind for former Charlotte mayor Harvey Gantt, Jr., who is Black. Gantt was embroiled in a tough Democratic primary for U.S. Senate, competing against white pharmaceutical executive Charlie Sanders.

Sanders ran on the slogan “the one Democrat who can beat Jesse Helms” (Germond Reference Germond1996), and he “made electability the primary rationale for his campaign” (Sack Reference Sack1996). Electability was widely understood as “subtle code for race” (ibid.)—“the idea that a Black candidate could not defeat Helms” (Ahearn and Alexander Reference Ahearn and Alexander1996). Even among Black voters, “there [was] a strong feeling that white North Carolinians [would] not let a Black man beat somebody like Jesse Helms” (Sack Reference Sack1996). As one pastor said, “Harvey can’t beat Jesse [Helms]. No Black can. It’s sad. This is a great country, but it’s not perfect” (quoted in Germond Reference Germond1996).

Gantt responded to these doubts by acting “firmly to bring the racial issue into the open so he [could] combat it on his own terms” (Sack Reference Sack1996). As he told one majority-Black audience, “I think it’s wrong for anybody, four years from the 21st century, whether from my opponent or on their own, to suggest that we can’t win because of the pigmentation of our skin. That is a corrosive and damaging argument” (quoted in Sack Reference Sack1996).

Gantt ultimately prevailed in his primary, so this approach appears to have worked for him. Should other candidates facing strategic discrimination deploy similar moral arguments? Or might other responses work better?

To evaluate strategies for combatting strategic discrimination, I designed a follow-up experiment (Study 3) based on Study 2.

Methodology

The structure of Study 3 is the same as Study 2, except instead of treatments designed to induce strategic discrimination, Study 3 evaluates four treatments intended to mitigate strategic discrimination. Study 3 was fielded on MTurk from May 28–June 2, 2019. MTurk workers who had already participated in Study 2 were ineligible for Study 3; 4,561 subjects took the screening questions for Study 3, and 2,219 completed the full experiment. Full subject demographics are reported in online appendix table 1.35.

Dependent Variables and Control and Treatment Groups

The dependent variables for Study 3 are identical to those in Study 2, and Study 3 includes the same candidates. As in Study 2, the control group subjects proceeded directly to ranking the top three Democratic presidential candidates with the best chances of beating Donald Trump in 2020.

Before evaluating the Democratic presidential candidates, the first treatment group (“Correct Information”) was told that levels of bias against female and Black candidates are at historically low levels, and the vast majority of Americans are willing to vote for a female or Black president.

The second treatment group (“Naming and Shaming”) was told that some Democrats think they need to nominate a white man to be able to win in 2020. They were told that this type of thinking is called strategic discrimination, and it unfairly advantages white male candidates. They were also told that even people who value diversity can unintentionally engage in strategic discrimination.

The third treatment group (“Role Model”) was told that to win in 2020, Democrats should consider what worked for their party in 2018. They were then provided with a short vignette about Representative Lauren Underwood, a Black woman who beat a white male GOP incumbent in a majority white district that voted for Trump in 2016. The vignette did not explicitly mention Underwood’s race, but it was accompanied by her official portrait.

The fourth treatment group (“Black Voters”) saw a message emphasizing the strategic importance of Black voters. The text closely paralleled the messages about white and male voters used in Study 2. The full text of all these treatments can be found in online appendix table 1.37.

Hypotheses

Study 3 tests four hypotheses:

H5: When subjects are informed of the true low levels of bias facing female and Black candidates, they will evaluate female and Black candidates as being more capable of beating Trump.

H6: When subjects are informed that strategic discrimination advantages white men and unfairly harms female and Black candidates, they will evaluate female and Black candidates as being more capable of beating Trump.

H7: When subjects are primed with a vignette about a successful female African American congressional candidate, they will evaluate female and Black candidates as being more capable of beating Trump.

H8: When subjects are told that high Black turnout is the key to beating Trump, they will evaluate Black candidates as being more capable of beating Trump.

Results

All results reported in tables 7–10 are average treatment effects (ATEs) estimated using Welch’s t-test. I find support for H7 and H8, but not H5 or H6.

Table 7 Average treatment effects, correct information treatment

Table 8 Average treatment effects, naming and shaming treatment

Table 9 Average treatment effects, role model treatment

Table 10 Average treatment effects, Black voters treatment

Correct Information Treatment

For the correct information treatment, we cannot reject the null hypothesis of no effect. Contrary to Dowling and Miller (Reference Dowling and Miller2015), I find no evidence that facts change subjects’ beliefs about the competitiveness of female or Black candidates. Instead, my findings are consistent with a broader literature suggesting that when it comes to politics, misperceptions are sticky (Nyhan and Reifler Reference Nyhan and Reifler2010; Berinksy Reference Berinksy2017).

Naming and Shaming Treatment

The results of the naming and shaming treatment are also statistically insignificant. Even when subjects are explicitly told that strategic discrimination is a problem that unfairly disadvantages female and Black candidates, they do not meaningfully increase their assessments of female and Black candidates’ competitiveness against Donald Trump. This null effect suggests that merely calling out strategic discrimination is not a promising strategy for combatting it.

Role Model Treatment

When subjects are primed with the vignette about Representative Underwood, they rate Black and female presidential candidates as significantly more competitive against Donald Trump. Subjects in the role model treatment group include more female and Black candidates in their top three lists. They are more likely to put a female candidate in their #1 position (21.7% versus 12.8% in the control group; p<0.001), and they are more likely to say that a Black candidate has the best chance of beating Donald Trump (p<0.001).

These results are largely driven by subjects’ perceptions of Kamala Harris—7.8% of the subjects in the role model treatment group list Kamala Harris as having the best chance of beating Trump (versus 2% in the control group; p<0.001). Similarly, 39.7% of the treatment group includes Harris in their top three lists, as compared to 27.9% of the control group (p<0.001).

Black Voters Treatment

When subjects are told that Black voters are the key to victory in 2020, they rate Black candidates as more competitive against Donald Trump. As compared to the control group, subjects in the Black voters treatment group are more likely to list a Black candidate as having the best the chance of beating Trump in 2020 (4.9% versus 15.9%; p<0.001). They are about fourteen percentage points more likely to include at least one Black candidate in their list of the top three most competitive candidates (p<0.001), and on average they include more Black candidates on their lists (p<0.001).

Both Kamala Harris and Cory Booker benefit significantly from this treatment. As compared to the control group, Harris’s chances of being rated most competitive against Trump increase from 2% to 8.1% (p<0.001), while Booker’s chances increase from 2.9% to 7.8% (p=0.01). Similarly, both candidates see large jumps in their chances of being included among subjects’ top three most competitive candidates, from 27.9% to 42.1% for Harris (p<0.001) and from 18% to 26.8% for Booker (p<0.01).

Discussion and Context

Study 3 suggests that for candidates trying to overcome strategic discrimination, it is most productive to make the case that fielding diverse candidates advances the goal of winning elections. By contrast, messages that call out strategic discrimination and attempt to correct subjects’ misperceptions about others’ biases have no statistically significant effect. However, it is important to note that Study 3 used written priming messages, rather than videos or interactive exercises that might be more compelling. A different strategy for communicating these messages could yield different results.

Additionally, in real elections, candidates seeking to overcome strategic discrimination often use a strategy that was not possible to evaluate in Study 3: they out-perform the competition, proving viability by shattering fundraising records, winning debates, and notching up victories in straw polls, caucuses, and primaries. To be clear, out-performing the competition is an imperfect, individual-level approach to deal with strategic discrimination, not a means of solving the broader problem. It is neither reasonable nor equitable to say that if women and people of color want to be taken seriously as candidates, they must be exceptional. Put simply, not everyone can be Barack Obama.

Nonetheless, it is worth learning from Obama’s path to the White House. In 2007 and 2008, many people—including African AmericansFootnote 24—were skeptical of Obama’s candidacy. They wondered, “Is America ready to elect a Black president?” (e.g., Crowley and Johnson Reference Crowley and Johnson2007; 60 Minutes 2008, min 4:40 and 6:48), and they worried that the answer might be “no.” To quote one young Black voter in South Carolina, “Personally, I don’t think he has a chance in hell. All those white people? Come on!” (quoted in Helman Reference Helman2007).

Obama eventually overcame these concerns by showing he could win over the very voters expected to be most biased against him. The Obama campaign deployed white surrogates (Zengerle Reference Zengerle2008), put “diverse but mostly white faces” on the risers at campaign events (ibid.), and produced campaign videos that intentionally featured footage of white audiences applauding enthusiastically (Zeleny Reference Zeleny2008).Footnote 25 Finally, Obama gained crucial momentum when he won the Iowa caucuses, proving that yes, a Black man could win even in the whitest corners of America.

Conclusion

Strategic discrimination is a subtle yet consequential form of discrimination in politics. All else being equal, Americans see hypothetical white male candidates as more electable than Black women, white women, and to a lesser extent, Black men. Real-world candidates’ racial-gender identities can also affect their perceived competitiveness. These dynamics are strongly intersectional. While problematic for white women and Black men, my experiments show that strategic discrimination poses particularly steep challenges for Black women. Though somewhat limited in their generalizability, these initial findings should mark strategic discrimination as an important phenomenon worthy of further study.

But why is strategic discrimination so salient at this particular moment in U.S. history? The answer may lie in three parallel trends: increasing diversity among candidates, increasing awareness of racism and sexism in society, and increasing political polarization.

First, a historic surge of women and people of color is flooding into politics, particularly on the Democratic side. Their presence may be prompting more active consideration of questions that were purely theoretical in the past. Without many Black candidates running in majority-white districts, and without many women running, period, there was little reason to contemplate whether diverse candidates were electable. Now such concerns are more immediate and tangible.

Second, from Black Lives Matter to the 2016 election to #MeToo to the Women’s March to “shithole countries” to Charlottesville to the Kavanaugh hearings, issues of race and gender are front and center in America’s national conversation. The percentages of Americans naming racism and sexism “very big” national problems have increased markedly in recent years, especially since 2016 (Neal Reference Neal2017; Hartig and Doherty Reference Hartig and Doherty2018). These changes in public opinion are generally framed as good for diversity, but strategic discrimination could be an unexpected side effect. If Americans are increasingly concerned about the prevalence and severity of racism and sexism, they may worry that sexism and racism will keep female and nonwhite candidates from winning general elections.

Finally, political polarization may fuel strategic discrimination. Hayes and Lawless (Reference Hayes and Lawless2016, 7) contend that polarization has “significantly leveled the playing field” for female candidates—and when it comes to general elections, they are right. Under conditions of extreme polarization, general election votes are cast largely according to party affiliation, with little room for a candidate’s identity to matter. But at the same time, as politics devolves into partisan warfare, each side becomes ever more desperate to “just win, baby!”Footnote 26 As a result, primaries may hinge more and more on electability, which is a raced and gendered concept.Footnote 27 Even if women and people of color objectively win their elections at the same rates as white men, they are perceived as less electable. So donors, party activists, and primary voters may gravitate toward white male candidates who feel like a safe bet, rather than taking a risk on a woman or a person of color. That’s strategic discrimination in action.

Supplementary Materials

To view supplementary material for this article, please visit http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S153759272000242X.

The online appendix includes additional tables and information about the experiments.

Footnotes

A list of permanent links to Supplemental Materials provided by the author precedes the References section.

*

Data replication sets are available in Harvard Dataverse at: https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/6FFKRI

This research was supported by the MIT Political Science Department; the MIT Political Experiments Research Lab, and the 2019 Carrie Chapman Catt Prize for Research on Women and Politics (Honorable Mention). Blair Read provided superb research assistance, with logistical help from Paula Kreutzer and Z. Y. Chris Peng. Adam Berinsky, Pavielle Haines, Danny Hidalgo, Rich Nielsen, Spencer Piston, Jamil Scott, Tagart Sobotka, Erin Tolley, Srdjan Vucetic, and Erika Weisz contributed valuable feedback, as did audiences at APSA 2019, the University of Toronto Political Science Department, the Public Law Centre at the University of Ottawa, and six anonymous reviewers. For moral support and encouragement, the author would like to thank Taylor Boas, Adam Bonica, Christine Cheng, Dara Kay Cohen, Amelia Hoover Green, Vivek Krishnamurthy, Eduardo Moncada, Sarah Parkinson, Maia Pelleg, Agustin Rayo, Julia Sweeney, and Michael Weintraub.

1 Gender bias and stereotypes shape candidates’ experiences and affect the way voters perceive and evaluate candidates, e.g., Huddy and Terkildsen Reference Huddy and Terkildsen1993; Streb et al. Reference Streb, Burrell, Frederick and Genovese2008; Burden, Ono, and Yamada Reference Burden, Ono and Yamada2017; Ditonto Reference Ditonto2019; Glick Reference Glick2019. Nonetheless, women do not systematically perform worse in U.S. elections, perhaps because the women who run are more qualified than their male counterparts; Pearson and McGhee Reference Pearson and McGhee2013. Some recent research even suggests that all else being equal, voters may prefer female candidates; Schwarz, Hunt, and Coppock Reference Schwarz, Hunt and Coppock2018; Teele, Kalla, and Rosenbluth Reference Teele, Kalla and Rosenbluth2018.

2 This is a change from decades past, when studies typically found more significant evidence of racial bias by U.S. voters, e.g., Sigelman and Welch Reference Sigelman and Welch1984; Terkildsen Reference Terkildsen1993.

3 For women of color, the process of becoming a candidate is intersectional, e.g., Holman and Schneider Reference Holman and Schneider2018; Shah, Scott, and Juenke Reference Shah, Scott and Juenke2019. Yet as Simien Reference Simien2007 points out, political science research on race and gender is largely bifurcated into two unconnected literatures: one on race, and one on gender; see also Hancock Reference Hancock2007. This is problematic because minority women candidates’ motivations, perspectives, and experiences are simultaneously shaped by both race and gender, making them distinct from white women and nonwhite men; Philpot and Walton Reference Philpot and Walton2007; Frederick Reference Frederick2013; Bejarano Reference Bejarano2013; Holman and Schneider Reference Holman and Schneider2018; Brown and Gershon Reference Brown and Gershon2017; and Silva and Skulley Reference Silva and Skulley2019.

4 Identity-based harassment of candidates ranges from racial slurs; e.g., Itkowitz Reference Itkowitz2019, to sexualized comments and inappropriate touching, e.g., Graham Reference Graham2018; Cotton Reference Cotton2020. See also Krook and Restrepo Sanín Reference Krook and Sanín2019 and Rheault, Rayment, and Musulan Reference Rheault, Rayment and Musulan2019.

5 As Shah, Scott, and Juenke observe, “the pipeline to candidacy is biased by both race and gender before voters are allowed to make their choices”; Reference Shah, Scott and Juenke2019, 432. Other political institutions are similarly raced and gendered; on Congress, see Hawkesworth Reference Hawkesworth2003. On feminist institutionalism more generally, see Krook and Mackay Reference Krook and Mackay2011 and Mackay, Kenny, and Chappell Reference Mackay, Kenny and Chappell2011.

6 Holzer and Ihlanfeldt measure employers’ perceptions of customers’ biases, not customers’ actual biases—which the authors characterize as a flaw in their research design; Reference Holzer and Ihlanfeldt1998, 863. The study is framed as being about actual discrimination by customers, not employers’ potentially erroneous perceptions of customers’ attitudes.

7 Exceptions include Todorov and Mandisodza Reference Todorov and Mandisodza2004 and Mildenberger and Tingley Reference Mildenberger and Tingley2019.

8 Figure 1 is based on data from the General Social Survey; Smith, Hout, and Marsden Reference Smith, Hout and Marsden2017. Although social desirability bias could be coloring the GSS data, list experiments also produce estimates well below the average estimates of the subjects in Study 1. For example, using a list experiment, Burden, Ono, and Yamada Reference Burden, Ono and Yamada2017 estimate 13% of Americans would not vote for a woman for president. In an older list experiment, Streb et al. Reference Streb, Burrell, Frederick and Genovese2008 estimate 26% of Americans would be angry or upset about a female president.

9 The Goldberg paradigm is a simple yet compelling experimental design frequently used to test for discrimination (e.g., Bertrand and Mullainathan Reference Bertrand and Mullainathan2004). Subjects rate profiles, resumes, or other materials that are identical but for the identities assigned to the authors. If ratings vary across randomly assigned identities, that is evidence of discrimination.

10 Although they can feel artificial, hypothetical candidate experiments are a powerful tool for isolating the causal effects of candidates’ identities, as in Teele, Kalla, and Rosenbluth Reference Teele, Kalla and Rosenbluth2018 and Doherty, Dowling, and Miller Reference Doherty, Dowling and Miller2019. Researchers who use hypothetical candidate profile experiments consciously choose “to trade a decrease in verisimilitude for an increase in our ability to directly manipulate the information environment”; Kirkland and Coppock Reference Kirkland and Coppock2018, 574.

11 I use hypothetical gubernatorial candidates because discussing race and gender at the presidential level invariably invokes comparisons to Hillary Clinton and Barack Obama, which is not ideal for an abstract experiment. I considered using hypothetical congressional candidates, but House races vary considerably. Some districts are majority-minority, while other seats have been held by the same incumbent for decades. By contrast, gubernatorial races are reasonably similar across the country: both major parties consistently run candidates, there are no multi-decade incumbents, and state boundaries cannot be gerrymandered. Additionally, gubernatorial candidates are seeking executive office, so they are somewhat comparable to the presidential candidates in Studies 2 and 3. That said, white women, women of color, and men of color run for governor more often than they seek the presidency, so subjects may be more comfortable with diverse gubernatorial candidates, as compared to presidential candidates.

12 Because each subject analyzed three profiles, the N is over 5,700.

13 Unfortunately, I do not have a measure of subjects’ own levels of sexism and racism. More research is needed to fully understand the relationship between individuals’ own biases and their views of candidates’ electability.

14 Additionally, the risk of experimenter demand effect is low; Mummolo and Peterson Reference Mummolo and Peterson2019. Even if subjects deduced that this was an experiment about race and gender, social desirability bias would presumably cause them to rate female and Black candidates favorably—which would run contrary to the results reported here

15 Sobotka Reference Sobotka2020 asked male subjects to complete the Modern Sexism Scale for themselves, and for “most men.” Subjects’ own scores are not strongly correlated with their estimates of others’ scores; personal communication from Tagart Cain Sobotka, March 3, Reference Sobotka2020.

16 I am unable to find any national surveys that have ever asked, “Would you vote for a Black woman for president?” or any variants on that question. Black women candidates are similarly missing from the experimental political science literature, e.g., Streb. et al. Reference Streb, Burrell, Frederick and Genovese2008; Heerwig and McCabe Reference Heerwig and McCabe2009; Teele, Kalla, and Rosenbluth Reference Teele, Kalla and Rosenbluth2018; Doherty, Dowling, and Miller Reference Doherty, Dowling and Miller2019. This oversight is unfortunate given the ease of incorporating intersectionality into research designs using hypothetical candidate profiles.

17 Though this experiment is somewhat oblique, I designed it this way because I cannot randomize real candidates’ racial-gender identities. Nor can I randomize subjects’ underlying beliefs, which are endogenously determined. The best I can do is to use priming to randomize the salience of strategic thinking about race and gender.

18 As Mutz notes, experiments “cannot tell us how many people are likely to be exposed to a given treatment in the real world … . Experiments estimate effects given exposure; nothing more and nothing less”; Reference Mutz2011, 151.

19 Despite some initial work by Simas Reference Simas2017, it remains largely unknown to what degree electability ultimately influences vote choice in a primary.

20 Effects for Amy Klobuchar are negative but statistically insignificant because in the control group, so few subjects rated her as competitive.

21 The white voters treatment effect for Cory Booker is negative but small and not statistically significant because few members of the control group perceive Booker as competitive.

22 It would be inadvisable to compare only the over-estimators in this treatment group with the control group, because the control group includes both subjects who (if asked) would have had low estimates of others’ sexism and racism, and subjects who (if asked) would have had high estimates of others’ sexism and racism.

23 As Deaton and Cartwright explain, when we have “no theory, or very weak theory,” experimental results can show proof of concept by “demonstrating causality in some population,” showing that “the treatment is capable of working somewhere”; Reference Deaton and Cartwright2018, 13. Although proof of concept experiments typically do not provide broad, generalizable results, they play an important role in theory development; Lieberman Reference Lieberman2016.

24 Obama addressed these doubts at an NAACP dinner in Sumter, SC, in November 2007: “I’ve heard that some folks in the barber shops, beauty shops—you know better than I—say to themselves, ‘I like Obama, but I’m just not sure America’s ready. I’m not sure other folks are ready. I’m not sure he can win.’ Don’t go around telling me I can’t do something! Because if you’re telling me I can’t do something, that means you’re telling your child they can’t do something. That means you’re telling yourself you can’t do something. I don’t believe that I can’t”; quoted in Helman Reference Helman2007.

25 Interestingly, these videos were intended to win over African Americans. Per David Axelrod, “The greatest barrier to breaking through in a big way was the skepticism among African-American voters that white voters would embrace a Black candidate”; Zeleny Reference Zeleny2008. Strategist David Binder similarly remembers that “the biggest problem we had with African Americans would be that they didn’t think he could ever win. That all changed with Iowa. The Iowa results proved to many African Americans that Obama had broader-based appeal and was not just someone who was going to be a token African American candidate”; Ambinder Reference Ambinder2009.

26 Quoting football coach Al Davis, Nancy Pelosi exhorted 2018 Democratic House candidates to “just win, baby!” Pelosi urged them to do whatever they deemed necessary to win their districts—including opposing her as Speaker of the House; Gambino Reference Gambino2018.

27 Hayes and Lawless note that even as polarization reduces the importance of gender in general elections, gender may continue to matter in primaries and nonpartisan elections; Reference Hayes and Lawless2016, 134.

References

60 Minutes . 2008. “The Long-Shot Candidate,” CBS, December 28. (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=F8MxP9adPO8).Google Scholar
Abrajano, Marisa A., and Alvarez, R. Michael. 2005. “A Natural Experiment of Race-Based and Issue Voting: The 2001 City of Los Angeles Elections.” Political Research Quarterly 58(2): 203-18.10.1177/106591290505800202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahearn, Lorraine, and Alexander, Lex. 1996. “Rematch: It’s Gantt vs. Helms.” Greensboro [NC} News & Record, May 7.Google Scholar
Allport, Floyd Henry. 1924. Social Psychology. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.Google Scholar
Ambinder, Marc. 2009. “Race Over?” Atlantic Monthly, January/February 2009. (https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2009/01/race-over/307215/).Google Scholar
Anastasopoulos, Lefteris. 2016. “Estimating the Gender Penalty in House of Representatives Elections Using a Regression Discontinuity Design.” Electoral Studies 43:150-57.10.1016/j.electstud.2016.04.008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bacon, Perry. 2018. “The Problem with ‘Electability.’” FiveThirtyEight, Aug. 21. (https://fivethirtyeight.com/features/the-problem-with-electability/).Google Scholar
Bai, Matt. 2004. “Electability.” New York Times Magazine, December 12. (https://www.nytimes.com/2004/12/12/magazine/electability.html).Google Scholar
Barbara Lee Family Foundation. 2019. “Ready, Willing, and Electable: Women Running for Executive Office.” Memo. (https://www.barbaraleefoundation.org/research/ready-willing-electable/).Google Scholar
Bateson, Regina. 2020. "Replication Data for: Strategic Discrimination." https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/6FFKRI, Harvard Dataverse.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Becker, Gary. 1971[1957]. The Economics of Discrimination, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226041049.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bejarano, Christina E. 2013. The Latina Advantage: Gender, Race, and Political Success. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.Google Scholar
Bertrand, Marianne, and Mullainathan, Sendhil. 2004. “Are Emily and Greg More Employable than Lakisha and Jamal? A Field Experiment on Labor Market Discrimination.” American Economic Review 94(4): 9911013.Google Scholar
Berinksy, Adam. 2017. “Rumors and Health Care Reform: Experiments in Political Misinformation.” British Journal of Political Science 47(2): 241-62.Google Scholar
Blank, Rebecca M., Dabady, Marilyn, and Citro, Constance F., eds. 2004. Measuring Racial Discrimination: Panel on Methods for Assessing Discrimination, Committee on National Statistics, Division of Behavioral and Social Sciences and Education. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
Brown, Nadia, and Gershon, Sarah Allen. 2017. “Examining Intersectionality and Symbolic Representation.” Politics, Groups, and Identities 5(3): 500505.10.1080/21565503.2017.1321995CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brownstein, Ronald. 2019a. “2020 Democrats Face the Most Diverse Electorate in History.” CNN Politics, February 12. (https://www.cnn.com/interactive/2019/02/politics/dem-primaries-exit-polls/).Google Scholar
Brownstein, Ronald 2019b. “The Democratic Debate Over Winning Back Trump’s Base.” Atlantic Monthly, May 2. (https://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2019/05/joe-bidens-bid-white-working-class-vote/588613/).Google Scholar
Burden, Barry C., Ono, Yosikuni, and Yamada, Masahiro. 2017. “Reassessing Public Support for a Female President.” Journal of Politics 79(3): 1073-78.10.1086/691799CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butler, Daniel M., and Preece, Jessica Robinson. 2016. “Recruitment and Perceptions of Gender Bias in Party Leader Support.” Political Research Quarterly 69(4): 842–51.10.1177/1065912916668412CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carroll, Susan J., and Sanbonmatsu, Kira. 2013. More Women Can Run: Gender and Pathways to the State Legislatures. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199322428.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chira, Susan. 2019. “Stacey Abrams, After Narrow Loss, Has Some Decisions to Make.” New York Times, March 5. (https://www.nytimes.com/2019/03/05/us/politics/stacey-abrams-georgia-democrats.html).Google Scholar
Coppock, Alexander, and McClellan, Oliver A.. 2019. “Validating the Demographic, Political, Psychological, and Experimental Results Obtained from a New Source of Online Survey Respondents.” Research and Politics 6(1): 114.10.1177/2053168018822174CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotton, Anthony. 2020. “Female Candidates Say They’ll Stand Their Ground in Democratic Senate Primary.” Colorado Public Radio, January 26. (https://www.cpr.org/2020/01/26/female-candidates-say-theyll-stand-their-ground-in-democratic-senate-primary/).Google Scholar
Crowder-Meyer, Melody. 2013. “Gendered Recruitment without Trying: How Local Party Recruiters Affect Women’s Representation.” Politics and Gender 9(4): 390413.10.1017/S1743923X13000391CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowley, Candy, and Johnson, Sasha. 2007. “Is Black America Ready to Embrace Obama?” CNN, March 1. (http://www.cnn.com/2007/POLITICS/02/28/obama.black.vote/index.html).Google Scholar
Culham, Devin. 2018. “Abdul El-Sayed Says ‘Powerful’ Democrats Think He Won’t Win Because He’s Muslim.” Detroit Metro Times, July 30. (https://www.metrotimes.com/news-hits/archives/2018/07/30/abdul-el-sayed-says-powerful-democrats-say-he-wont-win-because-hes-muslim).Google Scholar
Deaton, Angus, and Cartwright, Nancy. 2018. “Understanding and Misunderstanding Randomized Controlled Trials.” Social Science and Medicine 210:221.10.1016/j.socscimed.2017.12.005CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ditonto, Tessa. 2019. “Direct and Indirect Effects of Prejudice: Sexism, Information, and Voting Behavior in Political Campaigns.” Politics, Groups, and Identities 7(3): 590609.10.1080/21565503.2019.1632065CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Do, James J., Samuels, Steven M., Adkins, Donald J., Clinard, Matthew E., and Koveleskie, Aaron J.. 2013. “Gender Bias and Pluralistic Ignorance in Perceptions of Fitness Assessments.” Military Psychology 24(1): 2335.10.1037/h0094754CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doherty, David, Dowling, Conor M., and Miller, Michael G.. 2019. “Do Local Party Chairs Think Women and Minority Candidates Can Win? Evidence from a Conjoint Experiment.” Journal of Politics 81(4): 1282–97.Google Scholar
Dolan, Kathleen. 2014. When Does Gender Matter? Women Candidates and Gender Stereotypes in American Elections. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199968275.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowling, Conor, and Miller, Michael. 2015. “Can Information Alter Perceptions about Women’s Chances of Winning Office? Evidence from a Panel Study.” Politics and Gender 11(1): 5588.10.1017/S1743923X14000555CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fields, James M., and Schuman, Howard. 1976. “Public Beliefs about the Beliefs of the Public.” Public Opinion Quarterly 40(4): 427–48.10.1086/268330CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marched, First We, Ran, Then We. 2019. “Panel 4: The Personal Side of Being a Candidate.” Jennifer Chudy, moderator. Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA, January 12. (https://firstwemarched.com/video).Google Scholar
Fox, Richard L. and Lawless, Jennifer L.. 2008. “If Only They’d Ask: Gender, Recruitment, and Political Ambition.” Journal of Politics 72(2): 310-26.10.1017/S0022381609990752CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fox, Richard L. and Lawless, Jennifer L. 2011. “Gendered Perceptions and Political Candidacies: A Central Barrier to Women’s Equality in Electoral Politics.” American Journal of Political Science 55(1): 5973.10.1111/j.1540-5907.2010.00484.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fox News. 2018. “CA Dem Candidate: Party Officials Told Me I’m ‘Too Brown’ to Win.” June 5. (https://insider.foxnews.com/2018/06/05/california-democrat-says-party-told-him-too-brown-win-congress-seat-against-rohrabacher).Google Scholar
Frederick, Angela. 2013. “Bringing Narrative In: Race-Gender Storytelling, Political Ambition, and Women’s Paths to Public Office.” Journal of Women, Politics, and Policy 34(2): 113-37.10.1080/1554477X.2013.776379CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallup. 2019. “In Depth: The Presidency.” (https://news.gallup.com/poll/4729/presidency.aspx).Google Scholar
Gambino, Lauren. 2018. “‘Just Win, Baby’: Nancy Pelosi Tells Democrats It’s OK to Run Against Her.” The Guardian, May 8.Google Scholar
Germond, Jack W. 1996. “Who Will Face Helms May Hinge on Race.” Baltimore Sun, May 6.Google Scholar
Goldberg, Philip. 1968. “Are Women Prejudiced Against Women?Transaction 5(5): 2830.Google Scholar
Gontcharova, Natalie. 2018. “Black Women Are Running for Office—But Are They Getting the Support They Need?” Refinery29, June 4. (https://www.refinery29.com/en-us/2018/06/200865/black-women-running-alabama).Google Scholar
Glick, Peter. 2019. “Gender, Sexism, and the Election: Did Sexism Help Trump More than It Hurt Clinton?Politics, Groups, and Identities 7(3): 713-23.10.1080/21565503.2019.1633931CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, Ruth. 2018. “Struggling to Bring the ‘Blue Wave’ to Deep-Red Alabama.” New York Times Magazine, October 17. (https://www.nytimes.com/2018/10/17/magazine/struggling-to-bring-the-blue-wave-to-deep-red-alabama.html).Google Scholar
Hamby, Peter. 2019. “‘This is Do-or-Die’: Joe Biden’s ‘Electability’ Argument Is How Democrats Lose Elections.” Vanity Fair, May 7. (https://www.vanityfair.com/news/2019/05/joe-biden-electability-argument-is-how-democrats-lose-elections?verso=true).Google Scholar
Hancock, Ange-Marie. 2007. “When Multiplication Doesn’t Equal Quick Addition: Examining Intersectionality as a Research Paradigm.” Perspectives on Politics 5(1): 6379.10.1017/S1537592707070065CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartig, Hannah, and Doherty, Carroll. 2018. “More in US See Drug Addiction, College Affordability, and Sexism as ‘Very Big’ National Problems.” Pew Research Center. October 22. (https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2018/10/22/more-in-u-s-see-drug-addiction-college-affordability-and-sexism-as-very-big-national-problems/).Google Scholar
Hawkesworth, Mary. 2003. “Congressional Enactments of Race-Gender: Toward a Theory of Raced-Gendered Institutions.” American Political Science Review 97(4): 529-50.10.1017/S0003055403000868CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayes, Danny, and Lawless, Jennifer L.. 2016. Women on the Run: Gender, Media, and Political Campaigns in a Polarized Era. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781316336007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heerwig, Jennifer A., and McCabe, Brian J.. 2009. “Education and Social Desirability Bias: The Case of a Black Presidential Candidate.” Social Science Quarterly 90(3): 674–86.10.1111/j.1540-6237.2009.00637.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helman, Scott. 2007. “Politics of Doubt Gnaw at Black Voters in S.C.” Boston Globe, November 9.Google Scholar
Highton, Benjamin. 2004. “White Voters and African American Candidates for Congress.” Political Behavior 26(1): 125.10.1023/B:POBE.0000022341.98720.9eCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hohman, James. 2018. “The Daily 202: Joe Biden Appeals to Working-Class Whites Who Defected to Trump. Is that How Democrats Win Again?” Washington Post, October 15. (https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/powerpost/paloma/daily-202/2018/10/15/daily-202-joe-biden-appeals-to-working-class-whites-who-defected-to-trump-is-that-how-democrats-win-again/5bc396dc1b326b7c8a8d19a1/?utm_term=.ae53906af73e).Google Scholar
Holman, Mirya, and Schneider, Monica C.. 2018. “Gender, Race, and Political Ambition: How Intersectionality and Frames Influence Interest in Public Office.” Politics, Groups, and Identities 6(2): 264–80.10.1080/21565503.2016.1208105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holzer, Harry, and Ihlanfeldt, Keith R.. 1998. “Customer Discrimination and Employment Outcomes for Minority Workers.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 113(3): 835-67.10.1162/003355398555766CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huddy, Leonie, and Terkildsen, Nayda. 1993. “The Consequences of Gender Stereotypes for Women Candidates at Different Levels and Types of Office.” Political Research Quarterly 46(3): 503-25.10.1177/106591299304600304CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Juenke, Eric Gonzalez, and Shah, Paru. 2016. “Demand and Supply: Racial and Ethnic Minority Candidates in White Districts.” Journal of Race, Ethnicity, and Politics 1(1): 6090.10.1017/rep.2015.2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, Daniel, and Allport, Floyd Henry. 1931. Student Attitudes: A Report of the Syracuse University Research Study. Syracuse, NY: Craftsman Press.Google Scholar
King, Ledyard, Elbeshbishi, Sarah, and della Cava, Marco. 2019. “Elizabeth Warren’s Latest Hurdle to the Presidency: Democrats’ Belief Women Face Tougher Fight against Trump.” USA Today, September 10. (https://www.usatoday.com/story/news/politics/elections/2019/09/10/elizabeth-warren-democrats-worry-electability-against-trump/2055209001/).Google Scholar
Kirkland, Patricia A., and Coppock, Alexander. 2018. “Candidate Choice without Party Labels: New Insights from Conjoint Survey Experiments.” Political Behavior 40: 571-91.10.1007/s11109-017-9414-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitchener, Caroline. 2019. “This Millennial Congresswoman Is Bringing Vulnerability to Capitol Hill.” The Lily, March 25. (https://www.thelily.com/this-millennial-congresswoman-is-bringing-vulnerability-to-capitol-hill/).Google Scholar
Krook, Mona Lena, and Mackay, Fiona, eds. 2011. Gender, Politics, and Institutions: Towards a Feminist Institutionalism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Krook, Mona Lena, and Sanín, Juliana Restrepo. 2019. “The Cost of Doing Politics? Analyzing Violence and Harassment against Female Politicians.” Perspectives on Politics. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592719001397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lambert, Tracy A., Kahn, Arnold S., and Apple, Kevin J.. 2003. “Pluralistic Ignorance and Hooking Up.” Journal of Sex Research 40(2): 129-33.10.1080/00224490309552174CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lawless, Jennifer L. and Fox, Richard L.. 2010. It Still Takes a Candidate: Why Women Don’t Run for Office. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511778797CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawless, Jennifer L., and Pearson, Kathryn. 2008. “The Primary Reason for Women’s Underrepresentation? Reevaluating the Conventional Wisdom.” Journal of Politics 70(1): 6782.10.1017/S002238160708005XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lieberman, Evan S. 2016. “Can the Biomedical Research Cycle Be a Model for Political Science?Perspectives on Politics 14(4): 1054-66.10.1017/S153759271600298XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackay, Fiona, Kenny, Meryl, and Chappell, Louise. 2011. “New Institutionalism through a Gender Lens: Towards a Feminist Institutionalism?International Political Science Review 31(5): 573-88.Google Scholar
Mas, Alexandre, and Moretti, Enrico. 2009. “Racial Bias in the 2008 Presidential Election.” American Economic Review: Papers & Proceedings 99(2): 323-29.10.1257/aer.99.2.323CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCarthy, Justin. 2019. “Less than Half in US Would Vote for a Socialist for President.” Gallup News, May 9. (https://news.gallup.com/poll/254120/less-half-vote-socialist-president.aspx).Google Scholar
Mildenberger, Matto, and Tingley, Dustin. 2019. “Beliefs about Climate Beliefs: The Problem of Second-Order Opinions in Climate Policymaking.” British Journal of Political Science 49(4): 1279-307.Google Scholar
Miller, Dale T., and Prentice, Deborah A.. 1994. “Collective Errors and Errors about the Collective.” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 20(5): 541-50.10.1177/0146167294205011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miyajima, Takeru, and Yamaguchi, Hiroyuki. 2017. “I Want to but I Won’t: Pluralistic Ignorance Inhibits Intentions to Take Paternity Leave in Japan.” Frontiers in Psychology 8(1508): 112.10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01508CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mummolo, Jonathan, and Peterson, Erik. 2019. “Demand Effects in Survey Experiments: An Empirical Assessment.” American Political Science Review 113(2): 517-29.10.1017/S0003055418000837CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mutz, Diana Carole. 2011. Population-Based Survey Experiments. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Naughton, James. 1971. “Muskie Rules Out a Black Running Mate.” New York Times, September 9.Google Scholar
Neal, Samantha. 2017. “Views of Racism as a Major Problem Increase Sharply, Especially Among Democrats.” Pew Research Center. August 29. (https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2017/08/29/views-of-racism-as-a-major-problem-increase-sharply-especially-among-democrats/).Google Scholar
Niven, David. 1998. “Party Elites and Women Candidates: The Shape of Bias.” Women and Politics 19(2): 5780.10.1300/J014v19n02_03CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nunley, John M., Pugh, Adam, Romero, Nicholas, and Seals, R. Alan. 2015. “Racial Discrimination in the Labor Market for Recent College Graduates: Evidence from a Field Experiment.” B.E. Journal of Economic Analysis and Policy 15(3): 1093-125.10.1515/bejeap-2014-0082CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nyhan, Brendan, and Reifler, Jason. 2010. “When Corrections Fail: The Persistence of Political Misperceptions.” Political Behavior 32: 303–30.10.1007/s11109-010-9112-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Gorman, Hubert. 1975. “Pluralistic Ignorance and White Estimates of White Support for Racial Segregation.” Public Opinion Quarterly 39(3): 313-30.10.1086/268231CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Gorman, Hubert. 1986. “The Discovery of Pluralistic Ignorance: An Ironic Lesson.” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 22(4): 333-47.10.1002/1520-6696(198610)22:4<333::AID-JHBS2300220405>3.0.CO;2-X3.0.CO;2-X>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Gorman, Hubert, and Garry, Stephen L.. 1976. “Pluralistic Ignorance – A Replication and Extension.” Public Opinion Quarterly 40(4): 449-58.10.1086/268331CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parker, Kim, Graf, Nikki, and Igielnik, Ruth. 2019. “Generation Z Looks a Lot Like Millennials on Key Social and Political Issues.” Pew Research Center. January 17. (https://www.pewsocialtrends.org/2019/01/17/generation-z-looks-a-lot-like-millennials-on-key-social-and-political-issues/).Google Scholar
Pearson, Kathryn, and McGhee, Eric. 2013. “What It Takes to Win: Questioning ‘Gender Neutral’ Outcomes in US House Races.” Politics and Gender 9(4): 439-62.10.1017/S1743923X13000433CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philpot, Tasha, and Walton, Jr Hanes. 2007. “One of Our Own: Black Women Candidates and the Voters Who Support Them.” American Journal of Political Science 51(1): 4962.10.1111/j.1540-5907.2007.00236.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prentice, Deborah A., and Miller, Dale T.. 1993. “Pluralistic Ignorance and Alcohol Use on Campus: Some Consequences of Misperceiving the Social Norm.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 64(2): 243-56.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Quinnipiac University Poll. 2019. “Biden Is on Top of Democratic Pack, Quinnipiac University National Poll Finds.” March 28. (https://poll.qu.edu/national/release-detail?ReleaseID=2611).Google Scholar
Reflective Democracy Campaign. 2019. “The Electability Myth: The Shifting Demographics of Political Power in America.” (https://wholeads.us/wp-content/uploads/2019/08/The-Electability-Myth-_-The-Shifting-Demographics-of-Political-Power-In-America-8-1-19.pdf).Google Scholar
Rheault, Ludovic, Rayment, Erica, and Musulan, Andreea. 2019. “Politicians in the Line of Fire: Incivility and the Treatment of Women on Social Media.” Research and Politics 6(1): 17.10.1177/2053168018816228CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riccardi, Nicholas. 2019. “After 2016 Loss, Democrats Know They Need White Male Voters.” Associated Press, April 7. (https://www.apnews.com/79fefc13c5a54b089da12c7007e98ac8).Google Scholar
Sack, Kevin. 1996. “Race an Issue for Democrats in Primary Opposite Helms.” New York Times, April 21.Google Scholar
Schwarz, Susanne, Hunt, William, and Coppock, Alexander. 2018. “What Have We Learned about Gender from Candidate Choice Experiments? A Meta-Analysis of 30 Factorial Survey Experiments.” Presented at the Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association, Chicago, IL, April 5–8. (https://alexandercoppock.com/projectpages_SHC_gender.html).Google Scholar
Shah, Paru. 2014. “It Takes a Black Candidate: A Supply-Side Theory of Minority Representation.” Political Research Quarterly 67(2): 266-79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, Paru, Scott, Jamil, and Juenke, Eric Gonzalez. 2019. “Women of Color Candidates: Examining Emergence and Success in State Legislative Elections.” Politics, Groups, and Identities 7(2): 429-43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sigelman, Lee, and Welch, Susan. 1984. “Race, Gender, and Opinion Toward Black and Female Presidential Candidates.” Public Opinion Quarterly 48(2): 467-75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silva, Andrea, and Skulley, Carrie. 2019. “Always Running: Candidate Emergence among Women of Color.” Political Research Quarterly 72(2): 342-59.10.1177/1065912918789289CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simas, Elizabeth. 2017. “The Effects of Electability on U.S. Primary Voters.” Journal of Elections, Public Opinion, and Parties 27(3): 274-90.10.1080/17457289.2016.1270287CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simien, Evelyn M. 2007. “Doing Intersectionality Research: From Conceptual Issues to Practical Examples.” Politics and Gender 3(2): 264–71.Google Scholar
Smith, Eric R.A.N., and Fox, Richard L.. 2001. “The Electoral Fortunes of Women Candidates for Congress.” Political Research Quarterly 54(1): 205–21.10.1177/106591290105400111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Tom W., Hout, Michael, and Marsden, Peter V.. 2017. General Social Survey, 1972–2016 [Cumulative File]. Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-university Consortium for Political and Social Research [distributor], National Opinion Research Center [distributor]. https://doi.org/10.3886/ICPSR36797.v1Google Scholar
Sobotka, Tagart Cain. 2020. “Not Your Average Joe: Pluralistic Ignorance, Status, and Modern Sexism.” Men and Masculinities. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1097184X20901578CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Streb, Matthew, Burrell, Barbara, Frederick, Brian, and Genovese, Michael A.. 2008. “Social Desirability Effects and Support for a Female American President.” Public Opinion Quarterly 72(1): 7689.10.1093/poq/nfm035CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teele, Dawn Langan, Kalla, Joshua, and Rosenbluth, Frances. 2018. “The Ties That Double Bind: Social Roles and Women’s Underrepresentation in Politics.” American Political Science Review 112(3): 525-41.10.1017/S0003055418000217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Terkildsen, Nayda. 1993. “When White Voters Evaluate Black Candidates: The Processing Implications of Skin Color, Prejudice, and Self-Monitoring.” American Journal of Political Science 37(4): 1032-53.10.2307/2111542CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorov, Alexander, and Mandisodza, Anesu N.. 2004. “Public Opinion on Foreign Policy: The Multilateral Public that Perceives Itself as Unilateral.” Public Opinion Quarterly 68(3): 323-48.10.1093/poq/nfh036CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisz, Erika. 2020. “This Psychological Concept Could be Shaping the Presidential Election.” Nautilus, February 10. (http://nautil.us/blog/this-psychological-concept-could-be-shaping-the-presidential-election).Google Scholar
Williams, Linda E. 1990. “White/Black Perceptions of the Electability of Black Political Candidates.” National Political Science Review 2: 4564.Google Scholar
Zeleny, Jeff. 2008. “Saying Race Is No Barrier, Obama Still Courts Blacks.” New York Times, January 2. (https://www.nytimes.com/2008/01/02/us/politics/02race.html).Google Scholar
Zengerle, Jason. 2008. “The Message Keeper.” The New Republic, November 5. (https://newrepublic.com/article/62089/the-message-keeper).Google Scholar
Zhou, Li. 2019. “Democrats Are Prioritizing ‘Electability’ in 2020. That’s a Coded Term.” Vox, April 16. (https://www.vox.com/2019/4/16/18308141/democrats-electability-2020-presidential-nomination).Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 Perceptions versus reality

Note: Gray bars show yearly population estimates, based on weighted data from the General Social Survey (GSS). Black lines are 95% confidence intervals calculated with design-corrected standard errors. Subjects were asked, “If your party nominated a woman for president, would you vote for her if she were qualified for the job?” and “If your party nominated a [Negro/Black/African-American] for president, would you vote for him if he were qualified for the job?” I code subjects as unwilling to vote for a female or Black candidate if they said anything other than “yes.” (Other responses include “no,” “don’t know,” “wouldn’t vote,” or refused to answer.) Note that the question about a Black presidential candidate assumes the candidate is a man. The GSS has never measured public opinion on a Black woman president.
Figure 1

Table 1 Candidate profiles for Study 1

Figure 2

Table 2 Variation in perceived electability by candidate race and gender

Figure 3

Table 3 Democratic presidential candidates in Study 2

Figure 4

Table 4 Average treatment effects, male voters treatment

Figure 5

Figure 2 Average treatment effects by candidate, male voters treatment

Figure 6

Figure 3 Average treatment effects by candidate, white voters treatment

Figure 7

Table 5 Average treatment effects, white voters treatment

Figure 8

Table 6 Average treatment effects, estimate others’ biases treatment

Figure 9

Table 7 Average treatment effects, correct information treatment

Figure 10

Table 8 Average treatment effects, naming and shaming treatment

Figure 11

Table 9 Average treatment effects, role model treatment

Figure 12

Table 10 Average treatment effects, Black voters treatment

Supplementary material: Link

Bateson Dataset

Link
Supplementary material: PDF

Bateson supplementary material

Bateson supplementary material

Download Bateson supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 1 MB