Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-767nl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-11T15:29:36.554Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Economist's Glance at Goldman's Economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Esther-Mirjam Sent*
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame
*
Department of Economics, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN 46556, e-mail: sent.2@nd.edu.

Abstract

Goldman joins the ranks of epistemologists, philosophers, and science studies scholars trying to use economic models of science. For Goldman, these models are part of social rather than individual epistemics. His hope is that these models will illustrate that non-epistemic goals of individual scientists such as professional success do not necessarily undermine epistemic aims of science such as the acquisition of truth. This paper shows that there are inconsistencies between Goldman's individual and social epistemics, that these models do not live up to Goldman's standards of evaluation, and that the economic models that Goldman uses are not social.

Type
Symposium: The Use of Economic Concepts in Contemporary Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

The author gratefully acknowledges support from a grant by the University of Notre Dame Faculty Research Program.

References

Cox, J. C. and Goldman, A. I. (1994), “Accuracy in Journalism: An Economic Approach”, in Schmitt, F.F. (ed.), Socializing Epistemology: The Social Dimensions of Knowledge. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 189215.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1970), A Theory of Human Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1986), Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1989), “Replies to Commentators”, Philosophia 19: 301324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1991), “Social Epistemics and Social Psychology”, Social Epistemology 5: 121125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1992), Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1993), Philosophical Applications of Cognitive Science. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. and Shaked, M. (1991), “Results on Inquiry and Truth Possession”, Statistics and Probability Letters 12: 415420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. and Shaked, M. (1992), “An Economic Model of Scientific Activity and Truth Acquisition”, in A. I. Goldman 1992, pp. 227254.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. and Shaked, M. (1993), “Open Peer Commentary on the Scientific Status of Econometrics: Comment”, Social Epistemology 7: 249253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, D. W. (1997), “Caveat Emptor: Economics and Contemporary Philosophy of Science”, Philosophy of Science 64 (Proceedings): this issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1986), Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Juhl, C. and Kelly, K. T. (1994), “Realism, Convergence, and Additivity”, in Hull, D., Forbes, M., and Burian, R. M. (eds.), PSA, 1994 Vol. 1. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 181189.Google Scholar
Kelly, K. T. (1996), The Logic of Reliable Inquiry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, K. T. and Schulte, O. (1995), “The Computable Testability of Theories Making Uncomputable Predictions”, Erkenntnis 43: 2966.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirman, A. (1992), “Whom or What Does the Representative Individual Represent?Journal of Economic Perspectives 6: 117136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, A. A. (1985), “On Effectively Computable Realizations of Choice Functions”, Mathematical Social Sciences 10: 4380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, A. A. (1992a), “On Turing Degrees of Walrasian Models and a General Impossibility Result in the Theory of Decision-Making”, Mathematical Social Sciences 24: 141171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, A. A. (1992b), “Some Aspects of Effectively Constructive Mathematics That Are Relevant to the Foundations of Neoclassical Mathematical Economics and the Theory of Games”, Mathematical Social Sciences 24: 209235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mirowski, P. E. (1996), “The Economic Consequences of Philip Kitcher”, Social Epistemology 10: 153169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osherson, D. N, Stob, M., and Weinstein, S. (1986), Systems that Learn: An Introduction to Learning Theory for Cognitive and Computer Scientists. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Osherson, D. N, Stob, M., and Weinstein, S. (1988), “Mechanical Learners Pay a Price for Bayesianism”, Journal of Symbolic Logic 53: 12451251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar