Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-g5fl4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-03T01:59:34.359Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Normality as a Biological Concept

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Robert Wachbroit*
Affiliation:
Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy, University of Maryland
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy, Van Munching Hall, University of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742, USA.

Abstract

The biological sciences employ a concept of normality that must be distinguished from statistical or value concepts. The concept of normality is presupposed in the standard explications of biological functions, and it is crucial to the strategy of explanation by approximations in, for example, physiology. Nevertheless, this concept of normality does not seem to be captured in the language of physics. Thus attempts at explaining the methodological relationship between the biological sciences and the physical sciences by concentrating only on the concept of biological function cannot go very far. An analysis of the concept of normality is also necessary.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Work on this article was supported in part by a grant R01 HG00419 from the National Institutes of Health Center for Human Genome Research. I would also like to acknowledge the helpful comments I received on an earlier draft from Elliott Sober, David Wasserman, and especially Ken Schaffner, as well as from an anonymous referee.

References

Beckner, M. (1968), The Biological Way of Thought. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Bigelow, J. and Pargetter, R. (1987), “Functions”, The Journal of Philosophy 84: 181196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C. (1976), “Wright on Functions”, Philosophical Review 85: 7086.10.2307/2184255CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C. (1977), “Health as a Theoretical Concept”, Philosophy of Science 44: 542573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, P. (1975), “Functional Analysis”, The Journal of Philosophy 72: 741765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1965), “The Logic of Functional Analysis”, in Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: The Free Press, pp. 297330.Google Scholar
Joseph, G. (1980), “The Many Sciences and the One World”, The Journal of Philosophy 77: 773791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, C. D. (1945), “The Meaning of Normal”, The Yale Journal of Biology and Medicine 17: 493501.Google ScholarPubMed
Nagel, E. (1977), “Teleology Revisited”, The Journal of Philosophy 74: 261301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K. (1991), “Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defense”, Philosophy of Science 58: 168184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1985), The Structure of Biological Science. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1989), “Four Decades of Scientific Explanation”, in Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. C., (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 13, Scientific Explanation. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3219.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1980), “Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism”, Philosophy of Science 47: 350383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wachbroit, R. (1994), “Distinguishing Genetic Disease and Genetic Susceptibility”, American Journal of Medical Genetics. In press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, L. (1976), Teleological Explanations: An Etiological Analysis of Goals and Functions. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520333697CrossRefGoogle Scholar