Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-ckgrl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-16T21:35:38.005Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Realist Principles

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Geoffrey Hellman*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy Indiana University—Bloomington

Abstract

We list, with discussions, various principles of scientific realism, in order to exhibit their diversity and to emphasize certain serious problems of formulation. Ontological and epistemological principles are distinguished. Within the former category, some framed in semantic terms (truth, reference) serve their purpose vis-à-vis instrumentalism (Part 1). They fail, however, to distinguish the realist from a wide variety of (constructional) empiricists. Part 2 seeks purely ontological formulations, so devised that the empiricist cannot reconstruct them from within. The main task here is to characterize “independence of mind”. A pair of notions, “physical invariance” and “anti-determination”, seem to work. They enable us to assess anew “the problem of constructing the physical out of the phenomenal” (yielding certain clarifications demanded by Goodman). Modern cosmology, especially, is seen to present insuperable obstacles to such empiricist approaches to science. The final section on epistemological principles reveals a morass better avoided in favor of an elementary claim about perception, together with a rejection of any absolute observation/theory dichotomy. Finally, a positive, realist notion of “observable-in-principle” is sketched, and it is suggested that, from the perspective of relativistic cosmology, even this defines no boundary to potential knowledge.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1983 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I wish to thank Richard Healey for helpful correspondence on some of the issues discussed in this paper.

References

Asquith, P. D. and Giere, R. N. (eds.) (1981), PSA 1980 vol. II. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. (1968), “Substance, Reality, and Primary Qualities”, in Martin, C. B., and Armstrong, D. M. (eds.), pp. 86124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. (1981), “Scientific Realism and Naturalistic Epistemology”, in Asquith, P. D. and Giere, R. N. (eds.).Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1928), Der Logische Aufbau der Welt. Berlin: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
Clauser, J. F. and Shimony, A. (1978), “Bell's Theorem: Experimental Tests and Implications”, Reports on Progress in Physics 41: 18811927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, M., “Putnam on Realism”, unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1978), Truth and Other Enigmas. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J., Glymour, C. and Stachel, E. (eds.) (1977), Foundations of Space-Time Theories, Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science VIII. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1972), “Tarski's Theory of Truth”, The Journal of Philosophy 69: 347375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1980), Science without Numbers. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fisk, M. (1980), “Materialism and Dialectic”, Critique 12: 97116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1977), “Indistinguishable Space-Times”, in Earman et al.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1977), The Structure of Appearance, 3rd edition. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawking, S. W. and Ellis, G. F. R. (1973), The Large-Scale Structure of Space-Time. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hellman, G. and Thompson, F. W. (1975), “Physicalism: Ontology, Determination, and Reduction”, The Journal of Philosophy 72: 551564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hellman, G. (1978), “Accuracy and Actuality”, Erkenntnis 12: 209228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malament, D. (1977), “Observationally Indistinguishable Space-Time Theories”, in Earman et al.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. and Armstrong, D. M. (eds.) (1968), Locke and Berkely. New York: Anchor Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, G. (1962), “The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities” in Field, H. and Maxwell, G. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science III. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Misner, C. W., Thorne, K. S., and Wheeler, J. A. (1973), Gravitation. San Francisco: Freeman Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1976), “What is Realism?”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, pp. 174194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1969), “Epistemology Naturalized”, in Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. (1954), The Analysis of Matter. New York: Dover Press.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1963), Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1977), The First Three Minutes: A Modern View of the Origins of the Universe. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Wolff, T. (ed.) (1967), “A Reconstruction of the Argument of the Subjective Deduction”, in Kant: A Collection of Critical Essays. New York: Anchor Press, pp. 88133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar